The Colonizer's Model
of the World
Geographical Diffusionism and Eurocentric History
J. ML Blaut
THE GUILFORD PRESS
New York / London
© 1993 J. M. Blaut
Published by The Guilford Press
A Division of Guilford Publications, Inc.
72 Spring Street, New York, N. Y. 10012
All rights reserved
No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical,
photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise, without written
permission from the Publisher.
Printed in the United States of America
This book is printed on acid-free paper.
Last digit is print number: 9 8
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Blaut, James M. (James Morris)
The colonizer's model of the world : geographical diffusionism and
eurocentric history / by J. M. Blaut.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-89862-349-9 (hard) — ISBN 0-89862-348-0 (pbk.)
1. History — Philosophy I. Title.
D16.9B49 1992
901— dc20 93-22346
CIP
To Meca, Gini, and Mother
Acknowledgments
Many people contributed in many important
ways to the writing of this book. Peter
Taylor and Wilbur Zelinsky gave me great
encouragement and wise counsel (not
always heeded) during the years that I have been struggling with the issues
and ideas discussed here. Among many others who contributed
immensely to the book, and are happily given credit for many of the ideas
it contains (the good ideas, not the errors), I wish particularly to mention
Abdul Alkalimat, Samir Amin, William Denevan, Loida Figueroa, Andre
Gunder Frank, William Loren Katz, Jose Lopez, Kent Mathewson,
Antonio Rfos-Bustamante, America Sorrentini de Blaut, and Ben
Wisner. Over the years many other people have set me to thinking about
the problems discussed in the book and have shown me the answers to
some of these problems. Among these friends, teachers, and students, I
would like to mention Chao-li Chi, Ghazi Falah, Fred Hardy, Fred
Kniffen, Juan Mari Bras, Francis Mark, Sidney Mintz, Ng Hong, Doris
Pizarro, Randolph Rawlins, Anselme Remy, Waldo Rodriguez, Digna
Sanchez, Howard Stanton, David Stea, and Lakshman Yapa. Peter
Wissoker and Anna Brackett edited the book with patience and skill. A
number of paragraphs in Chapters 3 and 4 and one in Chapter 2 are taken
from an article in Political Geography (Blaut 1992b), and are reproduced
here with the kind permission of the publisher of that journal,
Butterworth-Heinemann.
vi
Contents
CHAPTER l. History Inside Out
The Argument, 1
The Tunnel of Time, 3
Eurocentric Diffusionism, 8
Eurocentrism, 8
Diffusionism, 11
The Colonizer's Model, 17
Origins, 18
Classical Diffusionism, 21
Modem Diffusionism, 26
World Models and Worldly Interests, 30
The Ethnography of Beliefs, 30
Diffusionism as a Belief System, 41
Notes, 43
chapter 2. The Myth of the European Miracle
Mythmakers and Critics, 52
Modernization as History, 53
The Critique, 54
The Countercritique, 58
The Myth, 59
Biology, 61
Race, 61; Demography, 66
Environment, 69
Nasty 'Tropical Africa, 69; Arid, Despotic Asia, 80;
Temperate Europe, 90
Rationality, 94
The Rationality Doctrine, 95; Rationality and the
European Miracle, 102
vii
CONTENTS
Technology, 108
Society, 119
State, 119; Church, 123; Class, 124; Family, 124
Notes, 135
chapter 3. Before 1492
Medieval Landscapes, 153
Protocapitalism in Africa, Asia, and Europe, 165
Notes, 173
152
chapter 4. After 1492
179
Explaining 1492, 179
Why America Was Conquered by Europeans and Not
by Africans or Asians, 180
Why the Conquest Was Successful, 183
Europe in 1492, 186
Colonialism and the Rise of Europe, 1492-1688, 187
Colonialism and Capitalism in the Sixteenth Century, 187
Precious Metals, 189; Plantations, 191; Effects, 193
Colonialism and Capitalism in the Seventeenth Century, 198
The Centration of Capitalism, 201
Notes, 206
chapter 5. Conclusion 214
Notes, 215
Bibliography
217
Index
237
CHAPTER 1
History Inside Out
THE ARGUMENT
The purpose of this book is to undermine one of
the most powerful beliefs of our time concern-
ing world history and world geography. This
belief is the notion that European civiliza-
tion — "The West" — has had some unique historical advantage, some
special quality of race or culture or environment or mind or spirit, which
gives this human community a permanent superiority over all other
communities, at all times in history and down to the present.
The belief is both historical and geographical. Europeans are seen as
the "makers of history." Europe eternally advances, progresses, modern-
izes. The rest of the world advances more sluggishly, or stagnates: it is
"traditional society." Therefore, the world has a permanent geographical
center and a permanent periphery: an Inside and an Outside. Inside leads,
Outside lags. Inside innovates, Outside imitates.
This belief is diffusionism, or more precisely Eurocentric diffusionism. It
is a theory about the way cultural processes tend to move over the surface
of the world as a whole. They tend to flow out of the European sector and
toward the non-European sector. This is the natural, normal, logical, and
ethical flow of culture, of innovation, of human causality. Europe, eter-
nally, is Inside. Non-Europe is Outside. Europe is the source of most
diffusions; non-Europe is the recipient. 1
Diffusionism lies at the very root of historical and geographical
scholarship. Some parts of the belief have been questioned in recent years,
but its most fundamental tenets remain unchallenged, and so the belief as
a whole has not been uprooted or very much weakened by modern
scholarship.
The most important tenet of diffusionism is the theory of "the
1
2 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
autonomous rise of Europe," sometimes (rather more grandly) called the
idea of "the European Miracle." It is the idea that Europe was more
advanced and more progressive than all other regions prior to 1492, prior,
that is, to the beginning of the period of colonialism, the period in which
Europe and non-Europe came into intense interaction. If one believes this
to be the case — and most modern scholars seem to believe it to be the
case — then it must follow that the economic and social modernization of
Europe is fundamentally a result of Europe's internal qualities, not of
interaction with the societies of Africa, Asia, and America after 1492.
Therefore: the main building blocks of modernity must be European.
Therefore: colonialism cannot have been really important for Europe's
modernization. Therefore: colonialism must mean, for the Africans,
Asians, and Americans, not spoliation and cultural destruction but, rather,
the receipt-by-diffusion of European civilization: modernization.
This book will analyze and criticize Eurocentric diffusionism as a
general body of ideas, and will try to undermine the more concrete theory
of the autonomous rise of Europe. The first chapter of the book discusses
the nature and history of diffusionism. Chapter 2 analyzes the theory of the
autonomous rise of Europe as a body of propositions about European
superiority (and "the European miracle"), then tries to disprove these
propositions, one after the other. Chapter 3 discusses world history and
historical geography prior to 1492, attempting to show that Europe was not
superior to other civilizations and regions in those times. Chapter 4 argues
that colonialism was the basic process after 1492, which led to the
selective rise of Europe, the modernization or development of Europe (and
outlying Europeanized culture areas like the United States), and the
underdevelopment of Asia, Africa, and Latin America. Chapter 4 also
argues that the conquest of America and thereafter the expansion of
European colonialism is not to be explained in terms of any internal
characteristics of Europe, but instead reflects the mundane realities of
location. The chain of argument in Chapters 2, 3, and 4, as a whole,
therefore, is an attempt to show that Europe did not have historical
priority — historical superiority — over what we now call the Third World.
This may seem to be too ambitious a project for one small book. I am
really making just one claim. I am asserting that a fundamental and rather
explicit error has been made in our conventional past thinking about
geography and history, and this error has distorted many fields of thought
and action. I am going to present enough evidence to show that the belief
in Eurocentric diffusionism and Europe's historical superiority or priority
is not convincing: not well grounded in the facts of history and geography,
although firmly grounded in Western culture. It is in a sense folklore.
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 3
THE TUNNEL OF TIME
If you had gone to school in Europe or Anglo- America 150 years ago,
around the middle of the nineteenth century, you would have been
taught a very curious kind of history. You would have learned, for one
thing, that every important thing that ever happened to humanity
happened in one part of the world, the region we will call "Greater
Europe," meaning the geographical continent of Europe itself, plus (for
ancient times only) an enlargement of it to the southeast, the "Bible
Lands" — from North Africa to Mesopotamia — plus (for modern times
only) the countries of European settlement overseas. You would have
been taught that God created Man in this region: the Garden of Eden
was mentioned as the starting point of human history in typical world
history textbooks of the period, and these textbooks placed Eden at
various points between the shores of the Mediterranean Sea and the
mountains of Inner Asia.
Some of your teachers would have also claimed that only the people
of this region are really human: God created the people of other places
as a different, nonhuman, or rather infrahuman, species. And all of your
teachers of science as well as history would have agreed that
non-Europeans are not as intelligent, not as honorable, and (for the most
part) not as courageous as Europeans: God made them inferior. If you had
asked your teachers why Europeans are more human and more intelligent
than everyone else you would perhaps have been chastised for asking
such a question. You would have been told that a Christian God created
and now manages the world, and it would be both silly and blasphemous
to suggest that He might show the same favor to non-Europeans,
non-Christians, that He does to those people who worship the True God
and moreover worship Him with the proper sacrament.
If you had been studying geography as well as history back in the
middle of the nineteenth century, you would indeed have learned
something about the non-European world. The people living in Africa
and Asia would have been depicted not only as inferior but as in some
sense evil. They are the people who refused to accept God's grace and so
have fallen from His favor. Africans are thus cruel savages, for whom the
best possible fate is to be put to useful work, and Christianized. Chinese
and Indians for some unknown reason managed to build barbaric
civilizations of their own, but because they are not Europeans and not
Christians, their civilizations long ago began to stagnate and regress. And,
for all their splendor, these never were real civilizations: they are cruel
"Oriental despotisms." Only Europeans know true freedom.
4 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Ideas of course change, and if you had gone to school some 50 years
later, around the turn of the century, you would have been taught a much
more secular form of history, and it would have had a strongly
evolutionary (though not yet Darwinian) flavor. You would have learned
that the earth is very old, that life is old, and that our species itself has
been around for a long time. But everything important still happened in
Europe (that is, in Greater Europe). The first true man, Cro-Magnon,
lived in Europe. Agriculture was invented in Greater Europe (perhaps in
the continent, perhaps in the Bible Lands, Europe's self-proclaimed
cultural hearth). You would have been told in world history class that the
first barbaric beginnings of civilization occurred in the Bible Lands. There
in the Bible Lands emerged the two Caucasian peoples who make all of
history. The Semites invented cities and empires, and gave us
monotheism and Christianity, but stopped at that point and then sank
back into Oriental decadence. The Aryans or Indo-Europeans, freedom-
loving though backward folk, built on these foundations, migrating from
southeastern Europe or western Asia into and through geographical
Europe, and creating the first genuinely civilized society, that of ancient
Greece. Then the Romans raised civilization to its next level, and
thereafter world history marched inexorably northwestward. If your
school was in England you would have been told that History marched
from "the Orient" (the Bible Lands) to Athens, to Rome, to feudal
France, and finally to modern England — a kind of westbound Orient
Express.
By now a secular picture of the geography of non-Europe had begun
to be taught in European schools. Africans continued to be described as
savages and Oriental societies as decadent and despotic. But important
changes had taken place in the relations between Europe and non-Europe
during the course of the nineteenth century, and by 1900 a particular
theory about this relationship had become fixed in popular discourse and
was now taught in schools as standard world geography. This was the
theory (described later in this chapter) according to which non-
Europeans can and do rise to a civil izational level, if not equal to that of
Europeans at least near that level, under European tutelage, that is, under
European colonial control.
Suppose we move forward another half century, to the history and
geography taught around the end of World War II. Not much change.
The first True Man is still the Cro-Magnon of Europe. Agriculture was
invented in the Bible Lands; so too was barbaric civilization. True
civilization still marches from Athens to Rome to Paris to London, and
perhaps sets sail then for New York. Non-Europeans do not contribute
much to world history, although they begin to do so as a result of
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 5
European influence. (Colonial peoples learn from their tutors; Japanese
imitate successfully, and so on.) Europeans are still brighter, better, and
bolder than everyone else. 2
We can sum all of this up with an image that will prove quite useful
in this book. This is the idea that the world has an Inside and an Outside.
World history thus far has been, basically, the history of Inside. Outside
has been, basically, irrelevant. History and historical geography as it was
taught, written, and thought by Europeans down to the time of World
War II, and still (as we will see) in most respects today, lies, as it were, in
a tunnel of time. The walls of this tunnel are, figuratively, the spatial
boundaries of Greater Europe. History is a matter of looking back or down
in this European tunnel of time and trying to decide what happened
where, when, and why. "Why" of course calls for connections among
historical events, but only among the events that lie in the European
tunnel. Outside its walls everything seems to be rockbound, timeless,
changeless tradition. I will call this way of thinking "historical tunnel
vision," or simply "tunnel history."
The older form of tunnel history simply ignored the non-European
world: typical textbooks and historical atlases devoted very few pages to
areas outside of Greater Europe (that is, Europe and countries of European
settlement overseas plus, for ancient history and the Crusades, the Near
East), until one came to the year 1492. Non- Europe (Africa, Asia east of
the Bible Lands, Latin America, Oceania) received significant notice
only as the venue of European colonial activities, and most of what was
said about this region was essentially the history of empire. 3 Not only was
the great bulk of attention devoted to Greater Europe in these older
textbooks and historical atlases, but world history was described as flowing
steadily westward with the passage of time, from the Bible Lands to
eastern Mediterranean Europe, to northwestern Europe. This pattern is
readily discernible if we notice the salience of places mentioned in these
sources, that is, the frequency of place-name mentions for different
regions at different periods. For the earliest period, place-name mentions
cluster in the Bible Lands and the extreme eastern Mediterranean. For
successively later periods, place-name mentions cluster farther and farther
to the west and northwest, finally clustering in northwestern Europe for
the period after about A.D. 1000: this is the "Orient Express" pattern to
which we referred previously.
After World War II, however, history textbooks began to exhibit
another, more subtle, form of tunnel history. The non-European world
was now beginning to insert itself very firmly in European consciousness,
in the aftermath of the war with Japan and in the midst of the intensified
decolonization struggles, the Civil Rights movement in the United
6 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
States, and the like. Most newer textbooks enlarged the discussion of
non-European history, and said something about the historical achieve-
ments of non-European cultures. Most textbooks gave a flavor of
historicity, of evolutionary progress, to non-European history, thus
departing from the older pattern, which dismissed these societies as
stagnant and nonevolving. Asian societies were now described as having
had an evolutionary motion, though a motion slower than that of Europe.
Africa was still described as stagnant, history-less, prior to the colonial
era. More salience was given to Asia. However, Africa and the Western
Hemisphere still received little mention for eras prior to 1492. The
pattern of place-name mentions in most (not all) texts and historical
atlases still suggested a flow to the west and northwest, from the Near East
to western Europe. And tunnel history dominated most textbooks in the
most important matter of all, the question of "why," of explanation.
Historical progress still came about because Europeans invented or
initiated most of the crucial innovations, which only later spread out to
the rest of the world. So the textbooks depicted a world in which
historical causes were to be found basically inside the European tunnel of
time, although historical effects were to be seen basically everywhere.' 1
Textbooks are an important window into a culture; more than just
books, they are semiofficial statements of exactly what the opinion-
forming elite of the culture want the educated youth of that culture. to
believe to be true about the past and present world. 5 As we have seen,
European and Anglo-American history textbooks assert that most of the
causes of historical progress occur, or originate, in the European sector of
the world. Textbooks of the early and middle nineteenth century tended
to give a rather openly religious grounding for this Eurocentric tunnel
history. In later textbooks the Bible is no longer considered a source of
historical fact, but causality seems to be rooted in an implicit theory that
combines a belief that Christian peoples make history with a belief that
white peoples make history, the whole becoming a theory that it is natural
for Europeans to innovate and progress and for non-Europeans to remain
stagnant and unchanging ("traditional"), until, like Sleeping Beauty,
they are awakened by the Prince. This view still, in the main, prevails,
although racism has been discarded and non-Europe is no longer
considered to have been absolutely stagnant and traditional.
Schools are always a little behind the time when it comes to the
teaching of newer topics and ideas. I wish I could report that the old
notions about Inside and Outside are today just artifacts, still taught in
some schools because of the usual lag between research and pedagogy, but
which have been discarded by Real Scholars, those who pursue historical
research and write the important and influential books on world history.
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 7
But this is not the case. In the matter that concerns us most, that of
explaining the larger flows of world history, the views put forward by
historical scholars today tend to be quite consonant with the theories
projected in textbooks. We can set aside the fact that many of the most
widely used textbooks, today as in the past, are written by prominent
historical scholars. There are many complex cultural reasons why
historical scholarship remains committed to Eurocentric explanations for
most of the crucial developments in world history: we will discuss some of
these reasons later in the present chapter and return to the question at
various points throughout the book. Suffice it at this point to notice a
very peculiar paradox. Historians have amassed a fine record of
meticulous scholarship, and rarely indeed do we encounter prejudice or
deliberate distortion in their work. Moreover, their judgments about
historical causation are constrained by the same methodological rigor as
we find in any other field of scholarship. It is only when we come to the
larger issues of causation, matters of explaining historical progress over
long periods and for larger regions, and matters of explaining profound
revolutions in history, that Eurocentrism exerts an important influence
on discourse, and often — as we will see — leads to the acceptance of poor
theories in spite of a lack of supporting evidence.
Most European historians still maintain that most of the really
crucial historical events, those that "changed history," happened in
Europe, or happened because of some causal impetus from Europe.
("Europe" continues to mean "Greater Europe.") To illustrate this fact, I
will list now, in historical order, a series of crucial Europe-centered
propositions. All of them are accepted as true by the majority, in some
cases the great majority, of European historical scholars. Some of them
indeed are true, but that is beside the present point, which is to show that
historical reasoning still focuses on Greater Europe as the perpetual
fountainhead of history.
1. The Neolithic Revolution — the invention of agriculture and the
beginnings of a settled way of life for humanity — occurred in the
Middle East (or the Bible Lands). This view was unopposed before
about 1930, and is still the majority view.
2. The second major step in cultural evolution toward modern
civilization, the emergence of the earliest states, cities, organized
religions, writing systems, division of labor, and the like, was taken in
the Middle East.
3. The Age of Metals began in the Middle East. Ironworking was
invented in the Middle East or eastern Europe and the "Iron Age"
first appeared in Europe.
8 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
4. Monotheism appeared first in the Middle East.
5. Democracy was invented in Europe (in ancient Greece).
6. Likewise most of pure science, mathematics, philosophy, history, and
geography.
7. Class society and class struggle emerged first in the Greco-Roman era
and region. 6
8. The Roman Empire was the first great imperial state. Romans
invented bureaucracy, law, and so on.
9. The next great stage in social evolution, feudalism, was developed in
Europe, with Frenchmen taking the lead. 7
10. Europeans invented a host of technological traits in the Middle Ages
which gave them superiority over non-Europeans. (On this matter
there are considerable differences of opinion.).
1 1 . Europeans invented the modern state.
12. Europeans invented capitalism.
13. Europeans, uniquely "venturesome," were the great explorers,
"discoverers," etc.
14- Europeans invented industry and created the Industrial Revolution.
. . . and so on down to the present.
All of the propositions in this list are widely accepted tenets of
European historical scholarship today, although (as we will see) there is
scholarly dispute about some of the propositions. All of this means that
you and I learned these things, perhaps in elementary school, perhaps in
university, perhaps in books and newspapers. We learned that all of this
is the truth. But is it? Clearly, some of these propositions are true. Some
others are true with qualifications. But some, as I will argue in this book,
are not true at all: they are artifacts of the old tunnel history, in which
Outside plays no crucial role and Inside is credited with everything
important and everything efficacious.
EUROCENTRIC DIFFUSIONISM
Eurocentrism
What we are talking about here is generally called, these days,
"Eurocentrism." 8 This word is a label for all the beliefs that postulate past
or present superiority of Europeans over non- Europeans (and over
minority people of non-European descent). A strong critique of
Eurocentrism is underway in all fields of social thought, and this book is
certainly part of that critique.
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 9
There is, however, a problem with the word "Eurocentrism." In most
discourse it is thought of as a sort of prejudice, an "attitude," and therefore
something that can be eliminated from modern enlightened thought in
the same way we eliminate other relic attitudes such as racism, sexism,
and religious bigotry. But the really crucial part of Eurocentrism is not a
matter of attitudes in the sense of values and prejudices, but rather a
matter of science, and scholarship, and informed and expert opinion. To
be precise, Eurocentrism includes a set of beliefs that are statements about
empirical reality, statements educated and usually unprejudiced Europe-
ans accept as true, as propositions supported by "the facts." Consider, for
instance, the 14 propositions about Europe's priority in historical
innovation which we listed above. Historians who accept these
propositions as true would be most indignant if we described the
propositions as "Eurocentric beliefs." Every historian in this category
would deny emphatically that he or she holds any Eurocentric prejudices,
and very few of them actually do hold such prejudices. If they assert that
Europeans invented democracy, science, feudalism, capitalism, the
modern nation-state, and so on, they make these assertions because they
think that all of this is fact.
Eurocentrism, therefore, is a very complex thing. We can banish all
the value meanings of this word, all the prejudices, and we still have
Eurocentrism as a set of empirical beliefs.
This, in a way, is the central problem for this book. We confront
statements of presumed historical and scientific fact, not prejudices and
biases, and we try to show, with history and science, that the
presumptions are wrong: these statements are false.
How is it that Eurocentric historical statements which are not
valid — that is, not confirmed by evidence and sometimes contradicted by
evidence — are able to gain acceptance in European historical thought,
and thereafter survive as accepted beliefs, hardly ever questioned, for
generations and even centuries? This is a crucial problem for historiogra-
phy and the history of ideas. To deal with it satisfactorily would take us
well beyond the scope of this book, the main concern of which is
empirical history and geography. Yet the problem cannot be avoided here.
Libraries are full of scholarly studies that support the Eurocentric
historical positions we are rejecting and refuting in this book. The sheer
quantity of this work, and the respect that is properly owed to the scholars
who assembled it, makes it certain that one cannot convincingly refute
these positions with the factual arguments that can be presented in one
book. No matter how persuasive these arguments may be, they cannot be
placed, so to speak, on one arm of a balance and be expected to outweigh
all of the accumulated writings of generations of European scholars,
10 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
textbook writers, journalists, publicists, and the rest, heaped up on the
other arm of the balance.
So, in this book, we must make a sort of two-level argument. The
main level is the empirical one: What did happen inside and outside of
Europe in the medieval and early modern centuries, and what
connections did take place between the two sectors in that period? At the
second level, we will look at some pertinent aspects of the history of
Eurocentric ideas and the social context surrounding these ideas. This
will be done mainly in the present chapter, which analyzes the nature and
history of diffusionist ideas and concludes with a discussion of the process
of social licensing by which these ideas gain currency and hegemony, and
in Chapter 2, which rather systematically examines the most important
arguments for European superiority prior to 1492 and to an extent
discusses their historical genealogies.
Scholars today are aware, as most were not a few decades ago, that
the empirical, factual beliefs of history, geography, and social science very
often gain acceptance for reasons that have little to do with evidence.
Scholarly beliefs are embedded in culture, and are shaped by culture. This
helps to explain the paradox that Eurocentric historical beliefs are so
strangely persistent; that old myths continue to be believed in long after
the rationale for their acceptance has been forgotten or rejected (as in the
arguments grounded in belief in the Old Testament as literal history);
that newer candidate beliefs gain acceptance without supporting
evidence if they are properly Eurocentric; and that, most generally, the
Eurocentric body of beliefs as a whole retains its persuasiveness and
power. But there is more to the matter than this. Eurocentrism is, as I will
argue at great length in this book, a unique set of beliefs, and uniquely
powerful, because it is the intellectual and scholarly rationale for one of
the most powerful social interests of the European elite. I will argue not
only that European colonialism initiated the development of Europe (and
the underdevelopment of non-Europe) in 1492, but that since then the
wealth obtained from non-Europe, through colonialism in its many forms,
including neocolonial forms, has been a necessary and very important
basis for the continued development of Europe and the continued power
of Europe's elite. For this reason, the development of a body of
Eurocentric beliefs, justifying and assisting Europe's colonial activities,
has been, and still is, of very great importance. Eurocentrism is quite
simply the colonizer's model of the world.
Eurocentrism is the colonizer's model of the world in a very literal
sense: it is not merely a set of beliefs, a bundle of beliefs. It has evolved,
through time, into a very finely sculpted model, a structured whole; in fact
a single theory; in fact a super theory, a general framework for many
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 11
smaller theories, historical, geographical, psychological, sociological, and
philosophical. This supertheory is diffusionism.
Diffusionism
When culture change takes place in a human community, that change
can be the result of an invention that occurred within this community. Or
it can be the result of a process in which the idea or its material effect
(such as a tool, an art style, etc.) came into the community, having
originated in some other community, in some other part of the landscape.
The first sort of event is called "independent invention." The second is
called "diffusion." 9 Both processes occur everywhere. So far so good. But
some scholars believe that independent invention is rather uncommon,
and therefore not very important in culture change in the short run and
cultural evolution in the long run. These scholars believe that most
humans are imitators, not inventors. Therefore diffusion, in their view, is
the main mechanism for change.
The scholars who hold this view are called "diffusionists." Whenever
they encounter a cultural innovation in a particular region, they are
inclined to look diligently for a process of diffusion into that region from
somewhere else, somewhere the trait is already in use. For instance, the
fact that the blow-gun is traditionally used among some Native American
peoples as well as some Old World peoples is explained by diffusionists as
being the result of the diffusion of this trait from the Old World to the
New: the New World people, they believe, probably did not invent the
trait for themselves. Why? Because they probably were not inventive
enough to do so. A larger form of this same diffusionist argument claims
that the great pre-Columbian civilizations of the Americas must be,
ultimately, the result of transpacific or transatlantic diffusions, because
these civilizing traits (agriculture, temple architecture, writing, and so on)
were found much earlier in the Old World than the New, and Native
Americans probably were not inventive enough to think up these things
on their own. 10 Some scholars, those who have been traditionally
described as "extreme diffusionists," believe that all civilization diffused
from one original place on earth: some of them think that this original
source of civilization was ancient Egypt, others place it somewhere in
Central Asia (for instance, the Caucasus region — which scholars used to
think was the original home of the "white" or "Caucasian" race). 11
The debates between diffusionists and their opponents have been
going on for more than a century in anthropology, geography, history, and
all fields concerned about long-term, large-scale cultural evolution. 12 The
12 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
antidiffusionists (often called "evolutionists" or "independent-invention-
ists") have tended to level two basic charges against the diffusionists:
1. Diffusionists hold much too sour a view of human ingenuity:
people are in fact quite inventive and innovative, so the possibility that
new culture traits will appear as a result of independent invention is
actually vastly greater than diffusionists admit. So investigators should
consider the possibility of independent invention in any given case,
rather than assuming a priori that a diffusion process explains the
situation at which one is looking.
2. Diffusionists are elitists. Every diffusion must start somewhere. An
invention must take place in some one community before it begins to
spread (diffuse) to others. If we accept the quite fundamental assumption
that all human groups are truly human in their thinking apparatuses, and
therefore broadly similar in their ability to invent and innovate — this
assumption is known as "the psychic unity of mankind," a nineteenth-
century label that is quaint but still in use — we would expect inventions to
occur everywhere across the human landscape. 13 But most diffusionists
claim that only certain select communities are inventive. In other words, most
communities change only as a result of receiving new traits by diffusion,
but some places are uniquely inventive and are the original sources of the
new traits. The people of these communities are more inventive than are
people elsewhere. The psychic unity of mankind is denied: some people, or
cultures, are simply smarter than others. They are permanent centers of
invention and innovation.
This is spatial elitism. If we make a map of this landscape, we find
that it has a permanent center and a permanent periphery. For the
"extreme diffusionists" the entire world was mapped out this way, at least
for the pre-Christian era: the permanent center of invention and
innovation was thought to be Egypt, or the "Ancient Aryan Homeland"
(a mythical place located somewhere in western Asia or southeastern
Europe), or the Caucasus, or some other supposed navel of the ancient
world. But the charge was leveled more broadly: diffusionists as a group
tended to imagine that some few places, or some one place, was the
primary source from which culture spread to all the other places.
It should be evident that diffusionism is very nicely suited to the idea
that the world has an Inside and an Outside. In fact, diffusionism was the
most fully developed scientific (or pseudoscientific) rationale for the idea
of Inside and Outside. That idea, as we saw, postulates one permanent
world center for new ideas; cultural evolution everywhere else results,
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 13
broadly, from the diffusion of new ideas from this permanent center. This
is simply the diffusionists' map on a world scale.
We come now to a fascinating anomaly. The critics of diffusionism,
in the nineteenth century and even in the twentieth century, failed
entirely to grasp the full implications of their critique. None of them
denied that the world has an Inside and an Outside. While criticizing the
diffusionists for their rejection of the principle of the psychic unity of
mankind, the antidiffusionists nonetheless believed that cultural evolu-
tion has been centered in Europe, and they therefore accepted the
idea — explicitly or implicitly — that Europeans are more inventive, more
innovative than everyone else. 1 "* This is made explicit when they write
about recent centuries, and particularly when they discuss the moderniz-
ing, missionarizing effect of European colonialism. It is also implicit in
their writings about ancient times. These anthropologists, archaeologists,
geographers, and historians of the second half of the nineteenth century
and the present century do not focus on the Bible Lands, and their
scholarly writings do not display any acceptance of religious assumptions.
Yet Inside and Outside are explicit. They write about the Near Eastern
origins of agriculture, of urbanization, and so forth. They then move
smoothly to arguments about European origins of most of the rest of
civilization.
My basic argument is this: all scholarship is diffusionist insofar as it
axiomatically accepts the Inside-Outside model, the notion that the world
as a whole has one permanent center from which culture-changing ideas
tend to originate, and a vast periphery that changes as a result (mainly) of
diffusion from that single center. I do not argue that the formal theory of
diffusionism, as it was advanced and defended by scholars in the nine-
teenth and early twentieth centuries, explains the Inside-Outside model,
the mythology of Europe's permanent geographical superiority and prior-
ity. Rather, the theory developed as a result of broad social forces in
Europe, and entered the world of scholarship from outside of that world —
from European society. Diffusionist scholars were, in essence, elaborating
and codifying this theory in the realms of scholarship within which they
worked: realms like archaeology, world history, and so on.
Before we proceed further I must post a warning: the word "diffusion-
ist" has some ambiguities, and these should not be allowed to bring
confusion into the present discussion. In any given debate as to whether a
novel trait in a certain place was invented by the people of that place or
was received from elsewhere by diffusion, those scholars who take the
latter view are supporters of a "diffusionist" position, that is, they
favor the specific hypothesis of diffusion as against that of independent
14 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
invention. This does not necessarily mean that they have a general
propensity to favor diffusion as a causal formula. Sometimes the specific
issue can be a very major problem. For instance, some scholars argue that
important West African culture traits diffused across the Atlantic to
America before 1492. Whether they are right or wrong in this matter, they
are not arguing any sort of Eurocentric diffusionism, nor do they necessar-
ily favor diffusion over independent invention in other contexts. But most
scholars who are consistent diffusionists are also Eurocentric diffusionists.
Now I will describe Eurocentric diffusionism in somewhat formal
terms as a scientific theory. That theory has changed through time, but its
basic structure has remained essentially unchanged. I will describe what
can be called the classical (essentially nineteenth-century) form of the
theory, leaving until a later section of this chapter a discussion of the not
very dissimilar modern form.
Diffusionism is grounded, as we saw, in two axioms: ( 1 ) Most human
communities are uninventive. (2) A few human communities (or places,
or cultures) are inventive and thus remain the permanent centers of
culture change, of progress. At the global scale, this gives us a model of a
world with a single center — roughly, Greater Europe — and a single periph-
ery; an Inside and an Outside. There are a number of variants of this
two-sector model. Sometimes the two sectors are treated as sharply
distinct, with a definite boundary between them. (This form of the model
is the familiar one. It is sometimes called the "Center-Periphery Model of
the World.") Another form sees the world in a slightly different way: there
is a clear and definite center, but outside of it there is gradual change,
gradual decline in degree of civilization or progressiveness or innovative-
ness, as one moves outward into the periphery. Another variant depicts
the world as divided into zones, each representing a level of modernity or
civilization or development. 15 The classical division was one with three
great bands: "civilization," "barbarism," and "savagery."
The basic model of diffusionism in its classical form depicts a world
divided into the prime two sectors, one of which (Greater Europe, Inside)
invents and progresses, the other of which (non-Europe, Outside) receives
progressive innovations by diffusion from Inside. From this base, diffusion-
ism asserts seven fundamental arguments about the two sectors and the
interactions between them:
1. Europe naturally progresses and modernizes. That is, the natural
state of affairs in the European sector (Inside) is to invent, innovate,
change things for the better. Europe changes; Europe is "historical."
2. Non-Europe (Outside) naturally remains stagnant, unchanging,
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 15
traditional, and backward. Invention, innovation, and change are not the
natural state of affairs, and not to be expected, in non-European
countries. Non-Europe does not change; non-Europe is "ahistorical."
Propositions 3 and 4 explain the difference between the two sectors - .
3. The basic cause of European progress is some intellectual or
spiritual factor, something characteristic of the "European mind," the
"European spirit," "Western Man," etc., something that leads to
creativity, imagination, invention, innovation, rationality, and a sense of
honor or ethics: "European values."
4- The reason for non-Europe's nonprogress is a lack of this same
intellectual or spiritual factor. This proposition asserts, in essence, that
the landscape of the non-European world is empty, or partly so, of
"rationality," that is, of ideas and proper spiritual values. There are a
number of variations of this proposition in classical (mainly late-
nineteenth-century) diffusionism. Two are quite important:
a. For much of the non-European world, this proposition asserts an
emptiness also of basic cultural institutions, and even an emptiness of
people. This can be called the diffusionist myth of emptiness, and it has
particular connection to settler colonialism (the physical movement of
Europeans into non-European regions, displacing or eliminating the
native inhabitants). This proposition of emptiness makes a series of
claims, each layered upon the others: (i) A non-European region is
empty or nearly empty of people (hence settlement by Europeans does
not displace any native peoples), (ii) The region is empty of settled
population: the inhabitants are mobile, nomadic, wanderers (hence
European settlement violates no political sovereignty, since wanderers
make no claim to territory, (iii) The cultures of this region do not
possess an understanding of private property — that is, the region is
empty of property rights and claims (hence colonial occupiers can
freely give land to settlers since no one owns it). The final layer,
applied to all of the Outside sector, is an emptiness of intellectual
creativity and spiritual values, sometimes described by Europeans (as,
for instance, by Max Weber) as an absence of "rationality." 16
b. Some non-European regions, in some historical epochs, are assumed to
have been "rational" in some ways and to some degree. Thus, for
instance, the Middle East during biblical times was rational. China was
somewhat rational for a certain period in its history. 17 Other regions,
always including Africa, are unqualifiedly lacking in rationality.
16 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Propositions 5 and 6 describe the ways Inside and Outside interact:
5. The normal, natural way that the non-European part of the world
progresses, changes for the better, modernizes, and so on, is by the diffusion
(or spread) of innovative, progressive ideas from Europe, which flow into
it as air flows into a vacuum. This diffusion may take the form of the spread
of European ideas as such, or the spread of new products in which the
European ideas are concretized, or the spread (migration, settlement) of
Europeans themselves, bearers of these new and innovative ideas.
Proposition 5, you will observe, is a simple justification for European
colonialism. It asserts that colonialism, including settler colonialism,
brings civilization to non-Europe; is in fact the natural way that the
non-European world advances out of its stagnation, backwardness,
traditionalism.
But under colonialism, wealth is drawn out of the non-European
colonies and enriches the European colonizers. In Eurocentric diffu-
sionism this too is seen as a normal relationship between Inside and
Outside:
6. Compensating in part for the diffusion of civilizing ideas from
Europe to non-Europe, is a counterdiffusion of material wealth from
non-Europe to Europe, consisting of plantation products, minerals, art
objects, labor, and so on. Nothing can fully compensate the Europeans for
their gift of civilization to the colonies, so the exploitation of colonies
and colonial peoples is morally justified. (Colonialism gives more than it
receives.)
And there is still another form of interaction between Inside and Outside.
It is the opposite of the diffusion of civilizing ideas from Europe to
non-Europe (proposition 5):
7. Since Europe is advanced and non-Europe is backward, any ideas
that diffuse into Europe must be ancient, savage, atavistic, uncivilized,
evil — black magic, vampires, plagues, "the bogeyman," and the like. 18
Associated with this conception is the diffusionist myth which has been
called "the theory of our contemporary ancestors." It asserts that, as we
move farther and farther away from civilized Europe, we encounter people
who, successively, reflect earlier and earlier epochs of history and culture.
Thus the so-called "stone-age people" of the Antipodes are likened to the
Paleolithic Europeans. The argument here is that diffusion works in
successive waves, spreading outward, such that the farther outward we go
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 17
the farther backward we go in terms of cultural evolution. But conversely,
there is the possibility that these„ ancient, atavistic, etc., traits will
counterdiffuse back into the civilized core, in the form of ancient, magical,
evil things like black magic, Dracula, etc.
The main oppositions between the two sectors can be shown in
tabular form. The following contrast-sets are quite typical in nineteenth-
century diffusionist thought:
Characteristic of Core
Inventiveness
Rationality, intellect
Abstract thought
Theoretical reasoning
Mind
Discipline
Adulthood
Sanity
Science
Progress
Characteristic of Periphery
Imitativeness
Irrationality, emotion, instinct
Concrete thought
Empirical, practical reasoning
Body, matter
Spontaneity
Childhood
Insanity
Sorcery
Stagnation
What I have described thus far is, of course, a highly simplified version of
the diffusionist world model. We will add qualifications and modifica-
tions as we proceed, and in particular we will see that there are significant
differences between the classical form of diffusionism and the modern
form of the model.
So much for what diffusionism is. What does it do 7 . In this book I will
show in some detail how diffusionism has shaped our views of history,
both European and non-European. Later in the present chapter and in
Chapter 2 I will show some of the concrete influences of diffusionism on
theories outside of history, some in psychology, some in geography, some
in economics, some in sociology.
But this discussion will be more meaningful after a different question
has been addressed. This is the question of how and why diffusionism
became such a foundation theory in Western thought. To this question
we now turn.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL
Perhaps all civilizations have a somewhat ethnocentric view of
themselves in relation to their neighbors, believing themselves better,
18 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
brighter, and bolder than every other human community and construct-
ing empirical theories to explain why this is the case, and to explain away
embarrassments. Perhaps we would find the seeds of diffusionism in all
these beliefs: the idea that progress is natural and calls for no explanation
in "our" society but is unnatural or at, any rate, less impressive in "their"
societies; the idea that "they" progress by borrowing from "us" and
imitating "our" ideas; and so on. But this does not add up to the theory of
diffusionism, nor is it very important for an understanding of diffusionism.
Diffusionism as I have been discussing it is a product of modern European
colonialism. It is the colonizer's model of the world.
Origins
Diffusionism became a fully formed scientific theory during the
nineteenth century. The origins of the theory, however, go back to the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries in Western Europe, where a belief
system was being constructed to give some coherence to the new reality of
change within Europe and colonial expansion outside Europe. The
conception of a two-sector world, the diffusionist distinction between
Inside and Outside, emerged from a very old conception of Christendom
and the Roman imperial legacy (which meant, for most of western and
southern Europe, a common source of legitimacy for the political and
landholding elites). But it is certainly not true that medieval Europeans
saw Christendom as a sharply defined space, naturally in conflict with
surrounding societies. Nor did medieval European thinkers have many
illusions about the relative power, wealth, and technological prowess of
Christendom as compared with Islamic and Oriental civilizations. But
certainly they had some idea, not of a collective identity, but of a
distinction between the lands inhabited by Christians, given divine
guidance and protection for this reason, and the lands of non-Christians.
Nevertheless, it was only after 1492 that Inside acquired a sharp geograph-
ical definition, less as a result of medieval ideas than of colonialism in the
early modern period.
European ideas about European progressiveness, Europe's somehow
inevitable progress, are also essentially postmedieval. Obviously, these
ideas were being discussed during the Middle Ages, and certainly there
was hope, prayer, and struggle for betterment, but medieval folk tended
rather to see their society as being in a relative state of equilibrium; their
religion spoke of the Fall, and of the need to accept existing conditions
(and rules), while the reality of medieval life (particularly fourteenth- and
fifteenth-century life) was not one of perceptible forward progress for the
mass of people. But European thinkers of the sixteenth and seventeenth
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 19
centuries were coming to conceive of history — their own history — as a
progressive process. Real progress (or at any rate accelerating change)
indeed was taking place in the communities occupied by these thinkers,
and the climate of ideas was changing in a complex but close association
with the rise of capitalism, the expansion of opportunity for individuals in
many regions, and the like.
One of the main problems confronted by these early modern
thinkers, both secular and religious, was the need to establish a belief
system, an ideology, that would convince conservative sectors of the
European community to accept the idea that progress is inevitable,
natural, and desirable, and thus to accept changes in the legal system
which would permit more rapid and widespread capital accumulation, to
persuade the landowning classes to treat land as a commodity and invest
their real holdings in risk enterprises, to introduce laws and practices to
mobilize labor for emerging capitalist activities at home and abroad, to
persuade Europeans in general to accept the painful changes being
imposed on them, and so on. Equally important was the need to explain
progress in ways that accorded with religion. This was done by seeing
God's guidance of (European) history, and by conceptualizing progressive
innovations as being products of the European mind or spirit and thus
ultimately products of the Christian soul. (We will go into these matters
later in this book.)
Thus emerged the conception of Inside as being naturally progressive
(diffusionist proposition 1), and as being progressive because of the
workings of an intellectual or spiritual force, "European rationality"
(diffusionist proposition 3). By the eighteenth century it had become the
practice in secular writings to discuss causality in history and philosophy
without referencing God and Scriptures, but the basic model of European
progress as natural, as rational, remained unchanged in its essence;
became, indeed, much fortified. 19 In none of this thought was there any
real suspicion that non-European civilizations might have had much to
do with the earlier, medieval progress of Christian Europe, or much to do
with its modern (sixteenth- to eighteenth-century) progress except in the
purely passive role of provider of labor, commodities, and land for
settlement, and, marginally, in some traits of technology and art. Nor was
there very much awareness that colonialism and its windfalls — inflow of
capital, intensification of intra-as well as extra-European trade, increase
in employment opportunities in mercantile centers and in the colonial
world, and much more — was an important cause of European progress.
Then, as later, the European conception of its own dynamic society
attributed dynamism not to external causes but to internal causes, and to
God. This relatively constant blindness to the importance of colonialism,
20 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
historically and even today, will claim our attention at various points in
this book.
The development of a conception of Outside proceeded in a more
complicated way. The sixteenth-century Spanish debates about the
nature of New World Indians — Are they human? Can they receive the
True Religion and, if so, can they be made slaves? — was a crucial part of
the early formulation of diffusionism, because it entailed an attempt to
conceptualize European expansion and explain why it was, somehow,
natural, desirable, and profitable, and to conceptualize the societies that
were being conquered and exploited, explaining why it was, again, natural
for them to succumb and to provide Europeans with labor, land, and
products. 20 European views of New World peoples were formed rather
quickly because in that region the basic pattern of colonialism emerged
quickly. The enterprise was immensely profitable from the very
beginning, from the first great shipments of gold in the early sixteenth
century (see Chapter 4). Resistance was rapidly overcome in Spanish
colonies and surviving Americans were rather quickly forced to submit to
colonial exploitation. (I refer here to the major centers of early
colonialism, such as central Mexico, the Greater Antilles, and the
Andes.) In the next century the profitability of slave plantations in Brazil
and the Antilles, and the fact that African slaves could, in spite of their
resistance, be forced to work and produce profit for Europeans, added
further to the conception of Outside: these people were naturally inferior
to Europeans, naturally less brave, less freedom loving, less rational, and
so on, and progress for them depended on acceptance of European
domination, hence diffusion. In sum, the New World experience, with
Native Americans, Africans, mestizos, and mulattos, in areas of mining,
large-scale estate agriculture, commercial plantations, and so forth,
produced the kernel of the diffusionist propositions (2, 4, and 5), which
assert that non-Europe naturally depends on Europe for progress and this
is due to a lack of the intellectual and spiritual qualities that Europeans
possessed. It also produced the diffusionist proposition (6) that European
expansion is natural and leads naturally to the transfer of wealth from
non-Europe to Europe.
But these activities were taking place only in the New World and the
slave-trading coasts of Africa. The civilizations of Sudanic, southern, and
eastern Africa were not conquered by Europeans until (in most cases) the
nineteenth century; the Ottoman Empire was not only formidable
throughout this period, but was indeed expanding its territorial control in
southeastern Europe at the same time that Iberians were conquering the
New World. And the other great empires did not begin to succumb to
colonialism before the mid-eighteenth century: European activities in
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 21
nearly all parts of Asia and Africa were mainly matters of trade, with
dominance of long-distance maritime trade, small territorial footholds
here and there on certain coasts, and the like (see Chapter 4). Thus, in
the sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries, the diffusionist
model of Outside which had been applied to Americans and to the groups
of Africans transported to America as slaves could not be applied to the
civilizations of the Old World.
For these Eastern Hemisphere civilizations a limited and somewhat
tentative form of the diffusionist model was accepted during this period.
These civilizations were indisputably rich and technically advanced.
Rationality in the sense of inventiveness was clearly present, or at least
had been present in the past, when the great and impressive innovations
(technology, architecture, banking, and so on) had occurred. What these
civilizations lacked was the moral component of rationality, because,
fundamentally, they were not Christians. These were "Oriental despot-
isms," societies in which there was, naturally, cruelty, lack of freedom,
lack of a decent life for the common people (while the elite wallowed in
decadence and sin), etc. (We discuss this concept at some length in
Chapter 2.) The moral failing necessarily led to an inability of these
societies to progress in the present, the era when Europe is naturally
progressing, although Europeans could not deny, even though they found
it most puzzling, that these despotic civilizations had, indisputably,
progressed in the past. (At times the puzzle was resolved by declaring that
they had progressed in pre-Christian times, and had lost the Grace of God
through having refused to accept Christianity. 21 ) Only in the nineteenth
century, with the rapid colonization of India, Southeast Asia, interior
Africa, and (as a kind of collective colony) China, did the diffusionist
propositions about Outside, and about the natural relations between
Inside and Outside, become generalized to all of non-Europe. It was in this
late period, I think, that the final diffusionist propositions the notion of
counterdiffusion of evil and savagery and disease from Outside to Inside,
become fully developed. The bogeyman (from the Malay Buginese
people) came from Outside. So too did Dracula, whose homeland lay on
the edge of Asia. 22
Classical Diffusionism
The nineteenth century was the classical era for colonialism, and the era
when Eurocentric diffusionism assumed what I will call its classical form.
After the Napoleonic Wars colonialism expanded and intensified with
remarkable rapidity. Between 1810 and 1860 or thereabouts Europeans
subdued most of Asia, settled most of North America, and began the
22 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
penetration of Africa. Between 1860 and the start of World War I, the
rest of Asia and Africa was occupied and the profits from colonialism, the
value of capital accumulated in Asia, Africa, and Latin America, along
with the riches flowing from newly settled areas of European settlement,
expanded enormously. In the latter part of the century the rate of growth
in colonial agricultural enterprise exceeded that of industrial develop-
ment on a world scale, and other forms of development, such as the
mining of nonprecious metals, were becoming important for the first
time. 23 There is profound disagreement as to how important all of this was
for European social and intellectual evolution in this period. I will enter
this debate in Chapter 4, but for the present it is sufficient to assert that
the overall effect of European expansion, through colonialism in the
narrow sense, through settlement, and through semicolonial economic
dominance, was profound enough to create a very large intellectual
model, the classical form of diffusionism.
By 1870 or thereabouts there was broad agreement among European
thinkers about the basic nature and dynamics of the world. Few doubted
that biological and social evolution — that is, progress — were fundamental
truths, although evolutionary processes were more often explained in
religious or metaphysical ways than in naturalistic ways, as in Darwin's
theory. 24 It seemed clear that Europeans were naturally to experience
permanent social evolution, that this had been God's or Nature's plan
throughout history. Some historical thinkers described the general
process in holistic terms, as the evolution of society or the state; others
treated it in reductionist (in a sense, psychological) terms as an
intellectual ascent, a matter of the steady advance of human reason, with
capitalism, industry, and so on, treated as products of mind; but many
thinkers (among them Herbert Spencer) saw no opposition between the
social and intellectual models, treating progress as a kind of flowing
stream, which carried with it an evolution both of society and of mind. 25
All of this was explicit with regard to Europe and Europeans including of
course Anglo-Americans. Thus by the 1870s at the latest the central
diffusionist proposition, the notion of natural, continuous, internally
generated progress in the European (or west European) core, was very
firmly in place. Its truth was no longer really questioned by mainstream
thinkers.
There was, at the same time, a convergence of views about the nature
and historical dynamics of the non- European world. By the middle of the
nineteenth century the biblical time scale had been rather definitively
rejected (though not yet in all history textbooks), and it was no longer
necessary to argue that differences between Europeans and all other
cultures had to have evolved in the space of a few thousand years unless
HISTORY INSIDE OUT
they had been there from the start, unless, that is, polygenists were right
and some human groups had been created separately from, and perhaps
much earlier than, Adam and Eve. This gave room for wide-ranging
theorization about the way cultural differences had evolved. Paralleling
this change was a general rejection of the literal biblical beliefs about the
original nature of human society. Culture was now (after midcentury)
quite generally seen as a product of evolution from very primitive
beginnings, exemplified in the notion of a primordial "stone age."
(According to the Old Testament, humans had possessed advanced
technology, including agriculture and the use of metals, in the days of
Genesis.)
The reasons for the rapid crystallization of beliefs about non-
Europeans are complex, but the most important underlying reason was the
progress of colonialism. This produced two effects in particular. One was
a flood of information about non-European people and places, such that,
for the first time, a coherent — though highly distorted — description could
be given in the European literature about non-Europeans, both civilized
and "savage." The second reason was a practical, political and economic
interest in proving certain things to be true, and other things untrue,
about the extra-European world and its people. The two processes were
tightly interconnected.
Colonialism in its various forms, direct and indirect, was an
immensely profitable business and considerable sums of money were
invested in efforts to learn as much as possible about the people and
resources of the regions to be conquered, dominated, and perhaps settled,
and to learn as much as possible about the regions already conquered in
order to facilitate the administration and economic exploitation of these
regions. The nineteenth century was the age of scientific exploration —
Darwin in the Beagle, Livingstone in Africa, Powell in the Rockies, and
so on — but the sources of support for these efforts tended to be institutions
with very practical interest in the regions being studied. Paralleling all of
this was the great surge of missionary activity that supported some
exploration (including Livingstone's) but most crucially led to the
gathering of important, detailed, information about ethnography,
languages, and geography by hundreds of dedicated missionaries through-
out the non-European world. Also of great importance were the detailed
reports that colonial administrators everywhere were required to submit,
reports providing information about native legal systems, land tenure
rules, production, and much more.
Most of what was learned about non-Europeans came from these
sources. It is not necessary for me to dwell on the fact that the people who
supplied the information were Europeans with very definite points of
24 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
view, cultural, political, and religious lenses that forced them to see
"natives" in ways that were highly distorted. A missionary might have
great love and respect for the people among whom he or she worked but
could not be expected to believe that the culture and mind of these
non-Christians was on a par with that of Christian Europeans. A colonial
administrator not only had cultural distortions but usually worked with
economic interests and classes (European planters, mining corporations,
ZCLmindnrs, and so on) and consciously or unconsciously put forward views
about common people, and about resources, that reflected the biases and
concrete interests of these elite groups. Strictly speaking, missionaries and
colonial administrators were in the business of diffusing Europe to
non-Europe. Thus the entire corpus of information about non-Europeans
that was gathered in this process has certain quite definite distortions. It
was immensely valuable in spite of this fact, but the plain fact is that
theories constructed from this information — and this includes the great
bulk of nineteenth-century anthropological, geographic, and politi-
coeconomic theories about non-Europeans — are systematically distorted.
The distortions are, broadly, those of diffusionism.
But colonial interest added an additional kind of distortion, a matter
of shaping knowledge into theories that would prove useful for
colonialism. Scientific and legal theories were constructed in general by
policymakers and by intellectuals who were either themselves poli-
cymakers or were close to policy. (In England, for instance, an
extraordinary percentage of the influential historians, social theorists,
even novelists and poets, had direct connections with the East India
Company, the Colonial Office, and other private and public agencies of
empire. 26 ) I include under the label "theory" a wide range of general
arguments, including the larger constructs of history.
At the most general level, intellectuals were shaping theories of
social evolution which were in essence demonstrations that the postulates
of diffusionism are natural law. As we noticed previously, the nineteenth-
century debates between those called "evolutionists" and those called
"diffusionists" were essentially debates between two versions of diffusion-
ism. A great range of theories in both camps were constructs aimed to
assist in colonial activity, and to develop and strengthen the doctrine that
European colonialism is scientifically natural, a matter of the inevitable
working out of social laws of human progress (development of the family,
law, the state, etc.). Also at the very general level, seminal works of the
middle and later nineteenth century on ancient and modern history
presented various sophisticated diffusionist ideas, mainly about the
reasons for and the facts of Europe's natural and persistent progress
compared with other peoples, those now being colonized. These historical
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 25
constructs were important in building support for colonial activities
among European populations; and later, as colonial educational systems
appeared, for convincing the natives that colonialism was natural,
inevitable, and progressive.
In Chapter 2 I will discuss a number of these diffusionist theories
which emerged, or became concrete, in the nineteenth century in the
complex association of scholarship and colonialism, focusing on those
theories that today underlie the myth of Europe's historical and cultural
superiority. Here I need only show how classical diffusionism arose in
tandem with classical colonialism, and for this purpose a pair of
representative theories can be singled out by way of illustration.
One such theory was the postulate that non-Europeans have not
developed concepts of private property in important material resources
such as land. The theory asserted that private property emerged from
ancient European roots, notably Roman land law and various putative
Germanic traits relating to individualism; that other civilizations, lacking
this history (and, by implication, lacking the mental and cultural qualities
associated with this history), remained in a stage of evolution in which
true individual ownership could not be fully conceptualized. These people,
therefore, needed to have capitalism imposed on them. In fact, the theory
was developed mainly by lawyers and administrators in the European
colonial corporations and colonial offices, and had one very concrete
purpose: to establish the legal basis for expropriating land from colonized
peoples, on the fiction that the colonized had no property rights to this
land because they had no concept of property rights in land. 27 Yet the
theory became essentially an axiom in nineteenth-century intellectual
thought. Even Karl Marx accepted it, and doing so produced a large theory
about the evolution of private property — a major part of his theory about
the origins of capitalism — in which it was argued (or rather assumed) that
this evolution was peculiarly a European phenomenon, and that colonial-
ism, for all its horrors, did at least bring about the diffusion of capitalism to
the non-European world, a necessary though painful process for the
non-Europeans. Thus even Marxism, perhaps the most antisystemic doc-
trine to come out of nineteenth-century Europe, was strongly shaped by
diffusionism. 28
A larger form of this doctrine, the more general "myth of emptiness,"
the diffusionist idea that a colonized or colonizable territory was empty of
population, or was populated only by wandering nomads, people with no
fixed abode and therefore no claim to territory, or lacked people with a
concept of political sovereignty or economic property, had similar coloni-
alist functions, and arose in a similar way. The same is true of a closely
related doctrine, the theory of "Oriental despotism" (older in point of
26 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
origin, but developed fully in nineteenth-century diffusionist thought),
according to which non-Europeans lack the concept of freedom, hence
suffer despotic governments that stifle all progress — until Europeans bring
freedom to them in the form of colonialism (which ironically is the purest
negation of freedom). These and other theories that arose from classical
diffusionism are still employed today to reinforce the myth of Europe's
historical and cultural superiority; we will discuss them in Chapter 2,
which seeks to refute this myth.
The era of classical diffusionism was the era of classical colonialism,
the era when European expansion was so swift and so profitable that
European superiority seemed almost to be a law of nature. Diffusionism, in
its essence, codified this apparent fact into a general theory about Euro-
pean historical, cultural, and psychological superiority, non-European
inferiority, and the inevitability and absolute righteousness of the process
by which Europe and its traits diffused to non-Europe. Diffusionism then
ramified the general theory into innumerable empirical beliefs in all the
human sciences, in philosophy, in the arts. 29 And it applied these beliefs
in particular cases, explaining and justifying the individual acts of con-
quest, of repression, of exploitation. All of it was right, rational, and
natural.
Modern Diffusionism
The nineteenth century, or more precisely the interval between the
defeat of Napoleon and the beginning of World War I, was a time of
relative peace and relative progress for Europeans. Colonialism fueled this
process with resources, markets, cheap labor, and lands for settlement by
Europeans, and colonialism resolved many of Europe's internal contradic-
tions in the process. The idea that progress in European civilization and
expansion of that civilization in space were different dimensions of the
same historical force was the dominant idea of the time, and this was, of
course, the central notion of diffusionism.
But all of this changed early in the twentieth century. The world is
finite in size, so spatial expansion had to come to an end, and by 1900 all
of the non-European world had been carved up into colonies,
semi-colonial spheres of control, and territories of settlement. This
change of conditions produced a change in thought: the essential problem
now was exploitation and the maintenance of control in the face of
native resistance. Thus it became a question not of expansion but of
equilibrium. At the same time tensions among European powers — some
of the tensions were connected to conflicts over colonies — boiled over
into general war among the European powers. Soon after World War I
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 27
came the Great Depression. Then, immediately, World War II. Between
1914 and 1945, then, the minds of European intellectuals were focused
not on the idea of progress and expansion, but on the question of how to
prevent disaster: how to maintain, or return to, peace and prosperity. The
code word was "normalcy."
The central notion of diffusionism did not fit this intellectual mood.
The prevailing doctrines of this period were theories of stasis, of
equilibrium, not theories of expansion. Economics dwelled on Keynesian
ideas of equilibrium. In geography, the doctrine known as "regionalism"
prevailed, the idea that the various parts of the world are stable, coherent,
well-demarcated regions and tend to remain that way. Anthropology was
emphasizing two equilibrium theories: "functionalism," a model of social
systems (and cultures) as stable and self-correcting systems, and "cultural
relativism," a doctrine that declared in essence that each culture has
intrinsic worth. Anthropologists of course worked primarily among
colonized peoples, and these two theories were closely integrated with
colonial policy, mainly as a basis for policies designed to prevent native
unrest while allowing European exploitation of land, minerals, and
labor. 30 Thus equilibrium doctrines were very widespread, probably
dominant, in European thought throughout most of the first half of the
twentieth century.
Diffusionism, in this period, seems to have gone into a partial eclipse.
History and geography textbooks were still sublimely diffusionist, in an
essentially nineteenth-century mood, emphasizing the beneficial spread
of civilization to Africa, Asia, and Latin America ("where our bananas
come from"), the teleological rise of "the West," and so on. In social
thought, the doctrines of "extreme diffusionism" (discussed earlier) were
still being advanced, and still debated. 31 And it should not be thought
that the decline of diffusionism as a doctrine of cultural dynamics implied
a decline in prejudice. The notion that non-Europeans are less rational,
less innovative, and so on, was as intense as ever: perhaps even more
intense since this was the period of Nazism and like doctrines, and since
genetic racism seemed, in this era, to be science, not prejudice. We return
to this matter in Chapter 2.
A new and modern form of diffusionism gained prominence after the
end of World War II, in the period of collapsing colonial empires and an
emerging "Third World" of underdeveloped but legally sovereign
countries. This doctrine, generally known today by the title "moderniza-
tion," or "the diffusion of modernization," arose in the late 1940s and the
1950s. Immediately after the Japanese surrender in 1945 it became clear
that a number of colonies would gain independence immediately:
liberation forces were now very strong and, in the wake of the world war,
28 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
all of the colonial powers except the United States were now quite weak.
All of them wanted to hold on to their colonies, the sources of great profit
in the past and presumably also in the future. Each of the colonial powers
maneuvered in its own way to hold on to its colonies, sometimes resorting
to forcible efforts to suppress independence movements, sometimes
conceding political independence grudgingly but peacefully where
continued colonial control seemed patently impossible. 32
All colonies had been saturated during the classical colonial era with
the ideological message that economic and social progress for the colonial
people had to come through the diffusion of "modernization" from the
colonizing power. "Modernization" meant the diffusion of a modern
economy (with major corporations owned by the colonizer), a modem
public administration (the colonial political structure), a modern techni-
cal infrastructure (bridges, dams, and the like, built by the colonizer), and
so on. I call this an ideological message, but it was in fact believed in
profoundly by the colonizers, who felt that their mission was, indeed, to
diffuse their own civilization to the peoples who were under their
"colonial tutelage," and the fact that this mission produced wealth for
their own country seemed only logical (recall diffusionist proposition 6).
In the new situation the colonizers had to persuade the colonized that the
"modernization" message was still valid. Doing so, they might convince
the colonized to voluntarily relinquish the ideal of political independence
in favor of the more pragmatic ideal of economic and social development
under a wise and benevolent colonial rule. Or, if independence was
insisted upon, this ideology would convince the people of the country
now acquiring freedom that the only way to develop that country
economically and socially was to retain the colonial economy, that is, to
allow the colonizer's corporations and banks to continue their (profita-
ble) work under the new regime: a system everyone today describes as
"neocolonialism. "
Now all colonial powers began a major campaign to intensify the
process of colonial economic development. 33 This should not be thought
of as cynical or hypocritical: remember that diffusionism defined the
colonial process as beneficial for the colonized as well as the colonizer, and
the technical and other personnel involved in the new colonial develop-
ment activities were utterly convinced that they were working for the
advancement of the colonized people. At the same time, a parallel
campaign was developed to further the same form of economic develop-
ment in the independent countries, partly through agencies of the United
Nations, partly through bilateral aid agreements. 34 The United States,
now the leading economic power, began to establish its own aid programs
in countries throughout the underdeveloped world. Again, this should not
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 29
be dismissed as cynical and political: there was, in this period, a tremen-
dously euphoric ideology that saw the end of the world war as the
beginning of an Age of Development, a time when the advanced nations
would work to bring — that is, diffuse — prosperity and advancement to the
poor nations.
Decolonization spread, and many liberation movements and newly
independent countries refused to accept the neocolonial option, either
ejecting foreign corporations (as did Indonesia) or opting for a specifically
socialist society. This added a new impetus to the diffusion-of-moderniza-
tion project. Efforts to bring about development through diffusion were
intensified in hopes that their success would lead countries to reject the
anticapitalist and antiforeign options. But the choice of either of these two
options seemed to imply a political alignment with the Soviet Union and
China, so the diffusion-of-modernization project now became important
as a matter of foreign policy in the Cold War. In 1959 the Cuban
revolutionary victory gave the project very high priority for the United
States, which now treated modernization and economic development,
particularly in Latin America, as a matter of the highest priority, calling for
very large investment. 35
Modern diffusionism is the body of ideas which underlay, and still
underlies, this new set of conditions in the Third World. The diffusion of
modernization, as it is carried out by public policy makers and private
corporations and theorized by intellectuals (at least in the metropolitan,
formerly colonizing, countries), is considered to be essentially the process
by which Third World countries gain prosperity by accepting the continu-
ous and increasing diffusion of economic and technological plums from
the formerly colonial countries, a process that now, as in the past, is
supremely profitable for the latter. In the diffusionist belief system, it is
profitable for everybody, and also is right, rational, and natural, just as it
had been a century earlier.
The ideas of 1993 are of course very different from the ideas of 1893,
so it would be wrong to think that modern diffusionism is the same as
classical diffusionism. Biological racism is no longer part of the model (as
we will see in Chapter 2), and few modern European thinkers believe that
non-Europeans simply do not have the potential to develop eventually to
the level of Europeans. Religious undertones are largely absent, and the
notion that a Christian god began things with the putative ancestors of
Europeans, in the Bible Lands, and thereafter guided Europeans, Chris-
tians, to persistent superiority over all others, is no longer very popular.
The historical greatness of some non-European civilizations is now fully
conceded. (But with one vital qualification: less rationality, less innova-
tiveness, than European civilization. We deal with this in Chapter 2.)
30 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
After about a quarter-century of blind faitb that the diffusion of moderni-
zation would bring about economic development everywhere, European
experts and scholars now qualify their belief in this model, and in
particular draw back from their former naive faith that the diffusion of
modern technology, particularly in agriculture, is the key to economic
development, the key to what used to be called "the take-off into sustained
growth."
But, all of this notwithstanding, the basic propositions of diffusionism
remain in place. Europeans still believe that Inside has one fundamental
cultural nature and Outside another, now admitting Japan into the Inside
sector. It is still believed that Europe in the past displayed a progressiveness
not found in any other civilizations, except in one or two places, at one or
two moments of history. Although European scholars no longer insist that
this fundamental difference between a progressive Inside and a stagnant or
slow-moving Outside will persist into the indefinite future, most of them
write and speak about the present and future as though this fundamental
dynamic will continue (again qualifying the picture to admit Japan, and
perhaps a few small East Asian societies, into the dynamic of Inside). But
today, as we will see in the next chapter, there is a growing, though still
small, group of European scholars, mainly responding to the newer ideas
that now emanate from non-European scholarship in postcolonial socie-
ties, who question the overall diffusionist model, and who deny its
historical conceptions about the superiority of Inside over Outside.
WORLD MODELS
AND WORLDLY INTERESTS
Diffusionism is a poor theory. Diffusionism, as I argue in this book, is not
good geography and not good history. Yet it exerts a tremendous influence
on scholarship, and has done so for a very long time. How do we account
for the fact that a bad theory can be so widely believed to be true, and for
such a long time? We should briefly consider this question before we shift
from the discussion of the nature and evolution of diffusionism as a theory
to the discussion of empirical history, the topic of later chapters. It is
important to understand how this (and every) theory interlocks with
other ideas and responds to social interests.
The Ethnography of Beliefs
In this discussion we will look at ideas as cultural facts: we will look at
them ethnographically, as beliefs held by human beings who belong to
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 31
specific sorts of communities and categories. We will see that a study of
ideas-as-beliefs is quite different from an inquiry into the validity or truth
of ideas, and that the study of ideas-as-beliefs is in some cases the more
important and more basic of the two sorts of inquiry. We will see, in
addition, that scientific beliefs arrange themselves in larger structures,
belief systems, and that belief systems (like diffusionism) have certain
crucial relationships of compatibility to one another and conformality to
the values or interests of the groups of people who hold them to be valid.
Pursuing this ethnographic exploration of the character of ideas-as-beliefs
we will, I think, discover why the theory of diffusionism has had a life
history that is more clearly explained by the life history of European
society, and more particularly European colonialism, than it is by any
intellectual or social process within the scientific community.
Scientific ideas, and empirical ideas in general, can be examined in
two ways. One is comfortable and traditional. It considers ideas in terms
of their communicated meaning. Are they logical; that is, do they reflect
an internally consistent argument? Are they valid in the sense that what
they assert about the real world seems to have evidential support? This
combination of logic, or structure of argument, and evidential basis is the
kind of thing we look for whenever we evaluate scientific ideas — indeed
all ideas that concern empirical reality. The second way of looking at
ideas inquires about the people who believe a given idea, who
communicate it to others as a belief, and about the people who listen and
in turn accept the idea as a belief. The question whether a person believes
in the validity of an idea is not at all the same as the question whether the
idea is in fact a valid one. Questions about belief status are matters of
ethnography: of finding out why beliefs are held by given people; how
beliefs come to be accepted and rejected by these people; how given
beliefs are connected in the minds of these people with other beliefs held
by them; how new candidate beliefs are weighed and accepted or rejected;
and how beliefs as such are connected to other parts of culture, including
values, social organization, class organization, politics, and so on. What
makes this kind of inquiry threatening is the fact that it can provide
independent and reliable evidence that a given group of people holds a
given idea to be true for reasons that have little to do with logic and
evidence, for reasons grounded in culture.
Interestingly, we experience no discomfort and sense no threat when
we read an account written by some anthropologist or cultural geographer
about the beliefs, values, myths, and so on, of some small and obscure
society in some far corner of the earth. Indeed, we expect an
anthropologist to tell us more about the social or cultural reason why the
"natives" hold to these ideas than about the validity of the ideas. In this
32 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
kind of context it is quite normal to have a description of ideas that
distinguishes between the matter of their logical and evidential basis and
the matter of their cultural binding. But when this ethnographic
approach is applied to what are called "Western" ideas, in the realms of
science, history, and the like, the results are disturbing and the enterprise
itself seems somehow improper.
Ideas are, so to speak, surrounded by culture, and we can examine the
surroundings and the way ideas are embedded in their surroundings. This
is the ethnographic study of ideas. Now it happens to be a terminological
convention in the field of anthropology to attach the prefix ethno- to a
word designating a particular field of knowledge, such as medicine,
botany, geography, and the like, when our purpose is to study that body of
knowledge ethnographically. The study of "medicine," for instance, is
different from the study of "ethnomedicine." The latter is an ethno-
graphic field, asking what the medical beliefs are in a given culture, how
these beliefs relate to the rest of that culture, and how to generalize
cross-culturally about medical beliefs in all (or some set) of cultures.
When we put together along with ethnomedicine all the other scientific
fields prefixed by "ethno-," we get, naturally enough, ethnoscience,
meaning the ethnographic study of all sciences; more broadly, all fields of
empirical belief. Ethnohistory is part of that corpus. 36 So, too, is
ethnogeography.
The subject matter of ethnoscience is belief. Ordinarily we look at
beliefs as they are enshrined in empirical statements, generally sentences
that assert some predicate to be true about some subject. The
fundamental, though not the smallest, unit of study in ethnoscience is the
statement of belief and the person or group who makes — and holds
to — this belief statement. For every empirical statement in social science
there is an ethnoscientific question about its belief status and there is a
profoundly different question about its truth status. The two questions do
not forever remain separate, but they come together only at the
conclusion of a long analysis. That analysis explains in the end why so
many diffusionist statements in which historians and geographers firmly
believe are really false.
The study of beliefs is also the study of belief-holding groups. Two
very important points have to be made about belief-holding groups. A
belief-holding group can be a group of any type. However, among the
various types of belief-holding groups, the most fundamentally important
are cultures, classes, and combinations that can be thought of as
ethnoclasses. None of these types is an abstraction, except in the matter
of defining units and boundaries. Cultures are highly variable from place
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 33
to place and person to person, but the analytical unit itself is real and
concrete. Its individual members also have concrete reality. There is no
philosophical conundrum about the cultural whole "versus" its individual
(human) parts in the matters we are discussing now. Thus there is an
ethnoscience of each individual human being and also an ethnoscience of
groups as collectives. Classes are a bit more problematic. However, most
people accept the broad idea that there is a basic division between two
class communities, one, the working class, the other an elite class,
deploying political power and generally accumulating wealth. I will
simply take it as given here that a rough class bifurcation exists in most
societies of this and the preceding century, while conceding that it is not
always possible to tell whether a given group in a given society belongs to
the working (producing) class or to the elite class or to some ambiguous
or uncertain grouping that does not fit comfortably in either of the two.
One such problematic grouping that relates closely to the issues discussed
in this book includes professors and others engaged in studying and
writing about society and the environment. They are not members of the
accumulating class, the elite, but scholars and writers are in most cases
(not all) strongly bound to that class, and for all their intellectual
penetration, discipline, and honesty, they tend to think, say, and write
down ideas that are useful to the elite. This is true most pointedly for ideas
of the sort related to diffusionism.
Culture and class intersect in ethnoclass communities. There is a
crucial use in this book for the concept of an ethnoclass community. I will
argue strongly that the elite groupings of European countries together, in
spite of their cultural (and national) differences, are a basic and
permanent belief-holding group, and that their beliefs form, to a large
extent, a single ethnogeography and ethnoscience. This reflects the fact
that, for the period with which we are mainly concerned, the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries, these elites have had a common set of interests
in relation to the working classes of their own countries and of the
non-European world, and they have together underwritten the produc-
tion of a coherent belief system about the European world, the
non-European world, and the interactions between the two. The most
important proposition in this book, in fact, is the assertion that
diffusionist ideas are at the core of the single belief system generated
under the influence of, and for the interests of, the European elite.
Although it should not be thought that the science and history produced
under the stimulus of this ethnoclass is "biased," nevertheless we will see
that the entire body of ideas concerning geography, history, and social
science are strongly influenced by their ethnoclass patronage. Overall,
34 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
and through the two-century-long flow of ideas, the product is a body of
diffusionist beliefs which persist, and continue to influence social
practice, although they are quite unscientific.
Beliefs assemble themselves into belief systems. The difference is not
exactly a matter of relative complexity. Most simple beliefs are just those
ideas that can be expressed in simple declarative sentences (although
some call for a poem or a painting), and which people do express as
assertions, with more or less confidence as to their veracity. We are
interested in three things about these belief sentences and the acts in
which they are expressed. They are empirical (not purely logical or purely
evaluative). They are expressed as true, or possibly true. And they are
thought of by the belief holders as cognitively whole or discriminable, as,
putting it crudely, "concept," "ideas." What makes such a hard-to-be-
precise-about unit important is the fact that individual humans do not
simply think up such ideas or concepts out of thin air or immediate
perceptual experience. These unit beliefs tend to retain their character as
beliefs through long intervals of time, often generations, and among large
numbers of people. Still more structure is to be found in a belief system
that consists of chains of statements connected together by implication
("because . . ."). This kind of belief system I will call, unoriginally, an
argument. It simply needs to be noted that the chain of statements in an
argument may or may not proceed from simple to complex. A tighter
structure is to be found in those systems called theories. Simple beliefs,
then, are aggregated in various ways into belief structures, belief systems.
Each belief system, in turn, is assembled (psychologically) into various
sorts of higher order systems.
The highest level, comprehending all of the empirical beliefs held by
a given belief-holding unit — including some beliefs that contradict one
another — is the group's (or individual's) ethnoscience as a whole.
Included here are all of the beliefs held to be true, or possibly true, about
the external world, natural and social; beliefs about the self or person; and
beliefs about technique — the self's capability to manipulate and influence
the world. The ethnoscience, in a way, is an encyclopedia.
How does it happen that a new belief is admitted into a belief
system? The question is not where new ideas come from but how they
become validated, that is, given a kind of social license that admits them
to the status of a belief, a belief that is at least accepted as a tenable
hypothesis, a "reasonable idea," and at most accepted as fact. Three quite
distinct judgments — I think also distinct procedures — are involved in this
licensing process. One is a judgment of compatibility. The second is a
judgment of verifiability (the matter of empirical verification). The third
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 35
is a judgment of conformality (or value conformality). Scholarly conceits
to the contrary notwithstanding, verification is the least important of the
three.
All the belief systems held by a given group are in one way or another
interrelated. Some are tightly connected: one theory may seem to follow
directly from another, for example. Normally the relationship is much
looser. But all belief systems have one basic and common relationship
with all other belief systems held by a group. They are compatible. This
means that they can coexist peacefully in the same ethnoscience: they are
not cognitively or culturally dissonant. Although beliefs may occasionally
contradict one another, total lack of relationship is not in principle
possible: directly or indirectly, all beliefs held by a given belief-holding
group (or individual) are somehow linked together, and some judgment of
their compatibility will be made more or less often. Typically, belief
systems reinforce one another: "If P is true, it is reasonable to suppose that
Q is true." Or "If P is true, it follows necessarily that Q is true." What
counts here, because this is an ethnographic scenario, is the fact that the
belief systems are judged to be compatible. The judgment of compatibility
is not simply a definition, an assertion to the effect that when the group
holds two or more beliefs at the same time they are merely labeled
"compatible." Compatibility is the outcome of an important social
process. The process is most transparent when new candidate beliefs are
introduced: when some new hypothesis is proposed within a belief-
holding group and must, as it were, apply for a license. One of the most
crucial tests it must pass is that of compatibility with existing beliefs.
Compatibility is the loosest of all relations among theories and other
beliefs within an ethnoscience. Compatibility is, in a sense, a bridge that
must be built over gaps in the overall body of thought. One sort of gap is
obvious: it is the incompleteness of knowledge. The other sort, less
obvious, is highly significant for the argument of this book. Here, the gap
among theories (and other beliefs) is actually filled, but not by argument.
In ordinary language, "it seems reasonable" to suppose that one theory
lends support to another, or one historical belief is explained by another.
This matter of "reasonableness" bears very close examination, because
"reasonableness" is that form of the relation of compatibility which allows
the most absurdly unreasonable ideas to pass for well-founded scientific
argument.
Broadly speaking, there are two important ways in which gaps are
bridged with "reasonableness" in place of" — and disguising the lack of — an
explicit, defensible argument. One way calls for an insertion of value
statements in place of belief statements; we will explore this device in the
36 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
next section. The other device lies within the belief system itself. It
substitutes, for an explicit argument, an implicit one. To understand how
it works we have to distinguish between explicit and implicit beliefs.
Implicit beliefs are usually matters "too obvious to mention,"
"beneath notice," "obviously true," "taken for granted." They are
ordinary beliefs (and theories) which tend not to surface in discourse.
There is nothing mysterious about most implicit beliefs; they are not
somehow buried in the unconscious, or deliberately hidden from view.
Some beliefs simply tend to be more often thought about consciously and
verbalized than others, for a variety of unsurprising reasons. Those readily
verbalized are explicit beliefs, those not, are implicit beliefs. There is no
hard line of demarcation in a case of this sort, involving informal
communication of belief.
But the demarcation is quite sharp in the case of formal, written and
published, expositions of belief. The implicit beliefs are simply not
written about. If they emerge in print at all, it is in the form of explicitly
stated assumptions, or "axioms." Here, the conclusion that terminates an
implicit argument is exposed to view, but not the argument itself. Rarely
is there any attempt to deceive or obfuscate. The writer merely takes it for
granted that the reader holds the same set of implicit beliefs and is willing
to accept the "reasonableness" of unsupported assumptions. Both share
the same ethnoscience and the same value system.
Implicit beliefs, as we will see, are the weakest link in the diffusionist
world model. Throughout this book we will encounter diffusionist
theories that simply hang in the air, unsupported by argument and
evidence. In fact we will find, for large chunks of the diffusionist world
model, that most of the propositions which would be needed to make
these areas of belief coherent and sound are simply missing. In other words,
relatively few of the beliefs are explicit and grounded. And these few are
not connected together, so the fabric as a whole is incomplete. It seems
complete only to those who are prepared to take a great deal for granted,
who fill in the gaps with implicit beliefs.
Verification is the matter of testing a candidate belief to see whether
it fits the facts. There are various kinds of test and various controversies
about the nature of verification, but such questions need not detain us.
The normal sort of verification involves a search for evidence that would
seem to support or contradict the new hypothesis, the candidate belief.
The process is never complete: everyone, of every culture and community,
has to be satisfied with partial confirmation (and disconfirmation) of
empirical beliefs. For us the important point about verification is this:
verification is never sufficient grounds for converting a hypothesis into an
accepted belief. Nor is it even necessary.
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 37
The judgment of compatibility is more crucial than that of
verifiability, and this holds true among social scientists as it does among
all other groups of natives. Part of verification is itself a matter of judging
compatibility. The words and procedures used in verification, the criteria
on which a test is deemed adequate, and much more besides, are drawn
from the stock of existing beliefs, and the test of a candidate belief is
therefore only partly a matter of direct confrontation with new evidence.
But this is not the main point. In any belief-holding group, a new idea, a
candidate belief, tends to be judged more on the basis of the way it fits
into the existing belief system than on the basis of its directly
apprehended meaning.
The same thing happens in self-conscious scholarship. It has long
been a truism that existing scientific beliefs tend to be defended in the
face of new hypotheses that question them, and the defense is often fierce,
bitter, and dogmatic. (Whitehead once called scientists "the leading
dogmatists. Advance in detail is admitted: fundamental novelty is
barred." 37 ) The truism was popularized by Thomas Kuhn in a dramatic
scenario that he called a theory of scientific revolutions: in essence,
crucial scientific beliefs gain a position of suzereignty, their supporters
gain positions of academic power, and so the beliefs become entrenched
and hold sway for long periods of time, even after evidence against these
beliefs has massively accumulated. Eventually there is a historic break: a
"scientific revolution" which overthrows the existing ruling theory or
paradigm and installs another one, which, in turn, holds sway for a period
of time. 38 But Kuhn's frame of reference (in his Structure of Scientific
Revolutions) was physical science, and we are told very little about the
historic process by which beliefs gain, and retain, hegemony in social
science, including history and cultural geography. In these fields the
process is fundamentally different. For one thing, influential beliefs hold
sway for reasons that reflect much more directly the interests of elite
groups outside of the scholarly field itself, and the replacement of one
theory by another reflects mainly these external interests, not a Kuhn-like
intellectual revolution within the community of scholars itself. Secondly,
in these fields it is much less easy to attack old theories with new
evidence, in part because scientific methods here are usually very inexact
and in part because the collecting of evidence itself is guided and
sometimes determined by existing beliefs. Thus it is that large belief
structures, like diffusionism, persist for generations, untroubled by
"scientific revolutions."
People have a tendency, sometimes slight, sometimes strong, to
believe what they want to believe. Another way of putting this is to say
that beliefs are influenced by values, or that cognition interacts with
38 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
valuation to produce what Tolman elegantly called the "belief-value
matrix." 39 The most straightforward (or at least modest) notion of
"values" finds them to be judgments of preference, assertions of what is
good and bad, right and wrong, liked and disliked, by individuals and
groups. Values, like beliefs, are aggregated into systems. But value systems
are very different from empirical belief systems. The latter, broadly put,
assert things to be true (or untrue) about the world; the former assert
things to be preferable (or not), hence they call for action upon the things
uncovered by belief, and John Dewey was right in describing such
assertions as "agendas. "4° Viewed in this way, the realm of value is not
autonomous and opaque. It is mainly a transition zone between belief and
practice. Values are interests.
Values interact with beliefs in a belief-value matrix. A belief system
and a value system tend to maintain some degree of consistency with each
other during limited periods (except in times of very rapid social change).
This somewhat regular relation between the two systems I will call
conformality, and it works both ways. Statements do not ordinarily become
validated beliefs if they do not conform to the values, and therefore the
interests, of the group. But value judgments indicate preferences for future
action, and a given judgment is likely to be rejected by a group, sooner or
later, if the future action it calls for is flagrantly impractical: if the action
clearly cannot succeed given the nature of the real world as depicted in
the belief system. Obviously, matters are more complex than this and also
less predictable. In any case, the dominant belief system for a group must
in the long run conform to the value system, and when the two fall out of
conformality, one or the other will be forced to change. Since values are
the expression of concrete worldly interests, the belief system will tend, in
ordinary times, to bend more readily to the value system, and to worldly
interests, than vice versa.
The judgment of value conformality is a crucial part of the binding
of belief to culture. The notion that beliefs are culture-bound is of course
a familiar one, but the idea that this proposition applies fully to the belief
systems of scholars is not really accepted except in the most general and
abstract way and therefore in a way that does not usually permit an
analysis of the manner in which a particular scholar's values (or interests)
affect his or her empirical statements. The stronger proposition, that all
new ideas in social science are vetted for their conformality to values, and
more precisely to the value system of the elite of the society — which is not
necessarily the value system of the scholars themselves — and that this
process of validation normally and frequently leads to the acceptance and
persistence of really unscientific ideas, is hardly even considered, even
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 39
though it is normal doctrine in ethnoscience (normal, at least, when
applied to natives other than ourselves).
But there is an even stronger proposition that I will defend in this
book with concrete arguments and evidence: the proposition that our
world'Scale models, and many of our specific theories and factual truisms,
are accepted mainly — and in some cases only — because of their
conformality to the values of the European elites; that this has been the
case since the beginning of the nineteenth century, and is true today.
Many of these demonstrably false beliefs are built into the world model of
diffusionism, and this is so because diffusionism is the central intellectual
doctrine that explains and rationalizes the actions and interests of
European colonialism and neocolonialism.
Conformality is really the crucial part of validation. This is not
ordinarily a matter of the "establishment" suppressing free speech
(although this happens quite frequently). The judgment of conformality
is a complex binding process. At all times the dominant group (a class or
ethnoclass) has a fairly definite set of concrete worldly interests. Some of
these conflict with others, but all tend toward the maintenance of the
elite group's power and position. Because of its power to reward, punish,
and control, this group succeeds in convincing most people, including
most scholars, that its interests are the interests of everyone. These
interests are social, economic, and political agendas, and it is a simple
transformation to insert the word "ought" and turn them into values.
Viewed statically, the interests are always clear, and the values derived
from them cohere into a dominant value system that more or less mirrors
these interests. Hence we have at all times a kind of environment of
values, surrounding and influencing the ongoing validation process in
scholarship.
The way this influence is exerted is very complex in our society
today, but it was quite simple and transparent in the last century, when
the main lineaments of diffusionism and other beliefs related to
colonialism were being sketched in. In those days, not only was it true, as
Marx said, that the ruling ideas are the ideas of the ruling class, but it was
also true that almost nobody but the ruling class, and its subalterns, had
the opportunity to render those ideas effective, in the form of publication,
lecturing at influential schools and universities, and participating in
policy formation and execution. Conformality, in those times and places,
was accomplished largely through the social vetting process by which only
those people who adhered to the dominant value system were in a good
position to tender hypotheses as candidate beliefs. I do not believe that
the process is altogether different today, but it would take us far afield to
40 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
discuss it here at length. We can simply take note of the background of
most professors (very few of whom are the offspring of poor or minority
families), the reward structure in universities and consultantships, and
other elements that jointly produce this result: few professional social
scientists want to propose candidate beliefs which do not conform. This
explains why, in spite of the most rigorous adherence to scientific method
and scholarly canons, our theories remain, to a large degree, conformal.
In sum, validation proceeds by subjecting any candidate belief to
three tests: compatibility, verifiability, and value conformality. Of these
three, perhaps only conformality is essential (and then only in relatively
tranquil times). Verification can be waived on occasion, provided that
the hypothesis is both conformal to interests and nicely compatible with
existing beliefs, be they explicit theories or implicit beliefs emerging as
stated or unstated assumptions. Strong verification is, in any case, pretty
hard to come by in the social sciences (a methodological fact that is often
mistaken for an epistemological verity). In these fields, a judgment of
compatibility is always rendered — if not on the candidate belief then on
the person who proposes it — and it is most unusual for a new hypothesis
or theory to become accepted as a belief if it contradicts the corpus of
accepted beliefs in its field. But it is always the case that society and its
elite need to be supplied with answers to pressing problems confronting
them. So there is an important countercurrent. New hypotheses that
display a touch of the novel and hold some possibility of solving an
already recognized problem are encouraged, indeed rewarded. They must
be compatible but not completely so.
There is simply no way that a scholar, once installed in the profession,
can prevent conformal values from creeping into his or her work. This in
spite of the fact that nearly all are honest, careful, and competent. The
reason why my argument seems, incorrectly, to be an attack on scholarship
is because the problem is almost always seen in connection with explicit
beliefs, and with consciously held attitudes. The fields that study human
society are a weak infusion of explicit theory within a body of belief that
is largely implicit. Scientific method prevents us from accepting the
arguments of an explicit theory merely because we want to do so. But the
main grounding for each such theory is its compatibility with other beliefs
in the system, expressed as a matter of "reasonableness." It is "reasonable"
to accept certain assumptions (reflecting certain implicit beliefs) and not
others. One theory seems "reasonable," or plausible, because it is
compatible with another, accepted theory, although no explicit chain of
connection exists: most links in the chain are buried in the realm of
implicit belief. Finally, it seems "reasonable" to seek verification for a
hypothesis with certain observations and not with others.
HISTORY INSIDE OUT 41
It should be added that the disciplined work of social scientists usually
prevents them from unwittingly validating a hypothesis on grounds of
value conformality. The problem, and it is a severe one, is that, thinking
that our explicit beliefs are not validated by value conformality, we let
value conformality control our implicit beliefs. These then provide a
bridge across gaps between explicit theories, rendering them compatible,
or serve up the assumptions which provide the starting point for new
explicit theories, formal and informal. Scientific and scholarly method
demands rigor only for the explicit theories.
Diffusionism as a Belief System
The discussion thus far has been designed to lay the foundation for an
understanding of three aspects of the diffusionist belief system: its struc-
ture, its binding to certain groups in certain societies, and its evolution,
this last aspect including the important questions of why diffusionism
became prominent and why it has persisted. It would not be much of an
oversimplification to say that diffusionism developed as the belief system
appropriate to one powerful and permanent European interest: colonial-
ism. From 1492 to the present the wealth drawn into Europe — meaning, as
in all of this discussion, Greater Europe — from the non-European world
has been a vital nutriment for the elite classes of Europe: for their
maintenance of status within their societies, and for their progress.
Whether this statement can be generalized to include all classes within
European society, whether, that is, colonialism was an interest of the
nonelite classes of Europe in most times and places, is a contentious issue
which I do not need to address. I am merely asserting that ( 1 ) Europe's elite
depended on colonialism; (2) Europe's elite was tremendously influential
in the evolution of European ideas and more specifically European
scholarship; and (3) Europe's elite held a permanent social interest in the
creation and development of a conformal belief system, a body of thought
that would rationalize, justify, and, most importantly, assist the colonial
enterprise. As that enterprise evolved and changed, so too did the body of
ideas constituting diffusionism.
Most of this book is devoted to a delineation and critique of
diffusionist beliefs, so I do not need to review the nature of the belief
system here. Suffice it to say, the doctrine ranges over all scales of fact,
from world geography and world history to ideas about the qualities of
individual human beings, European and non-European, and descriptions
and explanations of particular local events. The scope of the diffusionist
belief structure encompasses a fair share of European ethnoscience. That
is, a fair share of the licensed belief statements in European ethnoscience
42 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
are used within the diffusionist belief structure, although they are also
used in other structures. (Some examples to be discussed in Chapter 2 are:
beliefs about demographic behavior, about intelligence, about the origins
of civilization, about the fertility of tropical soils.) These statements range
from modest assertions of evidential fact to complex and elaborate
theories, both formal and informal. They enter the diffusionist canon
through all of the licensing procedures for belief acceptance discussed
above. Over time, all of them go through the screening process of
conformality with the value or interest of colonialism, or go through the
indirect screening process that accords them the status of being
compatible with other beliefs which are themselves conformal. Over
time, the belief system accretes new diffusionist beliefs and discards those
that contradict the canon or that have lost their relevance in a changing
world. Since colonialism, in various newer forms such as neocolonialism,
remains an interest of the elite, and since implicit beliefs go unnoticed
and uncriticized, the process of adding, subtracting, and modifying
diffusionist beliefs continues in the present. Were this not the case, the
multitude of beliefs about Eurocentric history which claim our attention
in this book would long since have been discarded.
Diffusionist beliefs at the space-time scale that embraces the whole
world and the whole of history, tend to form a rather tightly structured
theory, as we saw earlier in this chapter. The theory, in brief, describes the
essential processes that take place in an "inner," essentially European,
core sector of the world, describes those that take place in an "outer,"
essentially non-European sector, and describes the modes of interaction
between the two sectors, the most important of which is the
inner-to-outer diffusion of innovative ideas, people, and commodities.
We can describe this world-scale space-time theory as the
"diffusionist world model." It is the colonizer's model of the world.
The obvious question arises: what would we conceive to be a
nondiffusionist world model? This would be a world in which the
processes at work in any one sector are expected also to be at work in the
other sectors. In essence, this model is driven by a concept of equal
capability of human beings — psychological unity — in all cultures and
regions, and from this argument it demands that any spatial inequalities
in matters relating to cultural evolution, and more specifically economic
development, be explained. Stated differently: equality is the normal
condition and inequalities need to be explained. Diffusionism, in
contrast, expects basic inequality between the Inner and the Outer sectors
of the world — and of humanity. The uniformitarian principle is not one
of uniformity; it is the principle of human equality.
At space-time scales smaller than the world, the diffusionist belief
HISTORY INSIDE OUT
system is very diffuse, parts of it hanging together as formally elegant
theories, parts of it floating around as compatible but weakly connected
belief statements. It would take us far beyond the scope of this book to
attempt a description of all of the parts, levels, and subsystems in the
diffusionist model as a whole, ranging upward and downward from the
world model to the level of particular space-time event descriptions. But
we can make a start.
NOTES
1. In this book the word "Europe" refers to the continent of Europe and to
regions dominated by European culture elsewhere, regions like the United States and
Canada.
2. This quick survey of 150 years or so of world history textbooks is, of course,
very schematic and impressionistic. Some further comments may be of use. In
textbooks of the first period, around 1850 (plus or minus a decade or so), the original
home of Man is often stated to be the Garden of Eden, which is located by different
textbook writers in different parts of western Asia. For instance: somewhere east of
Canaan and near Mesopotamia (Robbins, The World Displayed in its History and
Geography, 1832, p. 13); somewhere in the "healthful" mountains between the
Caspian Sea and Kashmir or Tibet (Miiller, The History of the World to 1783, 1842, pp.
27, 43-44); perhaps near the borders of the Mediterranean Sea (Tytler, Universal
history, From the Creation to the beginning of the Eighteenth Century, vol. 1, 1844, p. 17);
in the Vale of Kashmir (Willard, Universal History in Perspective, 1845, p. 34);
somewhere between the Caucasus Mountains and the Himalayas (Keightley, Outlines
of History, 1849); in the Himalayas (Weber, Outlines of Universal History, 1853, p. 6);
in Armenia (Collier, Outlines of General History, 1868). There seems to be a kind of
median location of Eden near the Caucasus Mountains, which was also, by no
coincidence, the supposed place of origin of the "Caucasian race." Noah, of course,
began postdeluvian history on Mt. Ararat, in Armenia (also roughly in the region of
the Caucasus). Noah is supposed to have migrated then to Europe (Whelpley, A
Compound of History, From the Earliest Times, vol. 1, 1844, p. 10), or Mesopotamia
(Robbins, 1832, p. 20), or Palestine, or some other part of the Bible Lands. Noah's
three sons are supposed, then, to have dispersed and to have founded the branches of
mankind — the first great diffusion process. In most textbooks of this period history
tends to move west; some textbooks present the Hegelian notion that history proceeds
inexorably westward, following the sun, with the implication that the United States,
farther west still, will replace Europe as the next center of world civilization.
It was widely believed in this period that nonwhites were not truly and fully
human. One version of this theory, the notion of "polygenesis," claimed that God had
created true humans in the Garden of Eden and other races — or at least the "black
race" — in other places and times. This theory questioned the standard interpretation
of the Old Testament (that everyone is descended from Adam and Eve), so, not
surprisingly, it was not stated as truth in the textbooks I consulted. (I have not,
however, looked at textbooks used in the antebellum South, and the theory of
polygenesis was most popular in slaveholding regions, as an ideological grounding for
the treatment of blacks as things rather than people.) Yet polygenesis was important
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
enough to be mentioned and then rejected — in favor of the view that all humans are
descendants of Adam and Eve — in some textbooks, down to the end of the century
(see, for example, Dew, A Digest of the Laws, Customs, Manners, and Institutions of the
Ancient and Modem Nations, 1853; Fisher, Outlines of Universal History, 1885; Duruy
and Grosvenor, A General History of the World, 1901). But polygenesis was not needed;
the belief that nonwhites are inferior to whites is asserted in one way or another in all
the textbooks I examined. The theory of "degeneration" served just as well as
polygenesis. It was the notion that the descendants of Ham, and perhaps other biblical
peoples, migrated away from the Bible Lands, eastward and southward, and
degenerated from civilization toward savagery, or even lower, as they did so, because
they had not accepted Christ, or because they migrated into inferior environments, or
for some other reason. (See, for instance, Keightley, 1849, 5-6: "the savage is a
degeneration from the civilized life," and Africans are near the apes.) Degeneration
was asserted in some textbooks, but in most the simple fact of white superiority was
stated and left unexplained. The history of the world is, in general, the history of the
white race, or the Semitic and Aryan peoples (see below). For times later than the
Roman era, non-Europe is scarcely discussed, except as a backdrop for discussions of
the Crusades, the building of colonial empires, and the like. (See Harris, The Rise of
Anthropological Theory, 1968, for an excellent discussion of polygenesis and
degeneration.)
Nearly all textbooks of the period around 1900 (give or take a few years) accepted
the newer scientific theories about the age of the earth and the fact of biological
evolution (though not the Darwinian theory of evolution). The biblical account of
human history, however, was retained in many books, although fewer of them
accepted the formerly standard Old Testament chronologies (for instance, that things
began in 4004 B.C.). Books of this period tended to present the so-called "Aryan
theory," a theory derived from philology but expanded into a theory of culture history.
Earlier philologists had identified an "Aryan" or "Indo-European" language family,
and also a "Semitic" family (which many authorities, including textbook writers,
identified with Noah's sons Japheth and Shem, respectively). The white race consists
of these two peoples. One branch of the Aryans supposedly migrated west into Europe
(from the supposed "Aryan hearth," somewhere southwest or northwest of the
Caucasus). These were progressive, energetic people, who founded European
civilization mainly after they had acquired Christianity from the Semites, who
invented the first barbaric civilizations and monotheism but then stagnated into a
dreamy, decadent, unambitious culture and thereafter ceased to advance civilization.
No other culture, apart from these two, had much to do with history. (According to
Freeman, Genera! Sketch of History, 1872, p. 2, history "in the highest and truest sense
is the history of the Aryan nations of Europe"; see also Collier, 1868; Swinton,
Outlines of the World's History, 1874; Gilman, First Steps in General History, 1874;
Anderson, New Manual of General History, 1882; Steele and Steele, A Brief History of
Ancient, Medieval, and Modem Peoples, 1883; Fisher, 1896; Quackenbos, Illustrated
School History of the World, 1 889; Thalheimer, Outline of General History for the Use of
Schools, 1883; Sanderson, History of the Worldfrom the Earliest Time to the Year 1898;
Duruy and Grosvenor, 1901. Ploetz and Tillinghast presented this theory in Epitome
of Ancient, Medieval, and Modern History, first published in 1883, in its many editions
down to 1925 when, in an edition edited by H. E. Barnes, the theory was finally
eliminated.) See Bernal's Black Athena (1987, 1991) for an insightful discussion of the
Aryan theory and related topics in the history of European thought.
Because the Old Testament spoke of agriculture — Cain knew farming and
HISTORY INSIDE OUT
Abraham herded domesticated animals — the history textbooks tended not to address
the problem of where agriculture was invented until very late in the nineteenth
century, the period when science was beginning to deal with this problem. Some
scientists and some textbook writers then began to speculate that, just possibly,
agriculture was as old in continental Europe as it was in western Asia and Egypt.
(From the point of view of science, see Joly, Man Before Metals, 1897.) But the idea
that agriculture originated in the Bible Lands remained dominant although now it
was viewed (by most) as an invention, not an artifact of original creation. The
ethnographic fact that some tribal peoples (for instance, in Australia) did not practice
agriculture was commonly explained, in the textbooks of the earlier nineteenth
century, in terms of the theory of degeneration: their ancestors had somehow lost the
art. Later in the century it became more common to use the diffusionist conception
that agriculture had been invented by west Asian or (conceivably) European peoples,
then diffused outward over the rest of the world, and cultures that did not practice it
in modern times simply had not yet acquired it, either because of their isolation or
because they were too stupid to take it up.
The Orient Express was a famous train that ran between western Europe and
western Asia. Although various routes were used in different eras, the basic line ran
from Constantinople (Istanbul) through Greece to northern Italy or Austria, then on
to France, and (via Ostend) England. Most of the history textbooks write about world
history as though it marched northwestward, rather like the westbound Orient
Express, with stations (so to speak) in Athens, Rome, Paris, and London. (See
Chapter 2 for further discussion of the Orient Express model.)
3. In nineteenth-century world history textbooks, Turkey was given some
attention because of its political involvement with European affairs. World
geography, in contrast to world history, always covered the entire world, and
textbooks as well as the great multivolume descriptive geographies (like Reclus's
classic 19-volume Nouvelle Geographie Universelle, published between 1876 and 1894)
gave considerable attention to Asia, Africa, and Latin America. This should not
mislead us, however. One of the primary functions of geography throughout this
entire period was to teach European children what they needed to know about
non-Europe in order to participate in their countries' imperial and commercial
activities in these regions. See Hudson, "The New Geography and the New
Imperialism: 1870-1918" (1977) and McKay, "Colonialism in the French Geograph-
ical Movement" (1943), on the close relation between geography and colonial
activities.
4. The character of this newer approach can be seen if we look at two
well-known modem university-level texts, one written by W. H. McNeill of the
University of Chicago (A World History, 3rd ed., 1979), the other by J. M. Roberts of
Oxford University (The Hutchinson History of the World, 2d ed., 1987; published in the
United States as The Penguin History of the World). For pre-Christian-era world
history, more than three-quarters of the place-name mentions in both books are places
in Europe and the Middle East (including North Africa); less than one-quarter of the
place-name mentions are places in other parts of the world and only about 1% are in
Africa. For the Christian era to A.D. 1491 there is significant divergence between the
two books. In Roberts's text, European and Middle Eastern places constitute about
85% of place-name mentions. In McNeill's text, European and Middle Eastern places
constitute only 60% of the place names mentioned, a significant departure from the
older tradition although still well out of proportion to this region's size in area and
population. (Sub-Saharan Africa accounts for only 2% of mentions for the period
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
A.D. 1-1491.) In both books, therefore, the region I have been calling "Greater
Europe" has considerably lower salience for pre-1492 history than was typically the
case in older world history textbooks. As to explanation, however, both books retain
much of the traditional perspective. Roberts gives almost no causal role to the cultures
and regions of the world other than Europe and the Middle East (including North
Africa) for any period prior to 1492. McNeill gives considerable weight to East Asia
and some to South Asia for certain historical periods, but almost all of the world
history-making forces emanate from Europe, western Asia, and North Africa for the
period before 1492. (An exception is the Black Death, which, according to McNeill,
swept westward into these regions from farther Asia. On this matter, see also
McNeill's Plagues and Peoples, 1976.) Examples of the Eurocentric explanations
offered by both authors will be given in Chapter 2 of the present book.
It is, however, insufficient to look only at those present-day textbooks that are
clearly identified as "world history" textbooks. Quite frequently university courses
covering the subject of world history use history textbooks that carry titles like "The
History of Western Civilization." (See, for instance, Lerner, et al., Western
Civilizations: Their History and Their Culture, 1988; Kagan, et al, The Western Heritage,
1987; Chambers, et al., The Western Experience, 1987.) If such a textbook neglects the
non- Western world, there can be no complaint that it is misleading: the title clearly
specifies "West" not "World." But if the course is designated as "world history" and
the textbook is designated as "Western history," then we have a problem. The worst
scenario would be one in which world-history teaching continues to be Eurocentric
history in disguise. I do not know of any research which tests the following
hypotheses: (1) Given that, today, historians are sensitive to the need to avoid
Eurocentric bias in the teaching of world history, do some of them simply change the
title to "Western" so that Eurocentrism becomes, then, licit? And (2) is it possible
that there is a trend away from the teaching of "World" history and toward "Western"
(etc.) history and that this trend reflects a reaction (or adjustment) to present-day
demands for nonethnocentrism and "fairness?"
5. A school textbook is truly a key social document, a kind of modern stele. In
the typical case, a book becomes accepted as a high school (or lower-level) textbook
only after it has been reviewed very carefully by the publisher, school boards, and
administrators, all of whom are intensely sensitive to the need to print acceptable
doctrine; they are concerned to make it certain that children will read only those facts
in their textbook which are considered to be acceptable as facts by the
opinion-forming elite of the culture. The resulting textbook is, therefore, less an
ordinary authored book than a vetted social statement of what is considered valid and
acceptable for entry into the mind of the child. For this reason, research on textbooks
(including college textbooks, in which the same process is at work, though more
subtly) is, in fact, ethnographic research. It tells us about the belief system of the
opinion-forming elite of the culture as a whole. Therefore, geography texts in the
United States are really ethnogeography documents. Likewise, history texts are really
ethnohistory documents. They are probably as useful as cultural artifacts as any old
potsherd or inscription. See the final section of this chapter.
6. This argument is given much weight by Eurocentric Marxists, since class
struggle, for Marxists, is the central force in historical evolution.
7. A form of political feudalism is sometimes conceded to have been developed
earlier by the Chinese, but the great majority of European scholars, including most
Marxists, believe that European feudalism was unique in representing a form of society
that was a crucial, essential, stepping stone to modernity. See Chapter 3.
HISTORY INSIDE OUT
8. See Samir Amin's Eurocentrism (1988) for an excellent discussion of this
notion. The word "Eurocentrism" apparently was coined quite recently, to assemble
"European ethnocentrism" into one word. However, I (like Amin) do not think of
Eurocentrism as merely a species of ethnocentrism, as the following paragraphs will
make clear.
9. I use the word "community" to refer to any social unit, of any size. In this
discussion, for the sake of simplicity, the "communities" will be thought of as villages
distributed across a rural landscape. I neglect here the cases in which culture change
results from the combination of an independent invention and a diffusion event. See
my "Two Views of Diffusion" (1977) and "Diffusionism: A Uniformitarian Critique"
(1987a).
10. See Jett, "Further Information on the Geography of the Blowgun and Its
Implications for Transoceanic Contact" (1991); also see Carter, Man and the Land
(1968), and Edmonson, "Neolithic Diffusion Rates" (1961).
11. See, for instance, Eliot Smith, The Diffusion of Culture (1933), Perry, The
Primordial Ocean (1935), and Taylor, Environment and Nation (1945). Eliot Smith
flatly asserts that the ancient diffusion process radiating mainly from Egypt and
Phoenicia "continued for many centuries to play upon the Pacific littoral of America,
where it is responsible for . . . the remarkable Pre-Columbian civilizations" (quoted in
Zwernemann, Culture History and African Anthropology, 1983, p. 15).
12. On these matters, see Harris, The Rise of Anthropological Theory (1968) and
Steward, Theory of Culture Change: The Methodology of Multilinear Evolution (1955).
13. See Koepping, Adolf Bastion and the Psychic Unity of Mankind (1983),
Stocking Race, Culture, and Evolution (1968), and Harris, The Rise of Anthropological
Theory (1968).
14. Often the antidiffusionist camp was labeled the "cultural evolutionist"
camp, and the debate as a whole was labeled "diffusionism versus evolutionism." But,
as I argue here, evolutionists were to some extent diffusionists and diffusionists were
to some extent evolutionists. Moreover, I want to use the term "cultural evolution" in
this book in a much broader and much less controversial sense, as indicating merely
the search for explanation in larger questions of historical and cultural change. A
problem that is "historical" becomes a problem of "cultural evolution" when we ask,
broadly, "why?" Some scholars, of course, are not comfortable with this usage of the
phrase "cultural evolution." For some it carries baggage of economic determinism or
environmental determinism or technological determinism, or it signifies the notion
of an invariant sequence of cultural stages through which all human groups must
pass — but I mean none of that. Most cultural geographers use the phrase "cultural
evolution" just about as I use it here.
15. Both forms are sometimes combined; for instance, in the nineteenth century
northwestern Europe was considered (by northwestern Europeans) to be absolutely
civilized, Africa absolutely uncivilized, and all other areas (of the Eastern
Hemisphere) somewhere in between. These matters are discussed later in this book.
16. Max Weber's notion of "European rationality" is discussed in Chapter 2.
17. The varying conceptions of China, and also India, as semirational or
intermittently rational or rational in some ways but not in others are discussed in
Chapters 2 and 3.
18. The "bogeyman" refers to the Buginese, a Malay people who fought fiercely
against the Europeans and so were stigmatized in this way. The most famous fictional
vampire, Count Dracula, came to England from Outside (a barbarous mountain
region on the frontier of the Turkish empire).
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
19. On the history of the idea of progress in European thought, see, for instance,
G. H. Mead, Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century (1936), Toulmin and
Goodfield, The Discovery of Time (1965), Nisbet, History of the Idea of Progress (1980),
and Bowler, The Invention of Progress (1989). It is true that the idea of progress as the
normal condition was doubted by some thinkers during the nineteenth century (and
especially in opposition to the idea of biological evolution), but this was a minor and
intermittent countercurrent. See Stocking, Race, Culture, and Evolution (1987) and
Bowler, The Invention of Progress (1989).
20. See Huddleston, Origins of the American Indians: European Concepts,
1492-1729 (1967), Williams, The American Indian in Western Legal Thought (1990);
Hulme, Colonial Encounters: Europe and the Native Caribbean 1492-1797 (1992);
Gossett, Race: The History of an Idea in America (1963).
21. At times the notion was advanced that these civilizations had somehow
evolved in antediluvian times and had not been wiped out in the Flood (see, for
example, Keightley, Outlines of History, 1849). Haskel (Chronology and Universal
History, 1848, p. 9) speculates that Noah migrated to China where he or his
descendants founded the Chinese monarchy. "The early improvement and
populousness of the east, seems to favor this idea."
22. From the mid-nineteenth century or perhaps earlier, the literature on the
occult, on ghosts and monsters, and the like, tended to focus on extra-European
origins or homes or sources of the witches, monsters, demons, zombies, walking
mummies, evil spells ("black magic"), artifacts with supernatural powers, and so on,
all of which have a tendency to diffuse into Europe as a kind of counterdiffusion, an
undertow beneath European expansionism. See Brantlinger, Rule of Darkness: British
Literature and Imperialism (1988).
23. See W. A. Lewis, ed., Tropical development, 1880-1913 (1970).
24. See Bowler, The Invention of Progress (1989), Stocking, Victorian
Anthropology (1987), Mandelbaum, History, Man and Reason (1971).
25. Spencer, The Man Versus the State (1969). The complex interplay between
individualistic and holistic theories of historical progress during the nineteenth
century is discussed in G. H. Mead, Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Century
(1936) and Mandelbaum, History, Man and Reason (1971). I try to show in Blaut, The
National Question: Decolonizing the Theory of Nationalism (1987b) how most theories
of nationality and national evolution emerge from one or the other of these
intellectual streams, one essentially Kantian and psychologistic, the other essentially
Romantic and Hegelian.
26. Among them: Malthus, J. S. Mill, T. Macauley, and Thackeray. See
Brantlinger, Rule of Darkness: British Literature and Imperialism, 1830-1914 (1987).
Also see Williams, British Historians and the West Indies (1966) and Said, Orientalism
(1979).
27. See Thapar, Ancient Indian Social History: Some Interpretations (1978) and
"Ideology and the Interpretation of Early Indian History" (1982), and B. Chandra,
"Karl Marx, His Theories of Asian Societies, and Colonial Rule" (1981). We return
to this issue in Chapter 2.
28. See in particular Marx's article, "The British Rule in India" (1979). In later
work, Marx and Engels adopted a much more negative opinion about colonialism,
developing to some extent the idea of colonial underdevelopment: see Blaut, The
National Question: Decolonizing the Theory of Nationalism (1987b) for a discussion.
29. See Chapter 2.
30. See Asad, Anthropology and the Colonial Encounter (1975), and Temu and
Swai, Historians and Africanist History (1981).
HISTORY INSIDE OUT
31. Important examples are Eliot Smith The Diffusion of Culture (1933), Perry,
The Primordial Ocean (1935), Schmidt, The Culture Historical Method of Ethnology
(1939), Griffith Taylor, Environment and Nation (1945). See critiques in Radin, The
Method and Theory of Ethnology (1965), Lowie, The History of Ethnological Theory
(1937), and Harris The Rise of Anthropological Theory (1968).
32. Here I am of courserejecting the view, common among European scholars,
that colonies were relinquished voluntarily. This view has been rejected almost
universally by scholars in the formerly colonial world. It may conceivably have been
true for a few small islands from which profits no longer flowed to the colonizing
power, but even such cases are debatable. It is worth noting that the United States has
not given independence to any of the colonies it held at the close of World War II;
has not even formally conceded the right of full self-determination (including
independence) to Puerto Rico, the Virgin Islands, the Marianas, etc. The other
colonial powers would presumably have taken the same position, had they had the
power to do so in the face of colonial pro-independence forces; in such cases as the
Dutch East Indies, French Indochina, Kenya, Angola, Mozambique, and so on, the
colonizers tried to hold on to their possession by force of arms and failed. My view is
set forth in Blaut, The National Question (1987b), chap. 4, and Blaut and Figueroa,
Aspectos de la cuestion nacional en Puerto Rico (1988).
33. Representative examples include "Operation Bootstrap" in Puerto Rico, the
Colonial Development and Welfare programs in parts of the British Empire, the
increased funding for colonial agriculture and health departments, the establishment
of colonial universities, and so on. These programs, regardless of their underlying
political purposes (often hidden from the technical personnel involved) were, overall,
very impressive.
34. Often this work was a direct continuation of colonial technical work, often
with the same personnel, now "foreign advisor" or "United Nations expert" rather
than "colonial technical officer." ;
35. Thus the Alliance for Progress, the Peace Corps, the elevated funding of
technical and financial agencies of the Organization of American States, and the like.
36. On ethnoscience, see, for example, Gonklin, "Lexicographical Treatment of
Folk Taxonomies" (1969), Frake, "The Ethnographic Study of Cognitive Systems"
(1969), Blaut, "Some Principles of Ethnogeography" (1978), and Spradley and
McCurdy, Anthropology: A Cultural Perspective (1975). In my view, the categories
"history" and "science" cannot be distinguished ontologically, although historiogra-
phy is hardly an exact science.
37. Whitehead, Science and Philosophy (1948), p. 129.
38. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1970). More relevant is Fleck's
Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact (1979).
39. Tolman, "A Psychological Model" (1951).
40. Dewey, "The Logic of Judgements of Practice," in his Essays in Experimental
logic (1916).
CHAPTER 2
The Myth of the
European Miracle
Most European historians believe in some
form of the theory of "the European
miracle." This is the argument that Europe
forged ahead of all other civilizations far
back in history — in prehistoric or ancient or medieval times — and that
this internally generated historical superiority or priority explains world
history and geography after 1492: the modernization of Europe, the rise of
capitalism, the conquest of the world. Most historians do not see anything
miraculous in this process, but the phrase "the European miracle" became
in the 1980s a very popular label for the whole family of theories about
the supposedly unique rise of Europe before 1492. The phrase acquired its
new popularity mainly from a book by Eric L. Jones which appeared in
1981, a book simply entitled The European Miracle. 1
The historians do not agree among themselves on the question why
the miracle occurred: why Europe forged ahead in this perhaps miraculous
way. Is it because Europeans are genetically superior? are culturally
superior? live in a superior environment? Is it because one special,
wonderful thing happened in Europe, or happened to Europeans at a
special moment in history, giving Europeans a decisive advantage over
other societies?
Nor do the historians agree about when the miracle occurred or
began. Did it occur back in the prehistoric age in what some still call the
"Aryan" or "Indo-European" culture? in the late-prehistoric "European
'Iron Age'?" Did it begin with the Greeks? with the Romans? in the early
Middle Ages? in the late Middle Ages? Did it happen continuously
throughout history — a series of miracles — each pushing the Europeans
farther and farther ahead of the rest of humanity?
50
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 51
The historians debate these matters, the questions "why" and
"when," but not the question "whether" — whether a miracle happened at
all. Or, to be more precise, they do not even consider the possibility that
the rise of Europe above other civilizations did not begin until 1492, that it
resulted not from any European superiority of mind, culture, or environ-
ment, but rather from the riches and spoils obtained in the conquest and
colonial exploitation of America and, later, Africa and Asia. This possibil-
ity is not debated at all, nor is it even discussed, although a very few
historians (notably Janet Abu-Lughod, Samir Amin, Andre Gunder
Frank, and Immanuel Wallerstein) have come close to doing so in very
recent years. 2
My task in this chapter and in Chapter 3 ("Before 1492") is to show
that Europeans indeed had no superiority over non-Europeans at any time
prior to 1492: they were not more advanced, not more modern, not more
progressive. Then in Chapter 4 ("After 1492") I will show how colonial
riches brought about the rise of Europe and led to Europe's ultimate
hegemony over the world, showing also that Europe's internal characteris-
tics do not explain 1492 — do not, that is, explain the origins of colonial-
ism.
There seem to be two basic ways to argue that the myth of the
European miracle is wrong, that Europe did not surpass other world
civilizations before 1492. The best way by far is to look at the facts of
history, and demonstrate that the evolutionary processes that were going
on in Europe during and before the Middle Ages were essentially like the
processes taking place elsewhere in the world in terms of rate and direction
of development. I will try to demonstrate precisely this in Chapter 3,
which compares the medieval landscapes of Europe, Africa, and Asia, and
shows how a transition from feudalism and toward capitalism was occur-
ring in many parts of the Eastern Hemisphere just prior to 1492.
But the myth of Europe's unique "rise," its "miracle," is so deeply
embedded in European historical thought that an ordinary argument from
the facts probably would not be persuasive. As we saw in Chapter 1, the
dominant theory has been defended by generations of historians, with
practically no dissenting argument; it is supported as well by many other
ideas which are accepted as unquestioned truth in European culture; and
it fits in with and supports the interests of European countries (and
corporations) in their dealings with the non-European world. For these
reasons, I have decided to use another kind of argument — to demonstrate
the fallacies in the dominant theory — as a sort of ground-laying for the
empirical argument.
In the present chapter I will examine the most common arguments
used by historians today to support the theory of the European miracle, and
52 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
will try to show that they are unconvincing. This task is rendered
somewhat complicated, for a small book like the present one, by the sheer
number of different arguments currently in circulation and the number of
historians who are writing books and articles on the subject of, and in
support of, the theory of the European miracle. How, then, to proceed? I
will advance by stages. First I will present a brief discussion of the ways in
which historians have tended to argue the myth of the European miracle
in recent decades, and I will show how a critical, revisionist point of view
has begun to appear. Next I will lay out, in a kind of menu or classification
or checklist, the most important arguments in support of this myth that are
being put forward today, and I will try to show, for each argument in turn,
how unconvincing it really is. In the third stage, I will summarize the
empirical argument against the "miracle" position in two parts (the topics
of Chapters 3 and 4, respectively): the evidence that Europe was not ahead
of Africa and Asia (at a continental scale of attention) prior to 1492, and
the evidence that colonialism after 1492 accounts for the selective rise of
Europe.
MYTHMAKERS AND CRITICS
The idea that Europe was more advanced and more progressive than all
other civilizations prior to 1492 was the central idea of classical Eurocen-
tric diffusionism, as we saw in Chapter 1. Therefore we do not have to
consider the origins of the European miracle theory: it is our inheritance
from earlier times. However, after World War II the doctrine assumed a
distinctly modern form. First of all, the racist arguments had been
decisively rejected: no longer was it argued that non-Europeans are
genetically inferior to Europeans and that it is this inferiority that explains
why they lagged behind in history. Historians now generally accepted the
idea that European historical advantages reflected facts and happenings of
much earlier times. European superiority was a matter of prior arrival by
Europeans at a stage of development that all other people could aspire to
reach in the future: a matter, therefore, of priority, not innate superiority.
Second, there was a rapid increase in historical scholarship concerning the
non-European world after 1945, grounded in rather pragmatic political
and economic interests, and emanating in part from government- and
foundation-sponsored "foreign area studies programs," but this scholarship
nonetheless added greatly to the knowledge available in Western coun-
tries concerning non-Western history. The new knowledge was fairly
quickly put to rather limited use: some of the wilder fables were discarded
but the basic ideas about the non- Western world did not significantly
change. Third, and most importantly, the postwar world came to embrace
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 53
the crucial new theory of "modernization," the theory that the diffusion of
European ideas, things, and influence would bring about the economic
development of the non- Western world in the coming Age of Develop-
ment. This theory had important effects on history writing.
Modernization as History
The theory of modernization addressed the present and the future but it
was fundamentally historical. Its basic principle was the notion that
whatever had led in the past to European superiority could now be
diffused out into the non-European world and assist that world to more or
less catch up. As we saw in the last chapter, this new doctrine went
through two phases of development, the first in the post-World War II
period of decolonization, the second — an intensification of the diffusion
effort — after the rise of socialist countries in the Third World, and
particularly after the Cuban revolutionary victory in 1959.
A number of historical works appeared in the 1960s as part of this
intellectual process. Their central purpose was to show that the European
pattern of development, including most particularly the development of
capitalism, had been somehow the one, the natural course of human
progress, and many of these volumes quite explicitly drew the ideological
conclusion that the proper, natural course of future development in the
Third World would be to follow this natural European pattern (but not, of
course, slavishly). The most influential of these works was Rostow's 1960
volume, The Stages of Economic Growth: A Nori'Communist Manifesto.
This book was a plain assertion that Europe's past formula for develop-
ment, up to and including capitalism, was the only workable formula for
non-Europe's future development. Rostow married world history to world
development in a single diffusionist argument. 3
But there was a problem. Precisely what had caused the unique rise of
Europe? Now we must return for a moment to the classical diffusionist
period. European historians of the prior century were unanimous (I think)
in their acceptance of the fundamental idea that Europe has been
naturally and uniquely progressive. For most of them the basic force
underlying the process was unquestioned: some drew on their religious
ia'vtY\, others Wut on. metap\vjs\c'a\ (\\k.e Re^eV's evolvvrvg, "spuAt"^,
others appealed to a Smithian or Utilitarian idea of individual human
activity and purpose, and still others invoked the natural environment, or
demographic behavior, or class struggle, or something else, but I think it
likely that all of them held a common conception of an underlying force
of Progress, a basic directional force like the Solar Wind, in relation to
which partial facts (economic, psychological, environmental, and so on)
54 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
were epiphenomenal or merely symptomatic. After World War II,
however, a profoundly different set of basic beliefs became the norm. Now
the problem of explaining the rise of Europe was seen as a total problem.
That is, all of the phenomenon, including its most fundamental
dynamics, required explanation, or, stated differently, had to be put into
an explicit model in which explicit variables or "factors" were identified. .
There were, doubtless, many reasons for this new — or rather newly
popular — approach, among them the maturation of the discipline of
history itself, the loss of faith (in this age of chaos) in the idea of
inevitable progress, the general secularization of European thought, and
the development of social science disciplines.^ But whatever the overall
explanation, what emerged was a set of historical models, some new,
others (like Weberianism) refurbished, that explicitly tried to explain the
"European miracle" in terms of specific causal factors. This was the
signature of the modern form of diffusionist history. The effect of the
modernization perspective was not, by any means, dominant in all of
historical scholarship, but it was so in writings that sought to explain the
larger transformations of European history, and particularly the problem
of explaining the medieval changes that brought about the rise of
capitalism and modernity — the "European miracle." 5 We will review
many of these explanatory propositions later in the present chapter.
The Critique
The modernization approach was quickly challenged because it gave no
real role to non-Europe, past and present, save as an essentially passive
recipient of diffusions from Europe. For the period before 1492, it claimed
that the significant evolutionary processes took place in Greater Europe.
For the period from 1492 to World War II, it claimed that evolutionary
processes continued to effloresce mainly in Europe and that colonialism
brought the fruits of this progress to non-Europe. For the present and the
future, progress for non-Europe (the Third World) would consist of the ■
continued spread of innovations, mainly through mechanisms basically
inherited from the colonial era. These propositions were distinctly unpop-
ular among intellectuals of the Third World, and the rapid development
of Third World scholarship in this postcolonial period led rather quickly
to the emergence of a critical, even rejectionist, body of thought, includ-
ing a new historiography.
The basic thinking went about as follows: For the precolonical era, it
was necessary to resurrect one's own history and find out how it had
contributed to the history of the world. (Colonialist history dismissed
precolonial history for some colonies and distorted it for others. Therefore,
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
as Amilcar Cabral said with deep irony, when the colonies gain their
independence, they re-enter history. 6 ) For the colonial era, the belief that
colonialism itself the was source of all progress was patently untrue and
colonial history had to be rewritten to show how it had led to poverty
rather than to progress. On a world scale, new models had to be developed
to show that colonialism, far from diffusing modernization to non-
European societies, had diffused a mixture of good and bad innovations,
which, for much of the world, had been a process not of development but
of underdevelopment. 7 This body of thought came to be known as
"underdevelopment theory" in Africa and Asia and as "dependency
theory" in Latin America. Out of it came the first serious critique of
Eurocentric historiography.
One can trace the origins of this critique to earlier writings by a small
number of historians, most of them colonial subjects, often writing in
exile. Their main theme was a documentation of the negative effects of
colonialism on a particular place and people. Some of the writers — among
them W. E. B. DuBois, R. Palme Dutt, K. M. Panikkar, M. N. Roy, J. C.
Van Leur, C. L. R. James, George Padmore, and Eric Williams — developed
arguments on colonial processes at a world scale, and on the role of
colonialism in the postmedieval and modem rise of capitalism and Europe.
James showed that Caribbean slaves had played a role in the development
of capitalism not fundamentally different from that of the working class in
Europe. Williams's work ultimately had the strongest impact on Eurocen-
tric history. He showed that the wealth from slavery and the slave
plantation had been the crucial factor in the amassing of capital for the
Industrial Revolution in England. This argument was the first major
demonstration that non-Europe had played a central role in moderniza-
tion itself, and a sizeable literature has grown up among European
historians arguing about, and generally trying to counter, what is now
generally called "the Williams thesis." 8 During and after the period of
decolonization this critical historical literature expanded greatly, and a
large number of scholars began a direct attack on the diffusionist history of
the colonial period.
Much of this work will be discussed in later chapters. Here I want to
make several concrete points about the critique. First of all, a number of
historians from the European world (Bernal, Frank, Wallerstein, and
others) joined Third World historians as central figures in the movement.
Second, while the critique focused a good deal of attention on the
pre- 1492 period, showing that development had taken place in non-
Europe — for instance, Sharma and Habib documented the development
of feudal and postfeudal society in medieval India — for a long time very
little scholarly attention, within this critical tradition, was focused on
56 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
pre- 1492 Europe; the first major work that dealt with this problematic —
from a non-Eurocentric point of view, that is — was Amin's 1974 volume
Accumulation on a World Scale. 9 This is perhaps understandable since most
of the critical historians were themselves from the Third World, not from
Europe, and European history was not often a major interest. Yet it was
anomalous nonetheless. The core of the modernization doctrine in history
was, after all, the argument that Europe had begun to modernize before
other regions and before it established colonial control of other regions.
Thus, to refute the basic thesis one would have to show (as I try to now in
this book) that pre- 1492 Europe was not uniquely progressive. Of course,,
part of this argument consists of demonstrations that other regions were
progressive. But part of it must consist of refutations of the various
"miracle" propositions, those that claim to find in ancient or medieval
Europe some special quality of progressiveness.
There is another, quite curious anomaly in the relative lack of
attention to pre- 1492 Europe by historians in this critical tradition, the
tradition associated with underdevelopment or dependency theory and
the critique of colonialism. This has to do with the curious relation
between Third World scholarship, much of which is Marxist, and the
Marxist scholarship of the European world. European Marxists were
among the main critics of colonialism and among the main contributors to
dependency-underdevelopment theory. Marxist theory also inherited
from former times a strong anticolonial flavor and a profound skepticism
regarding the theories propounded by nineteenth-century mainstream
European historians. 10 Yet, oddly, most European Marxist historians
writing about pre-1492 Europe have tended to argue in favor of the
uniqueness-of-Europe doctrine.
Mainstream European historians have also contributed to the critique
of the central Eurocentric doctrine. This is not an anomaly. Scholars try to
pursue the truth and accept it whether or not it accords with their
ideological or cultural preferences. To some extent they succeed. Thus a
number of European scholars specializing in non-Europe have uncovered
some of the most important evidence against the Eurocentric model of
pre-1492 world history. The work of the Dutch historian J. C. Van Leur in
the 1930s, concerning the economic history of South and Southeast Asia
is a classic example of this antisystemic scholarship. 11 Another example
relates to Chinese history. Half a century ago Duyvendak uncovered truly
crucial facts about China's long-range voyaging in medieval times. Later,
Needham and his associates produced a series of studies about the history
of Chinese science and technology that had a profound impact on the
Eurocentric model and (as we will see) forced Eurocentric historians to
abandon a large piece of their argument concerning the supposed unique-
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
ness of medieval European technology. Other Western scholars, like
Wheatley and Elvin, delving into the empirical history of China with
indifference to ideological questions, have produced other sorts of evi-
dence about China's progressiveness in ancient and medieval times. 12 All
of this damages the miracle theory, although, as we will see later in this
chapter, Eurocentric historians have found ways to repair most of the
damage.
The critique of Eurocentric history is a very large subject, and our
concern in this volume is with just one part of it: the critique of European
miracle theories about the world before 1492, and related theories which
treat early modern world history as though non- Europe, and colonialism,
were merely marginal to evolutionary processes. On these issues the
critique has not progressed very far. I will give a few examples of important
recent contributions, and others will be cited throughout this book. Janet
Abu-Lughod's recent (1989) book, Before European Hegemony: The World
System A.D. 1250-1350, is a seminal study that demonstrates (I think
conclusively) that Europe was not more progressive and not more ad-
vanced than other civilizations in A.D. 1350. Having made this demonstra-
tion, she offers only a tentative and partial explanation for the selective
rise of Europe, and decline of the Orient, after 1350. She suggests that the
divergence took place in the period between 1350 and 1492. (I argue in
this book that the divergence occured only after 1492, with the beginnings
of massive accumulation in the Western Hemisphere, a windfall that did
not accrue to non-European civilizations of the Eastern Hemisphere, and
so gave Europeans their first and decisive advantage over these other
civilizations. See Chapter 4 below.) Samir Amin has argued in various
recent works that Europe was not more advanced than Africa and Asia at
the end of the Middle Ages, but rather was more unstable: because of its
marginal location at the edge of the hemispheric zone of civilization,
medieval class society was less fully seated, less stable, less indurated in
Europe than elsewhere, and so Europe changed toward capitalism more
readily. 13 This argument, although it does not grant any "miracle" to
pre-1492 Europe, nonetheless allows one of the old beliefs to stand: that
Europe was more dynamic than non-Europe during the Middle Ages.
Martin Bernal's new book Black Athena appears to have little connection
to the subject of the present volume, yet his arguments are very closely
connected indeed. Bernal shows that European historians have created a
myth about ancient Europe according to which African and Asian origins
and innovations are written out of history: the goddess Athena was
African. Bernal's work undercuts the still very popular theories about
ancient Europe's supposed uniqueness, and also exposes the ethnocentric
and ideological roots of much of the European scholarship that underlies
58 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
the classical diffusionist model. 14 Edward Said's 1979 volume, Orientalism,
a seminal critique of this process by which Eurocentrism and conservative
ideology has dominated European scholarly writing about the Near East
and Asia, is also important and quite relevant to our argument here. Other
such works will be referred to as we proceed. 15
The Countercritique
In recent years there has been an outpouring of writings that strongly
defend the traditional Eurocentric view, upholding the European miracle
theory in some of its various forms: we discuss many of these writings in
this chapter. In the same stream of writings there are counterattacks
against the more specific theories that question the traditional European '
views about slavery, colonialism, and the like (see Chapter 4), views that
treat these processes and events as marginal in social evolution. And new
theories (or modified forms of old theories) about the precise reason for
the uniqueness of Europe are being put forward and discussed. I have a
hunch that this is a scholarly movement that resonates with the new
political attitudes concerning the Third World. In any event, the decade •]
of the 1980s saw a number of writings of this sort and they appear to \
embody a rather conscious counterattack against the critical history
discussed above. 16
Some of the writers in this new literature are very self-consciously j
engaged in such a counterattack. A number of them are Marxists and are
insisting that the true, the original, the correct Marxist doctrine recognizes
the priority, past and present, of Europe. Robert Brenner, for example,
boldly argues that capitalism was invented by northwestern Europeans,
with no help from others, and therefore (600 years later) we must
acknowledge the continued priority of Europe. A number of other
Marxists, like Perry Anderson and Bill Warren, argue similar positions. 17
Among mainstream historians the . most dramatic event was the ,
appearance in 1981 of Eric L. Jones's The European Miracle. This book is
a remarkable recital of a goodly share of the colonial-era ideas about the ';.
precocity of Europe and the backwardness and irrationality of non- l j
Europe. More remarkable still is the positive reception this book has
received among many scholars, as though most of these old doctrines had
not long since been disproved.
Another movement at present is an attempt to find qualities present
in ancient and medieval European culture, and absent in other cultures,
which were the reasons for European development: qualities in the
European family, the European political system, the European mind, and $
so forth. This movement is actively resurrecting the turn-of-the-century
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 59
views of Max Weber about Europe's supposed "rationality" and the like;
indeed, most (not all) of these scholars can be thought of as Weberians
and many of them define themselves in that way. I will discuss Weber's
views later in this chapter, along with the views of some modern
Weberian scholars, among them Michael Mann and John A. Hall.
In the next section of this chapter I will try to extract the most
important of these newer views proclaiming Europe's pre- 1492 "miracle,"
and I will try to show that these views are mistaken.
THE MYTH
The myth of the European miracle is the doctrine that the rise of Europe
resulted, essentially, from historical forces generated within Europe itself;
that Europe's rise above other civilizations, in terms of level of
: development or rate of development or both, began before the dawn of
the modern era, before 1492; that the post- 1492 modernization of Europe
came about essentially because of the working out of these older internal
forces, not because of the inflowing of wealth and innovations from
non-Europe; and that the post- 1492 history of the non-European
(colonial) world was essentially an outflowing of modernization from
Europe. The core of the myth is the set of arguments about ancient and
medieval Europe that allow the claim to be made, as truth, that Europe in
1492 was more modernized, or was modernizing more rapidly, than the
rest of the world.
This is a myth in the classical sense of the word: a story about the rise
of a culture that is believed widely by the members of that culture. It is
I also a myth in the sense of the word that implies something not true. In
the following discussion I will unravel the fabric of this myth and show
that the strands of belief that compose it are very feeble. 18
The number of distinguishable belief statements that make up this
myth are, I am sure, uncountable. One of the many reasons the myth is so
durable is the fact that the basic generalization, the doctrine of the
miracle, is supported by such a great variety of individual beliefs that
historians of a given era can disprove some subset of these beliefs and yet
the supporters of the myth can merely shift to other beliefs as grounding
for the myth.
A more fundamental problem has to do with the way beliefs are
licensed. Beliefs tend to gain acceptance if they support the myth, and are
either rejected or denied attention if they do not do so. One part of this
problem of belief licensing (and relicensing, delicensing, etc.) poses a
particularly, perhaps uniquely, serious difficulty for efforts to critique the
60 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
miracle theory. Many of the beliefs that support this theory are implicit, not
explicit; that is, they do not enter into the scholarly discourse of historians,
and sometimes they do not enter even into conscious discourse in general.
(Recall the discussion of implicit beliefs in Chapter 1.) Many of these
beliefs we learn as children. Others seem self-evidently "reasonable"
because they accord with deep values of the culture, or with other,
accepted beliefs (historical, practical, religious, and so on). Thus, the
conviction that ancient and medieval Europe was more progressive than
other civilizations is supported by explicit beliefs, but these lie in a matrix
of implicit beliefs — unquestioned and usually unnoticed — about the pro-
gressive Europeans who "were our ancestors." By contrast, the matrix of
implicit beliefs about historical non-Europe includes ideas of alienness,
savagery, cruelty, cannibalism, deceitfulness, stupidity, cupidity, immod-
esty, dirtiness, disease, and so on — a matrix firmly supporting the general
belief that non-Europe cannot have been progressive. Examples of these
sorts of implicit beliefs, both positive and negative, will appear as we
proceed.
One kind of explicit belief about European superiority will not be
discussed here in detail. This is the openly religious statement, grounded in
faith, that a Christian god will naturally raise His people higher than all
others. Although we will refer to this view in various contexts, it is not the
kind of argument that can be analyzed or criticized, because it is grounded
in a faith that cannot be tested empirically; some believe it to be true and
others do not, and that is as far as the matter can be taken. Suffice it to say
at this point: the religious argument was so nearly universally accepted
down to the nineteenth century that other arguments were not seen as
necessary to many European intellectuals. Why, indeed, ask for the reasons
that Christian Europeans are superior when we know that unbelievers will
not go to heaven and, in this world, will not enjoy the grace of God?
Unbelievers will naturally be rendered less intelligent, less fortunate, and
so on. So long as scholars and educated people believed that religion
underlies all things, including science, and that God intervenes to control
human affairs, then it could simply be assumed that Europeans were
superior because that was God's will. It is what you would expect a
Christian god to do for Christians, particularly for those Christians who
worship Him in the right way. By the middle of the nineteenth century,
when Eurocentric diffusionism was at its height, when Europeans hardly
ever doubted their superiority over everyone else, although the explicitly
religious arguments were disappearing from scholarly discourse, they were
still there implicitly, as implicit beliefs. I rather suspect that the great
majority of arguments for the superiority of Europeans were finally
grounded in a religious faith: if the European environment is superior, that
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 61
is because God made it so; if the white race is superior, that is because God
made it so; if Europeans are more rational than everyone else and this has
no explicit explanation, one can infer that it is the work of God; and so on.
I do not know to what extent this kind of implicit appeal to the Deity is
still present but unnoticed in the thinking of contemporary Eurocentric
scholars, but I am certain that it quite often is so. We will from time to time
discuss the ideas of scholars (like Lynn White, Jr. and K. E Werner) who
explicitly connect their views about history with their religious beliefs; in
such thinkers the directionality of the causal arguments will be noted but
not in any sense condemned. Sometimes a scholar makes such arguments
unconsciously and implicitly. The only really disturbing cases are those
that exhibit conscious hypocrisy.
Biology
Basically two sorts of argument have been used to explain the uniqueness,
the superiority, of Europe and Europeans. One sort appeals to some
noncultural force or factor as prime cause; the other finds the prime cause
within culture itself. Setting aside the doctrine of divine intervention
(which one would generally think of as a cause external to human culture,
although the point is theologically rather complicated), two kinds of
noncultural, external causation are common. One appeals to human
biology, the other to the natural environment.
Race
Biological arguments assert, in general, that Europeans are superior,
biologically, to non-Europeans. The classical and typical form of this
argument was biological racism, the idea that Europeans had superior
heredity, and so were born with abilities greater than those displayed by
non-Europeans. Europeans were brighter, better, and bolder than non-
Europeans because of their heredity. Generally the descriptive category
used was not "Europeans" but rather "members of the white race," but the
distinction was not usually very important. Non-Europeans who were
classified as members of the white (so-called) race were nonetheless
believed to be inferior because they belonged to inferior subraces.
Sometimes Europeans themselves were divided into superior and inferior
subraces. Early in the nineteenth century it was widely, though not
dominantly, believed that white people were not even of the same
biological species as people of other races. This theory, "polygenesis,"
claimed to have both biblical and scientific support. 19 Its primary
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
importance was its use as a rationalization for slavery: if Africans were not
truly human, why, enslaving them could not be an evil act. This theory
melted away during the course of the nineteenth century, mainly because
it was offensive to liberal, modern, antislavery thought; what replaced it,
however, was not much of an improvement. This was the doctrine we call
classical racism, the belief that different human races have different
endowments, just as different breeds of domestic animals have such
differences — differences of intelligence, aggressiveness, courage, and the
rest — and these different endowments are matters of biological inheri-
tance. It was then argued, for instance, that Africans were endowed with .
lower intelligence than Europeans, so it was both natural and moral for
Europeans to colonize Africa and make all decisions on behalf of the
Africans who, themselves, either did not have the innate ability to make
these decisions, to govern themselves, or were just sufficiently less
intelligent than the Europeans that a period of European control and
tutelage was necessary while these slow-thinking Africans learned how to
govern themselves. Racism, in a word, had as its main function the
justification of colonialism and all other forms of oppression visited upon
non-Europeans, including minority peoples in countries such as the
United States.
Toward the end of the nineteenth century racism acquired a
pseudoscientific aura of apparent truth. Scientists claimed to have proof
of the differences among races, particularly as to intelligence. Now, also,
they were armed with Mendelian genetics, so it seemed eminently,
reasonable for scientists who were, themselves, racists, now to assert that
they had proof of the truth of the racist theories in which they already
believed. These so-called proofs were unmasked as pseudoscience in a
slow process that continued down to World War II: indeed, even today
there are more than a few so-called "scientific racists." What we need to
notice about scientific racism is that it merely provided a new way of
justifying something that was already almost universally believed to be
true among Europeans. This meant, on the one hand, that it did not do
much to intensify racism — which was in fact reaching a crescendo of
intellectual and scholarly importance around the turn of the century for
social reasons, having to do mainly with the growing importance of
colonialism — and, on the other hand, that the disproving of scientific
racism did not have much to do with the decline of racism's popularity in
the present century. Racism emerged from prescientific roots and survived
so long as it was useful, science or no science.
This is not to deny that scientific racism gave strong impetus to racist;
beliefs in society; in a time when science was acquiring great prestige and
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 63
influence, scientific arguments were indeed important. 20 And scientific
racism helped in some special ways. One important example here has to
do with supposed differences in endowment among the supposed subraces
within the so-called white race. Anti-Semitism, along with anti-Muslim
attitudes relating to colonialism in the Middle East, led to a prolif-
eration of theories about the inferiority of the so-called "Semitic"
subrace. ("Semite," of course, should refer only to someone who speaks
. a Semitic language, such as Hebrew or Arabic.) This racist underpinning
for anti-Semitism, then, became extremely useful for the general
argument about the superiority of Europeans in history over all
non-Europeans. 21 Semitic peoples were acknowledged to belong to the
' white race. Now it could be argued that only Europeans belonged to the
really superior subrace of whites. Semites were inferior. So were the
non-Semitic peoples of western Asia (Persians, Turks, and so forth).
: Indeed, in certain situations it was even argued that scientific racism
- proved the inferiority of southern and eastern Europeans: the northern,
. British and Germanic stock was truly superior to Italians, Slavs, and the
' rest. One famous instance of this sort of argument was the series of
} pseudoscientific testimonials given before the U.S. Congress at the time
it was debating the first important immigration legislation in the 1920s.
Scientists solemnly assured the Congress that southern Europeans were
inferior people, and so should be excluded from free immigration to the
United States in order to maintain the high racial quality of American
stock. 22
Today very few educated Europeans believe that there are genetic,
■ inherited differences among the races as to intelligence or any other
quality that might favor or inhibit social progress. Although a few people
believe in the doctrine of classical racism, most of them are careful to keep
their views to themselves, because today the doctrine is so thoroughly
rejected, and viewed with such repugnance. If this were a book dealing
with the history of ideas, we could go into the explanation for this
j transformation — the decline and fall of classical racism over a period of
no more than two scholarly generations. During the 1920s the belief in
the influence, major or minor, of inherited or racial differences was very
widespread. After 1945 the theory was very rarely defended. Probably the
key factor was Nazism. The Nazis grounded their ideology in this belief,
claiming that the so-called Nordics were a Master Race, that inferior
kinds of Europeans, inferior (so-called) subraces of whites — like the
so-called Semitic race — and all other races as a whole deserved to be ruled
by the Master Race. The Master Race, moreover, had the right to
I eliminate inferior subraces by genocide. Racism therefore was seen, and
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
still is seen, as a component of the horrible ideology of Nazism. It is true
that a small and fanatic group still preaches classical racism, and that a
very small number of academics still proclaim its validity. The need to
fight against the doctrine has not entirely ended. But this no longer is the
important issue when we talk about Eurocentric prejudices, because
another doctrine has largely replaced classical racism and performs much
the same function, rooting its argument not in genetics but in culture.
This doctrine can be thought of as cultural racism. 23
Classical racism was so pervasive, down through the 1920s, that it
probably figured as an explicit or implicit foundation for most arguments
about the superiority of Europeans in history. It is as though the scholars
who asked why Europe had risen and other societies had not done so had
part of their answer at the outset: Europeans began with a genetic
advantage, large or small, and then, throughout later history, they were
always to a greater or lesser extent favored by the influence of their
genetic superiority in matters intellectual, giving them superior
decision-making ability, inventive ability, and so on. Here was an
important reason why it did not, in those times, seem crucial to ask the
question, "Why?" At root, the answer was considered self-evident. Even
moderate racists, such as Max Weber (whose views we examine below),
could therefore assume that European superiority was carried along by a
kind of subtle undertow of genetics, that this made Europeans at all times
slightly more "rational" (Weber's favorite word), and, therefore, slightly
more progressive. It is very interesting that modern scholars retain the
notion of the superiority of European "rationality," a notion derived from
Weber and through him from all of nineteenth-century social thought,
yet they vigorously deny that the source of this "rationality" is racial
superiority. The intellectual contortions they have to go through to
retain the one without the other will claim our interest when we discuss
this matter.
Among the historians whose theories about the "European miracle"
are at present widely supported, only Max Weber uses classical racist
argument in a clear and overt way. But Weber was writing in the late
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, when classical racism was
accepted by the majority of European scholars. Weber's arguments are a
rather mild form of racism. He did indeed write of the "hereditary . . .
hysteria of the Indian," a basis for his argument that Indian religion
prevented Indian development. 24 He considered Africans to be geneti-
cally incapable of factory work. 25 Chinese have a "slowness in reacting to
unusual [intellectual] stimuli," a "credulity" or "docility" that Weber
thinks are wholly or partly hereditary traits. 26 And Europe's greater
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 65
"rationality" has a definite hereditary basis. 27 But the fact remains that
Weber gave much greater weight to nonracial factors. And Weber, for his
time, was only a moderate racist.
Moderate racism is, today, a more serious problem in the world of
scholars than is classical racism, because it is mainly an implicit theory. We
noted that Weber believed in the significance of racial differences, but he
referred to the matter very rarely; yet it must have been an unstated,
perhaps implicit, part of many of his arguments about social evolution in
general and the comparative evolution of Europe and non-Europe in
particular. This was fairly typical of early twentieth-century scholarship,
hence the racism in that scholarship often is too difficult to identify, and
the arguments presented by scholars seem not to be racist when they do not
explicitly mention race as a factor. But more serious still is the surviving
influence of what I call very moderate racism. A great number, perhaps the
majority, of mainstream scholars, in the period, say, of the 1920s, believed
that racial differences were very slight and that the individual human
being's capabilities and potentialities would not be predictable from his or
her race, that race differences only appeared influential on a statistical
basis for large groups: for instance, a slightly higher average "intelligence
quotient" for whites as against blacks. This belief was consistent with
militant opposition to racial discrimination. But it was not much better
than classical racism when applied to questions of social evolution and
comparison between European and non-European history. This is so
because the historical arguments did not need to postulate large racial
differences. If whites, on the average, held a tiny advantage over non-
whites in, let us say, inventiveness, that tiny advantage, working out its
influence over the centuries and millennia, would produce the result that
whites built high civilization and nonwhites did not. In a sense, this very
moderate racism was a more serious problem than ordinary racism, because
it allowed scholars to take liberal positions in opposition to overt racial
discrimination yet continue to believe that whites are superior genetically
to nonwhites within the subject matter of their own fields — anthropology,
geography, history, and so on. It did reduce the significance of race to that
of one "factor" among many, but it did not eliminate racial explanations
• in the matter of Europe's supposed superiority. 28
Probably it is unnecessary to say here that there is no credible
evidence in support of the idea that races differ in genetic inheritance
except in trivial matters like skin color. Even the idea of race is a vague
abstraction and not really useful. For our purposes, the generalization that
counts is this: racial differences explain nothing about culture or cultural
evolution. 2 ^
66 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Demography
Demographic behavior is usually considered the second important
biological factor in explanations for the European miracle. Causality here
is very murky. The specific form of theory with which I am concerned .
claims that Europeans, historically, controlled their population growth,
whereas other peoples did not, so that Europe tended not to suffer
overpopulation, and did not encounter what many historians call the
"Malthusian disasters" that supposedly prevented forward progress in
non-European societies. Malthusianism postulates, in its essence, that
ordinary people do not control their sexual urges and so have more |
offspring than can be fed; a disaster of some sort ensues, with famine, : J
pestilence, or war now reducing the population; and then people again
breed more children than they should, and the cycle renews. Malthus
considered this uncontrollable sexual urge to be general in the human
species, although the educated classes could control themselves to some ;
degree. Modern explanations for the "European miracle" modify this jj
theory in a key respect: they assert that Europeans, historically, have had
a cultural pattern of limiting the number of offspring whereas
non-Europeans lacked this pattern; as a result, European population was )
maintained, throughout history, in rough long-term proportion to
resources, in spite of periodic Malthusian crises, crises which were
important in explaining various facts of European history but were vastly
less significant than the supposed permanent grip of Malthusian
forces — lack of demographic control and perennial overpopulation and
misery — in non-European societies. Moreover, according to these J
historians, whenever technological advance or some other fortunate
circumstance led to a rise in living standards, Europeans, unlike
non-Europeans, did not allow their population to rise and thus eliminate
the fruits of progress. We need to notice that this argument does not really S
center on the biology of reproduction but, again, on rationality: it is
claimed or assumed that Europeans think about the problem of population
and others do not. So demographic arguments for the superiority of
Europe in history always return either to culture or to race: Europeans are
more rational either because they have superior heredity or because they .
have superior culture. If non-Europeans have uncontrollable sexual urges,
if they behave like the beasts in the field, this is either a sign of genetic
inferiority or a cultural quirk. In the arguments most frequently
encountered today, either culture is invoked or the matter is left
ambiguous. Yet there is a paradox. Many historians believe that
demography is an independent causal force in history. This telief is
generally grounded in a quasi-biological argument: ordinary people have •
•
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
only partial success in controlling their sexual urges, and only partial
success (or none at all) in controlling and spacing the birth of children. 30
Many supporters of the miracle myth simply argue, then, that Europeans
have greater, though still partial, success in controlling their behavior
than do non-Europeans. For instance, Eric L. Jones claims that this is
what he calls "the quality of Europeanness":
Europe did not spend the gifts of its environment as rapidly as it got them
in a mere insensate multiplication of the common life. 31
In other words, Europeans do not simply reproduce thoughtlessly, as
non-Europeans do. Jones makes the same point in many different ways; for
instance, he says of Chinese peasants that they preferred "breeding new
people" to improving their economic and political circumstances. 32 John
A. Hall makes a similar point:
The expansion of the European economy did not occur [through expansion
of cultivated acreage], as in late traditional China, because improvements
in output were not eaten up by a massive growth in population. The ratio
between population and [cultivated] acreage in Europe remained favourable
ultimately because of the relative continence of the European family.^
Europeans are sexually "continent." Europeans, therefore, do not suffer
overpopulation.
Another point worthy of notice: the historians have no difficulty
invoking population growth as a positive factor in European history, as an
indication of progress — for instance, the growth of Europe's population in
the eleventh century and thereafter is seen as proof that medieval Europe
was healthily advancing — whereas population growth in non-European
societies is seen as negative, as the working out of Malthusian laws of
"overpopulation." We will encounter examples of this very one-sided form
of argument as we proceed.
There is now abundant evidence that all societies practice population
control. 34 They seem to do so very effectively at the aggregate level:
although individual family groups may or may not succeed in controlling
the incidence of conception — because the methods of birth control are
often rather hit or miss — the society as a whole seems able to encourage
population growth or discourage it quite successfully. 35 It is most unlikely
that population growth takes place when the society would, in the long
run, suffer as a consequence; or, to put the matter more precisely, the
members of a society change their demographic behavior in the space of a
couple of generations when it becomes clear to them, as they observe
68 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
changes around them in the probability of infants surviving to adulthood,
and so on, that such change is desirable. The knowledge that all of this is
indeed the case has only appeared recently. 3( > But this accumulating
evidence really cuts the ground from under all Malthusian theories,
historical and contemporary, European and non-European. The
argument that population growth is an automatic, biological process,
which occurs whether or not there is food enough to feed additional
mouths, is simply wrong. 37
When the evidence began to accumulate that historic European
populations did indeed practice population control, some scholars
decided, appropriately, that the old Malthusian models do not make sense
in Europe: family size was kept small, births were controlled, and so forth,
back in the Middle Ages. This called for rejection of one traditional
theory, the idea that there is a general pattern for all so-called
preindustrial societies (or "traditional societies," or "peasant societies"),
involving high and uncontrolled birth rates, large families, etc., and thus,
inevitably, a Malthusian trend toward overpopulation. Most historians
today seem still to be wedded to the Malthusian theory, and still believe
that medieval social change in Europe was mainly, or at least partly,
produced by Malthusian cycles of overpopulation. 38 But some historians
now reject this perspective: population, in essence, is viewed by them as
a dependent variable, not an independent variable.
But only in Europe. This newer, essentially anti-Malthusian, theory
was rapidly shaped into a new explanation for the European "miracle." It
was simply asserted that European people, historically, controlled their
population, and so, when they accumulated surpluses of food and
commodities and wealth, these were not subsequently dissipated as
population grew out of control and stole away the savings. This pattern,
said these historians, was uniquely European and it was one important
reason why Europeans were able to accumulate wealth and eventually rise
into modernity and capitalism. Non-Europeans, by contrast, continued in
their unmodern, traditional pattern, with overpopulation wiping out all
benefits of forward progress. These Eurocentric historians, in a manner
characteristic of tunnel history, did not notice that new scholarship on
demography, some of it on historical demography — in various non-
European parts of the world, from India to Barbados — was tending to
overturn Malthusian notions as they apply to non-Europe just as readily
as had been the case a decade earlier in European scholarship. 39
We will take up a related matter, theories about the uniqueness of
the European family, at a later point in this chapter. For now, it is enough
to say, simply, that the demographic arguments in support of the
European miracle are utterly unconvincing. This holds true both for the
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 69
theories grounded in the belief in baleful Malthusian forces and for those
which assert that Europeans, uniquely, know how to avoid those forces.
Environment
Environmental determinism, the theory that the natural environment
strongly influences human affairs and human history, is no longer a
popular doctrine, but it is still used quite regularly in explanations for the
European "miracle." The point should, however, be qualified: Environ-
mental determinism, in the form it is used in these arguments today, is a
"determinism" in a limited sense only. It does not claim that the environ-
ment explains everything, or that the environment is the most important
explanatory factor. It is deterministic in the sense that it treats the
environment as a separate, simple cause or "factor" not mediated by
culture: something external to culture and influencing it from the outside.
One finds each Eurocentric historian adding one or a number of environ-
mentalistic arguments or factors to the mix, which, as a whole, explains
the superiority of Europe. Even the historians who want to build their case
mainly on social or political or intellectual foundations nonetheless
manage (I know of very few exceptions) to throw one or more environ-
mentalistic arguments into the stewpot, to give it body or flavor.
Environmentalistic arguments can be stacked into two piles. One
consists of the set of claims about the superior qualities of Europe's
environment and how they help to explain the rise of Europe. The other
pile consists of arguments as to why the nasty environments of other places
have blocked development there. The two sorts of argument are — perhaps
surprisingly — very different in form. Let us begin with the latter.
Two classical environmentalistic theories have been used over and
over again, and still remain in use, to explain the (supposed) nondevelop-
ment of Africa and Asia. The first theory argues that tropical regions are
innately inferior to cooler regions. This theory is used, for the most part, to
dispose of Africa. The second theory argues that peoples in arid regions are
held back from development because aridity necessitates irrigation, and
irrigation along with related features of irrigated river-valley life leads,
again necessarily, to the kind of civilization that is historically stagnant.
This theory disposes of Asian civilizations, along with Egypt. (Most of Asia
is not, in fact, arid.) I will discuss both of these theories, and more briefly
a few other environmentalistic explanations for the backwardness of
Africa and Asia.
Nasty 'Tropical Africa
The idea that tropical climates are nasty, and inhibit the forward march
of civilization, is a very old one in European thought. 40 During the
70 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
nineteenth century this notion was widely used to show why Africans
have (supposedly) remained uncivilized, and must naturally accept
European colonial control; it was one of the core theories of classical
diffusionism. 41 It was routinely built in to theories about the uniqueness
of Europe, the European miracle, although I must add that historians did I
not usually consider the reasons for Africa's nonrise worth bothering
about: the matter was considered self-explanatory, and labors were
devoted to the seemingly more important question why Asia (and North
Africa) did not rise. And the tropical-nastiness theory is still quite
regularly employed in historians' arguments. It is, for instance, crucial to
Jones's argument in The European Miracle. It is also significant in a special
arena: the debates among historians about African slavery, the slave
trade, and the slave plantation system. By contrast, geographers, who in
general know something about the natural environment and have long
grappled with the theories of environmental determinism, do not, today,
take the nasty-tropics theory very seriously. 42
The tropical-nastiness doctrine consists mainly of three distinct
theories. The first concerns itself with the supposed negative effect of a
hot, humid climate on the human mind and body; the second, with the
supposed inferiority of tropical climates for food production; the third,
with the supposed prevalence of disease in tropical regions. Down to the •
1940s, or thereabouts, there was some ambivalence among Europeans as to
the thesis that humans cannot labor as effectively in the humid tropics as ,
in other climates. The majority opinion had been that Africans can labor
under the hot sun — a convenient rationalization for plantation slavery —
but that Europeans cannot do so, although some diffusionist arguments
were built on the idea that tropical conditions induce sloth, indolence,
etc., in everyone, and thus the need for control-at-a-distance from temper-
ate-climate civilizations. Eventually it became clear, from many sources of
evidence including physiological studies, that human bodies of all sorts
can labor as effectively in the tropics as elsewhere if the bodies in question
have had time to adjust to tropical conditions. 43 Although the claim that
people in humid tropical regions cannot think as well as people in
temperate regions — the tropical sun "boils the brain" — was almost univer- :
sally accepted by Europeans in the last century and was incorporated into
some well-known theories about European civilizational superiority put
forward (for instance by Huntington and Markham) in the first half of the
present century, this theory, never grounded in evidence, is now rejected
across the board. Eric L. Jones is one of the few present-day European
historians who is unaware that this theory of "climatic energy" (as it was
called in the old days) has been exploded. Not only does Jones accept it as
vau'ci out he gives it some considerab/e significance:
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 71
Civilizations had long been rising and falling in warm latitudes, although
they appear to have been springing up farther and farther north. Such
explanation as the literature offers for this shift is essentially climatic
(Gilfillan 1920; Lambert 1971). On the one hand it correlates mean
temperature and the output of human energy, and on the other it claims
that in warm regions man was subject to the build-up of endoparasitic
infestation which caused each society there to reach a plateau of attainment
and then stagnate. 44
It should be noted that "the literature" does not support any of this. The
scholarly literature roundly rejects the theory of "climatic energy," which
has not in fact been seriously defended since the 1950s. Climatic
determinism as a whole is almost a dead letter. There has been no
northward "shift" of civilization (ancient civilizations were located from
the equator to 45° latitude). The notion that tropical regions are so
parasite-infested that cultures stagnate is false (it will briefly claim our
attention later). Jones's general belief that hot climates are "debilitating"
§ has little if any scholarly support, and does not in turn support the idea
that Europe's climate led to a European miracle. 45 There simply is no basis
for arguing that midlatitude climates are superior to tropical climates in
terms of psychological or physical effects on human beings.
The fruitfulness of tropical environments was much debated by
; nineteenth-century European scholars. Some argued that tropical regions
are lush and bountiful, but used this proposition not as a basis for asserting
high development potential but rather the contrary: tropical environ-
ments are too bountiful to offer what Arnold Toynbee might have called
a sufficient challenge to humanity, and so progress did not take place
except under colonial guidance. We deal with this thesis later in the
chapter. Our concern now is with the exact opposite thesis, which asserts,
; quite simply, that tropical environments are miserably poor in their
potential for agriculture and it is this that prevents tropical regions from
developing. (The term "tropics," or more properly "humid tropics," refers
to regions with no cold season and with moderate to high rainfall: roughly
1 750 mm. of rain or more per year. Most of sub-Saharan Africa falls within
the humid tropics, as does most of southern and southeastern Asia and
most of Middle and South America.) According to this thesis, little food
| can be produced on a given piece of land in the humid tropics.
Now this thesis — low agricultural productivity of tropical land — is
v hard to defend on the evidence, since population densities in the humid
tropics range from very low (in parts of the Amazon Basin, for instance)
to extraordinarily high (in Java, Bangladesh, El Salvador, Barbados,
\ Rwanda, and many other regions). The argument is grounded, rather, in
a theory about the nature of tropical soils. To put matters in perspective,
72 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
the scientific study of tropical soils is a very young field; few contributions
of any consequence can be dated earlier than World War II if we exclude
highly particular studies about the soils used for plantation crops like
sugar-cane.46 The really crucial information, relevant to the proof or
disproof of the traditional theories, was obtained in research carried out in
a number of experimental centers in the late 1940s and thereafter, and
then slowly disseminated to the world scholarly community. The result is
that some historians (including some current writers about the "miracle")
can still, today, make use of quite fantastic theories about the supposedly
evil nature of tropical soils. Some of these theories were refuted quite
recently; others are now, today, very close to refutation; a few others,
hardly defensible, nonetheless still lie around in the scholarly literature,
unrefuted. A brief, only slightly technical, comment on these theories is
necessary at this point of the discussion.
The old standard theory about tropical soils runs about as follows:
Because of the high heat and abundant rainfall in the humid tropics, these
soils cannot accumulate organic topsoil, since organic matter decomposes
rapidly and is quickly leached out as rainwater seeps downward in the soil.
Tropical soils, therefore, are low in plant nutrients. Also, they are subject
to severe erosion, partly because tropical landforms tend to have high
average slopes, partly because high rainfall means high runoff and
therefore much surface erosion.
These two basic physical propositions, about infertility of the soil and
erosion respectively, were then married to a cultural proposition, in the
following argument. Because of the low fertility and erodibility of tropical
soils, farmers must practice what is called "shifting agriculture." (This is a
farming system in which a field is prepared by clearing a piece of forest with
the use of fire, and then, after one or more years of cultivation, is
abandoned, another field being then cleared in turn and in its turn
abandoned, in a continuous process of shifting fields.) The standard theory
(as it was argued before the 1950s or thereabouts) then makes a series of
sweeping generalizations about the combined effects of infertile, erodible
tropical soils and shifting agriculture. It was claimed that farmers cannot
return to the original piece of land after it has been abandoned and left
fallow for some time, since the soils are too poor to regenerate and since
burning the piece of land permanently damages the soil. Even where the
environment is lush enough so that farmers can return and re-use each
field, the production from each field will be less and less as the cycles of use
and abandonment continue, and the soil will become more and more
infertile until finally it is unusable. All of this implied that peasant
communities would be unable to remain in any one region permanently;
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
that the villages themselves would have to be moved as large expanses of
forest land were used and then abandoned and the people needed to move
elsewhere to find fresh, cultivable lands. The result would be grave indeed:
a very sparse and highly mobile population with little or no chance of
developing large-scale trade, cities, and stable states.
The entire argument was inserted at this point into world history and
world geography. Most of sub-Saharan Africa is tropical. Therefore,
shifting agriculture must be used there and no civilization can develop
there. Or if civilization manages somehow to evolve to one extent or
another, it must sooner or later collapse. (The decline of the classical
lowland Mayan civilization was regularly used as the type example of this
historical outcome; it is still so used by a few scholars.)
This traditional model of tropical soils and shifting agriculture was
gradually softened as more information became available to students of
tropical soils and tropical agriculture. By the 1960s it was generally known
to the specialist community (though not yet to the majority of historians
and social scientists) that shifting agriculture does not damage the soil
under normal — that is, typical and widespread — circumstances. 47 Almost
never do shifting cultivators move their villages because of soil exhaus-
tion. (It became known, also, that shifting cultivation had been wide-
spread for many centuries in Europe, and there it had not apparently done
any damage to the environment.) From this emerged a softer cultural
model: if population densities are low, so that farmers can leave each
abandoned field for the many years required for soil and vegetation
regeneration, then shifting agriculture will remain an equilibrium farming
system, and there will be no long-term deterioration of the environment.
But even this modification would not much alter the historical
judgment about Africa and some other tropical regions: historians might
still believe that any civilization arising in such a tropical area cannot be
very complex under ordinary circumstances, because a low population
density of food producers would not seem to provide the basis for a
substantial complex of urban centers, religious centers, states, and the like.
(As to the lowland Mayan civilization, some scholars continued to claim
that shifting agriculture had destroyed the subsistence base of that civiliza-
tion, while others claimed that the decline and abandonment of cultural
centers like Tikal had been due to other sorts of processes.) In any event,
the prevailingly Malthusian view of peasants led to the general assumption
that population would grow out of control and regions of tropical shifting
agriculture would never rise very high in places like tropical Africa,
anyway.
The model in this form is still current among historians. It is
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
common in the European miracle literature, as the primary environmental
basis for claiming that Africa could not have "risen" in the same way that
Europe did. It is explicit in the work of some non-African Africanist
historians. 48
Evidence is now available to reject this entire theory, the notion
that tropical soils are bad for agriculture and therefore somehow inhibit
human history. First of all, we now know that tropical soils are not
inferior. They are different. Because of the higher rate of chemical and
physical weathering under humid-tropical conditions, soil production
from the underlying rock is much more rapid than is the case in cooler
climates. Therefore, soils maintain their fertility in considerable degree
from the dissolution of minerals, and much less from the accumulation
of organic matter. Erosion tends to be more serious, but regeneration
tends to be more rapid. Tropical soils that have developed on rocks that
are rich in plant-nutrient minerals are exceptionally fertile. Those
developed on rocks that are not nutrient-rich are exceptionally infertile.
There is no basis for comparing tropical and temperate "averages":
neither is better; they are different.
Evidence is also available now to reject the old view of shifting
agriculture. Farmers practice it on poor soils, being careful not to let fires
get out of control. They use a great number of techniques to assist the
natural vegetation to regenerate, and to increase soil fertility in the
cultivated fields, including green and animal manuring. When there is
a land shortage, the shifting rotation is shortened, by the use of various
techniques of intensification such as mounding or terracing, increased
labor applied to such matters as weeding, adoption of different crops and
different varieties, and many more.^ 9 The correlation between shifting
agriculture and low population density is a function of history, not
ecology. In the Americas it reflects in part the post-Columbian
depopulation. (The Amazon Basin, which today may have a farming
population of perhaps one million, probably had seven times that
number in 1492. 50 ) In part also it reflects the often unnoticed fact that
in most regions of the American tropics giant cattle ranches have pushed
farmers off the better land, giving a statistical appearance of low
population density: cattle have replaced people. 51 The same process
occurred in white-settled regions of southern Africa. Elsewhere in
tropical Africa, most farmers practice forms of agriculture that should not
be described as shifting agriculture except in marginal regions, like
mountainsides and semi-arid wastes. 52 Typically, they are sedentary or
semisedentary farming systems, involving such things as semipermanent
yam mounds and tree-crop farming, or irrigated farming, or mixed
farming, or they are systems in which the period of cultivation exceeds
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 75
the period of fallow, and fertility is maintained by many different cultural
practices including the use of green and animal manure. But the most
important generalization is this simple one: where there is soil
<■ degradation, and hunger, and poor farming, it reflects cultural causes
from recent history or colonial history. It does not reflect inherent
limitations of tropical agriculture and it does not reflect technological
ignorance on the part of farmers.
A few variant theories about the low food production potential of
the humid-tropical in general and Africa in particular are invoked by
, some historians. Some claim that Africans were unable even to farm in
Africa's humid-tropical regions until new technology, invented by
non-Africans, diffused into the continent. One form of this argument
! claims that ironworking was brought into Africa a little over 2,000 years
: ago, perhaps by the Romans, and only then were Africans able to tackle
-. the tropical forests. 53 Since shifting agriculture was practiced with stone
■ implements in ancient Europe, and since ironworking appeared in
Africa — possibly after independent invention — around 800 B.C. or
earlier, this theory is invalid.
An even more outlandish theory builds on the fact that some
Southeast Asian crops diffused into East Africa two millennia ago. Some
historians blandly assert that Africans could not farm in the tropical forests
until these tropical crops, domesticated by non- Africans, became available
for planting in the African forests. 54 It has, in fact, been well known for a
long time that Africans domesticated a great number of crops for humid-
" tropical regions, notably many varieties of the yam {Dioscorea spp.) the
prime staple food there. 55 Both of these diffusionist myths seem to be
' connected to an important colonialist belief — now important as an excuse
for apartheid in South Africa. The belief is that advanced African cultures,
with agriculture, trade, and states, expanded southward through the
: continent only very late in history, mainly because of the forbidding
; nature of the tropical part of the continent which held back their
:• southward movement. According to this myth of emptiness (see Chapter
1), they had not arrived in (most of) South Africa when the Europeans
| took over that region, and supporters of white supremacy in South Africa
claim, on this basis, that whites, having arrived first, have political and
. economic rights to own the land of South Africa. 56 In fact, the expansion
of agricultural peoples in Africa occurred thousands of years ago; recent
archaeology has shown that rain forest regions were settled by farmers at
least 3,000 years ago, and whites did not arrive first in South Africa.
Another variant of the myth of tropical nastiness as applied to Africa
: is the notion that rainfall variability in tropical Africa is uniquely and
devastatingly high, such that agriculture could not, in precolonial times,
76 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
be dependably practiced and famines were frequent and widespread. This
then leads into various arguments about African backwardness. For some
historians (among them Philip Curtin) there was a basic tendency toward
mobility of populations and internal slave trading; for others (notoriously
Joseph Miller), there was savagery and cannibalism. 57 These historians
belong to what I will call the "absolutionist" school of Eurocentric
Africanist history, which absolves Europeans of most of the responsibility
for slavery and the problems of modern Africa by finding explanations for
such matters within Africa itself, often in the African environment. The
European miracle historians make regular use of these arguments for
purposes of comparison. It happens to be the case that rainfall variability
is a serious problem in all semi-arid regions, including the Sahel zone
south of the Sahara in Africa and also the Great Plains in the central
United States, the steppes of Russia, and so on. Africa is not unique. The
more humid parts of this continent do not have a peculiar problem of
climatic uncertainty: this is a historians' myth, partly traditional, partly
resurrected after the recent Sahelian-Sudanic famines. The latter did not
reflect drought-proneness of the region. They reflected human problems,
mostly inherited from the colonial period, which became disasters when
ordinary rainfall cycles went through their dry phases. 58
Much the same sort of argument applies to other parts of the tropics.
In southern and southeastern Asia we tend, broadly, to find permanent,
that is, sedentary, agriculture on lands with relatively high fertility, and
shifting agriculture or tree crops on lands with low fertility. The
experience of colonialism during the past two centuries or so has muddled
that picture somewhat, since there have been major population
movements and large population increases in some areas — with conse-
quent distortions of farming systems in reaction to land shortage and
other nonenvironmental pressures. Yet the generalization still holds in
regard to the environment: tropical conditions do not carry the
implication of poor agricultural potential. 5 ^
What of the opposing theory, that the tropics are lush and bountiful?
Down through the middle of the nineteenth century this theory was very
widely accepted, and also this corollary: Since the fruits of the earth are
so easily obtained in tropical climes, humans do not have to exert
themselves to make a living. And so they do not progress. The argument
was then woven into many different theories. Buckle put forward one
such theory. 60 Marx put forward another, rather tersely, in a footnote in
Volume 1 of Capital, asserting without discussion that tropical regions do
not develop toward capitalism because here "Nature is too lavish . . . She
does not impose upon [man] any necessity to develop himself." 61 This
brief comment seems to be the only occasion on which Marx raised the
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
question why humid-tropical regions, including Africa, did not develop as
Europe did.
The bountiful-tropics theory is still used today in some theories that
try to explain the uniqueness of Europe's rise. I suppose that every
European child of our own time has seen some version of the cartoon
showing the native sitting under the coconut tree, waiting patiently for his
food to drop into his hands. This is not merely a relic of oldtime thought
or an implicit theory. Eric L. Jones uses the bountiful-tropics theory in The
European Miracle. (In West Africa "living was easy." 62 ) John A. Hall uses
it. 63 Occasionally it is used by Marxists, faithful to the letter of Marx's
comment quoted above. 64 Probably there is no need to explain why these
bountiful-tropics theories are unacceptable, since this — as we have seen —
is done time and again by scholars who insist that tropical regions are not
bountiful; rather, they are barren and nasty. Neither the one view nor the
other makes sense. And note that both are used toward the same end: to
show that tropical regions have inferior potential in history.
Finally, we come to the theory that tropical environments are so
disease-ridden that historical progress there is slowed, stopped, or
prevented. Some historians develop this argument specifically with
reference to Africa. Some others apply it sweepingly to all tropical
regions: for Eric L. Jones it is a major reason why both Asia and Africa
remained backward by comparison to Europe. Like the tropical-nastiness
theories discussed previously, this one is traditional in European thought,
and this fact is critically important for an understanding of the survival of
the theory down to the present and its use in the European miracle
paradigm.
One of the axioms of classical diffusionism, as we have seen in
Chapter 1, is the idea that diseases and other evil things naturally
counterdiffuse into Europe from non-Europe. It was therefore assumed by
many scholars (including, for instance, Buckle) that non-Europe is both
the source and the natural home of many — and the worst — maladies. 65
That axiomatic belief is still with us: plagues from the Black Death to
AIDS are still assumed — for it is always an assumption, whether or not
reinforced by evidence — to come from the non-European world. 66
This foundation belief was reinforced during the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries by the reports of upper-class European travelers
about the, to them, dirty, disgusting, diseased communities they found
outside of Europe. This was both a class phenomenon and a cultural one:
alien lifeways necessarily seemed to be unhealthy. But the belief gained
powerful reinforcement during the nineteenth century, when the growing
wealth and modernization of (much of) Europe led to a dramatic
improvement in health conditions, grounded in general improvement in
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
living conditions, improved sanitation, and, finally, progress in medicine.
Europe, therefore, seemed to be somehow healthy, non-Europe, somehow
unhealthy. This error is still very widespread. Underdeveloped countries
are poor. With poverty comes ill health. But the ill health is thought,
incorrectly, to somehow stem from the natural environments of these
regions or from the cultures of their inhabitants, not from poverty.
However disease-ridden India, Africa, China, etc., may have been in this
period, Europe itself had been just as disease-ridden a century or so earlier
(a fact known in part from the demographic facts about life expectancy of
ordinary Europeans down to the eighteenth century).
In this same period European colonial territories were expanding,
and it became evident that Europeans living in colonies tended to fall
prey to various kinds of exotic diseases. The most extreme case apparently
was West Africa, which was called in those times "the white man's grave."
Here the insecurity of the quite small coastal settlements — colonial
territories in sub-Saharan Africa did not really expand until very late in
the nineteenth century — combined with the massive effects of the
movement of slaves (many of whom died in these settlements) produced
peculiarly unhealthy conditions, though the Europeans thought the
source of the problem was the innate unhealthfulness of Africa itself.
Most of the important diseases of humans and their domesticated
animals are not peculiarly tropical. Smallpox, typhoid, pneumonia,
diphtheria, measles, bubonic plague, anthrax, and many other diseases are
found across many physical environments, and their severity from place to
place tends to reflect, more than anything else, conditions of human
poverty, crowding, and the like. To some extent this is true even of the
supposedly "tropical diseases," such as malaria (which, in fact, used to
plague extratropical areas, including New York). Some forms of malaria
tend to be associated with stagnant water, and thus with irrigated
agriculture, in a wide range of climates. Other forms, including some of
the most serious ones, are associated with tropical forest conditions, the
mosquito vector often breeding in bromeliad growths on the trees
themselves. It is true that these forms of malaria are especially associated
with shifting cultivation in the humid tropics. But farmers spend
relatively little time in the forest, if indeed there is forest. And they
develop immunities such that malaria does not ravage their communities
(as it does ravage communities of foreigners in their midst: traders,
colonial military personnel, and so on).
The question is: after all such matters have been taken into
consideration, is there, then, a remainder that can be called "the innate
unhealthiness of the tropics?" Probably the answer is no.
Although this generalization is now widely accepted, some historians
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 79
cling tenaciously to the idea that Africa is and always has been a uniquely
disease-ridden place. This is given as one reason for Africa's (supposed)
marginal role in world history, at least in modern world history. (Accord-
ing to William McNeill, disease "more than anything else, is why Africa
remained backward in the development of civilization when compared to
temperate lands." 67 ) In the view of some of the absolutionist historians,
notably Curtin, the disease-ridden character of West and Central Africa in
and after the sixteenth century is a key part of the explanation for the
complementary facts that this region became the source of slaves for the
Atlantic plantation economy and that this region, instead of "rising" with
the growth of the Atlantic economy, instead remained undeveloped. It is
important to put this theory into perspective in terms of the confrontation
mentioned at the beginning of this chapter between traditional European
historians and the Third- Worldist, revisionist school. Traditional scholars
(at least those of the absolutionist school) claim that Africa in the
sixteenth century had a rather small and mobile population, with little
development of complex civilization and state organization, and with
slave raiding and slave trading as important features of its society. Africa
had not risen above this very low level of civilization mainly because of the
prevalence of human and animal diseases — with other environmental
factors of the sort previously discussed being added on as additional factors.
Africa thus quite naturally became the prime source of plantation slaves;
and, also naturally, the slave trade did not fundamentally alter the reality
of African life.
Third World historians tend to dispute all of this. Africa was densely
populated before the slave trade, and the slave trade utterly devastated the
continent, destroying states and civilizations, depopulating vast regions,
and leading, overall, to disastrous underdevelopment. The slave trade
mainly reflected Europe's power relative to coastal African societies in the
seventeenth century and thereafter, in consequence of the immensely
profitable American plantations and — as we discuss in Chapter 4 — the
fact that militarily and commercially powerful West African states were
mostly located some distance from the coast. Disease increased in intensity
because of the devastation caused by the slave trade: depopulation, the
abandonment of large areas formerly cultivated and grazed (now turned to
forest and scrub), wars, economic decline, and so on. One crucial example
of this devastation has to do with the tsetse fly and trypanosomiasis or
African sleeping sickness. Traditional scholars claim that tsetse fly
infestation prevented Africans from developing extensive cattle herding
, in earlier times and in many other ways contributed to historical
stagnation. The response is that trypanosomiasis, like anthrax, is a disease
with many mammalian hosts. Depopulation led to the massive expansion
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
of wastelands, and of wild animal host populations, and thus to the spread
of conditions in which the tsetse fly could flourish. This in turn changed
trypanosomiasis from an endemic disease to which both humans and
cattle had some immunity and exposure, which was kept in check by the
relatively full occupation of lands, into a devastating disease that, since
the end of the last century, has indeed prevented the development of
animal husbandry in some areas of Africa. There is considerable evidence
that the expansion of bushland led to the expansion of tsetse-fly-infested
areas and thus to economic and social misery. 68 Beyond this, there is little
solid evidence either way about the history of health conditions in Africa
and among Africans (not colonial visitors), and there are many reasons to
doubt the inherited diffusionist assumptions and prejudices on this
matter. In any event, one cannot make a case that disease was an
independent force that "blocked" development in sub-Saharan Africa.
Arid, Despotic Asia
Asia is a large place and contains a large variety of environments. There
is, understandably, a very long and varied list of traditional environmen-
talistic arguments, most of them particular to some one part of Asia and
inapplicable to other parts. Back in the early nineteenth century, a pious
form of environmental determinism prevailed in geography, and it
seemed sensible to invoke a single explanation for all of this variety: God
had placed different natural obstacles in the paths of different Asian
peoples — heat in one place, cold in another, drought in a third. Today it
is more common to find, among historians writing about the "European
miracle," not a list of Asia's environmental infirmities but rather a set of
separate comparative judgments, each centered on Europe, and each
referring to a specific period in European history. Europe, or some part of
Europe, at some particular time, was superior to all of Asia in
environmental qualities X and Y and Z. Or, more typically, the
comparison will invoke environmental obstacles for one Asian region,
political obstacles for another, religious obstacles for a third, and so on, in
a very eclectic sort of argument.
For these reasons I will not review all the environmentalistic
theories as to why Asia supposedly remained backward in comparison to
Europe. I will deal with the comparative judgments about climate,
landforms, and so on, one by one, in the following section of this chapter
("Temperate Europe").
There is, however, one very large and coherent theory that is used
today, much as it was in the last century, to deal with Asia as a whole in
one grand and sweeping judgment of inferiority. This theory has a number
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
of variants which are known by various names, among them "the Asiatic
mode of production," "hydraulic society," and "Oriental despotism." The
theory is not usually thought of as an example of environmental determin-
ism, since it seems to start its argument with technology, claiming that
irrigation-based ("hydraulic") societies have certain highly distinctive
characteristics that inhibit historical development. But one of the roots of
this argument is environmental. It is the claim that aridity in Asia made
irrigation necessary. One can properly ask how a theory of this sort can be
applied to parts of Asia that are not at all arid. (It has even been invoked
as an explanation for Stalinism in wet, cold Russia. 69 ) To understand this
contradiction, and to understand accordingly why this theory is untenable
in all its forms and variants, we must look briefly at the history of the
doctrine.
European writers of the past half-millennium have tended to view
Asia as a place where people are inherently unfree and society is
inherently unchanging. It would take us far afield to go into the evolution
of this belief, but by the eighteenth century it had become a significant
part of the emerging doctrine of diffusionism. 70 It was accepted as an
axiomatic truth, rarely questioned, but efforts were made to explain this
inherent "Oriental despotism" (as it came to be called) in terms of
everything from theology to race to environment. The belief seems to
have been applied mainly to the Ottoman Empire, which was in that
period a political and military threat to some European societies and a
commercial threat to others, until the late eighteenth-century expansion
of direct European colonialism in India and Southeast Asia gave the
theory new functions. Not only was the notion of Oriental despotism
useful as a justification and rationalization for colonial expansion, but it
became the basis for colonial legal doctrines that were being fashioned at
that time. In Asia, it was decided, there is no private property in land
because the ruler, despotically, owns everything. Therefore, when we
Europeans depose the ruler, <we own everything. And if we take over a
despotic state, we acquire the rights of despotic rule over a people who
were unfree to begin with. (But European rule, however despotic —
colonies had no democracy — was described as bestowing "freedom.")
The modern form of Oriental despotism was often connected back to
the biblical "Orient." When modern Asian societies were described as
"stagnant," it seemed fair to assert that they basically retained the
character described for them in the Old Testament. (The Old Testament,
we recall, spoke of the existence of great cities, empires, agriculture, etc.)
While it was necessary to explain modern wonders like the Taj Mahal and
great modern Asian states, it was not difficult to view these as relatively
minor advances over the original biblical civilization, and to find
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
secondary explanations for the evident fact that Asian civilizations had
advanced somewhat — but long ago they had ceased to advance, and so
remained essentially biblical and essentially stagnant. 71
I think it likely that the geographical connection between aridity;
and "Orient" comes partly from this source, that is, from the biblical
images of arid regions like Mesopotamia and Egypt. Partly, no doubt, it
comes from the fact that early modern Europe, down through the
mid-eighteenth century, thought mainly of the dry western Asian regions,
the Ottoman realm and the Persian-Inner-Asian region, as "the Orient,""
because the farther Orient, from India to Japan, was still somewhat
remote from European attention. In any event, early nineteenth-century
geographers like the great Karl Ritter were describing one special type of
geographical-cultural system, the type associated with Asian civilizations
of the great river valleys of arid Asia and northeastern Africa, notably the
Nile, the Tigris-Euphrates, the Indus, and smaller valleys of similar
character, and ascribing the traditional Asiatic traits of despotism to
regions of this type. They seem to have extended this model somehow to :
comprehend the river valleys of wetter parts of Asia, through a logical
leap from the idea of irrigated river-valley civilizations in arid regions to
irrigated river-valley civilizations in Asia as a whole.
The general association of Oriental despotism with river-valley
civilizations, from Egypt to China, was commonplace in the nineteenth
century. 72 Marx and Engels, however, took the idea a definitive step
forward by advancing a theory that derived Oriental despotism from
propositions about aridity and irrigation. 73 In the 1850s Marx and Engels
were, for the first time, seriously confronting the question of how their
essential theory of historical evolution could be applied on a world scale.
It needs to be said first that they were probably the most skeptical
European thinkers of their time as regards all of the traditional and (as
they insisted) elitist social theories then in vogue. But their skepticism
had inevitable limits, since they were products of an elitist German
education and since they knew almost nothing about the world outside of
Europe apart from what they learned in the press, and in books and official
papers presenting the colonial point of view with all its prejudices.
Accordingly, Marx and Engels did not seriously question the prevailing
doctrine that the Orient is in some sense despotic and to some degree
historically stagnant and unprogressive. But their skepticism about
European social theory, with its elitist foundations, immunized them from
the usual explanations for Asian despotism and stagnation. Asians were
no less rational than Europeans, and no less willing to struggle against
economic exploitation. This reasoning led Marx and Engels to speculate
that the cause of Asiatic despotism and unprogressiveness lay, not in
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 83
human society, but in the natural environment. In Asia, it appeared,
social evolution had not led to private property ownership: the ruler,
despotically, owned the land, except where it remained as original
communal property. Hence this speculation from Engels:
The absence of property in land is indeed the key to the whole of the East.
Herein lies its political and religious history. But how does it come about
that the Orientals did not arrive at landed property, even in its feudal form?
I think it is mainly due to the climate, taken in connection with the nature
of the soil, especially with the great stretches of desert which extend from
the Sahara straight across Arabia, Persia, India and Tartary up to the
highest Asian plateau. Artificial irrigation is here the first condition of
agriculture. . . . An Oriental government never had more than three
departments: finance (plunder at home), war (plunder at home and
abroad), and public works. ^
This theory was advanced very tentatively by Marx and Engels, and
was modified in later writings; it appears that Engels rejected it altogether
in his late writings. 75 Our interest lies in the fact that the environmental -
istic component remains influential today, even though it is now obvious
that Marx and Engels were mistaken in the notion that Asia is arid. The
theory nonetheless has had an effect on recent Marxist discussions about
the European rise of capitalism and the (supposed) nonrise of capitalism
in Asia. 76 More crucially, it has been woven into the mainstream
European miracle literature in an interesting intellectual sea change.
Max Weber, early in the present century, and Karl Wittfogel, at
midcentury, are probably the key figures in the transformation of this
rather archaic doctrine into a modern environmentalistic argument for
the European miracle. Weber had little to say about the natural
environment per se. Drawing on various scholarly ideas which were in
circulation in turn-of-the-century Europe, including Marxian ideas, he
argued that the development of private property in Europe's Antiquity
and Middle Ages was indeed one of the primary features of social
evolution toward capitalism. He stressed what he saw as a fundamental
difference between the rise of feudal (seigneurial) property, which was
close to, and moving toward, full private property, and a contrasting form
that he associated with the Asian river-valley civilizations (and ancient
Egypt). He saw that social form as being associated closely with the need
to irrigate in such environments, hence associated, inferentially, with the
environment. These latter societies were, he said, despotic and land was
not, in general, passed fully into the hands of officials, but rather lent to
tHem on temporary tenure, on condition of service, as a means of
providing them with rental income, men for military levies, and so on.
84 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Irrigation required collective labor appropriation under despotic rule, for
maintenance of canals and waterworks. In forested lands of Europe, such
despotic rule over peasants had not been needed. 77 Thus in Greece and j
elsewhere in Europe yeoman farmers, individualists, became the signature
of rural society. Cities, instead of being mainly the seat of despotic power,
became truly urban. Thus, in general, there was a peculiarly western
trajectory, toward modern urban and capitalist society.
The crucial factor which made Near Eastern development so different [from
Greek development] was the need for irrigation systems, as a result of which
the cities were closely connected with building canals and constant
regulation of waters and rivers, all of which demanded the existence of a
unified bureaucracy. There was an irreversible character to this develop-
ment, and with it went subjugation of the individual. . . . On the other
hand in Greece . . . the position of the monarchs declined . . . and so began
a development which ended . . . with an army recruited from yeoman
farmers who provided their own arms. Political power necessarily passed to
this class, and therewith started to emerge that purely secular civilization
which characterized Greek society and caused capitalist development in
Greece to differ from that in the Near East. 78
Weber's formulation of the difference between Oriental societies
and Western societies has become one of the fundamental arguments of
the miracle theory as it is put forward in our own time. But Weber did not
put firmly in place one important part of the edifice. This is the matter of
showing why irrigation societies acquired the special characteristics
assigned to them: despotism and stagnation, and, beyond that, lack of
private property, lack of full urban development, and so on. This essential
technical and environmental elaboration of the theory was introduced in
1955 by Karl Wittfogel, in his book Oriental Despotism.
Wittfogel, an ex-Marxist who started his argument with the Marxian
proposition which we have discussed, tried to show that societies grounded
in irrigation, "hydraulic societies" as he called them, are necessarily j
despotic and must necessarily have the kinds of social and political
properties that earlier writers had associated with Oriental despotism. The
same is true of societies that somehow acquire-at-a-distance the character-
istics of hydraulic societies, by diffusion. (Hence, according to Wittfogel,
nonhydraulic Soviet Russia became despotic.) Wittfogel's reasoning was
environmentalistic, in a manner less ignorant of physical geography than
Marx and Weber but nonetheless quite naive. Wittfogel believed that
irrigating a tract of land necessarily, deterministically, increases its produc-
tivity. Some societies will thus choose to adopt irrigated agriculture, and so
the great river valleys of Asia were occupied. But, according to Wittfogel,
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
irrigation requires major public works for the creation and maintenance of
canals, and hence requires a command-type political structure — he says
this was the origin of the state as a political form — which also functions to
control the distribution of water.
Thus hydraulic societies are necessarily despotic. There are a number
of fallacies in this argument, as many scholars have pointed out. Three of
the fallacies concern the environmental proposition, the idea that
irrigation necessarily increases productivity massively, and therefore leads
to the development of complex social stratification, the state, and so on.
First fallacy: irrigation increases productivity substantially only when the
ecologically limiting factor on crop growth is lack of water; but quite
often — in Asia as elsewhere — this is not the case. This means that the
elaboration of great irrigation systems is not a natural response to the
environment. Rather, a small-scale irrigation system in a river-valley can
become enlarged into the great system as an effect, not a cause, of political
and social inequality: pressure to deliver surplus pushes the process,
enlarges the irrigation network, and leads, logically, to ever greater
inequality. In other words, the large irrigation systems are preceded by,
and explained by, existing despotism or social complexity, not by
environmental mandates. (Wittfogel argues in roughly the opposite
direction: the need to irrigate in a dry region leads a society to develop
coercive command structures to manage the irrigation system, and thence
leads to class oppression and the state — and despotic Oriental civiliza-
tion.) The one ecological generalization that makes undoubted sense is
the correlation of land productivity with population size and density,
which is basic to the elaboration of social hierarchies and such things as
religious ceremonial centers and states. But irrigation does not, magically,
make land productive. Some land is highly productive without it. In the
I classical Mesopotamian and Nile cases we do not know whether the
ruling classes forced increases in productivity, and this created the large
irrigation systems, or whether the process worked the other way around.
The second fallacy is the belief that the irrigation of truly dry river valleys
made these valleys immensely productive, overall. Irrigation allowed
agriculture to be practiced in lands otherwise desertic, but water was
always in short supply and we know very little about crop yields. What we
do know is that the really high productivity, and large social entities (in
terms of population size as well as density), were found in wetter regions,
mainly rice-farming regions, where elaborate irrigation systems usually
were unnecessary for agriculture (and sometimes rainwater alone filled
the paddies, as on the lower Irrawaddy plain and part of northern Luzon).
Third fallacy: There is good reason to believe that some of the oldest
civilizations were grounded not in irrigation, but in drainage, an
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
ecological response that does not ordinarily involve large-scale water-
works. Drainage systems seem to have preceded irrigation in the earliest
Mesoamerican civilizations. It is quite possible that the earliest Eastern
Hemisphere irrigation systems, in such places as the Nile, the
Tigris-Euphrates, the Indus, the Wei, the Yellow, the Niger, etc., were
originally drainage systems, opening up swampy riverine regions and
perhaps elaborating polities long before the societies became committed,
to major engineering works and so became "hydraulic." 79
Wittfogel's environmentalistic argument, bringing down to our own
time the old ideas of Marx and Engels about aridity, irrigation, despotism,
and stagnation, juxtaposed with Weber's arguments about the difference
between Oriental despotism and the rest, is seminal for many present-day
European miracle historians, although most of them modify Wittfogel's
theory in important ways. The essential concept is the notion of hydraulic
society, explicitly or implicitly seen as a natural product of arid Asian
river valleys (and the Nile). The way this leads to "miracle" arguments in
the writings of such historians as Eric L. Jones, Michael Mann, and John
Hall deserves a moment's attention.
Eric L. Jones, in The European Miracle, lays stress on what he
conceives to be the fundamental difference between "rainfall-farming"
societies of Europe and irrigating societies of Asia. Wittfogel, he says, was
essentially right. Irrigating societies suffered the "political consequences
of a society with a huge, manipulated peasant mass."
European agricultural society was able to avoid a comparable history of
authoritarianism — a kind of political infantilism — by virtue of an open-
ended productive environment of forest land and rainfall farming. 80
Jones then adds to all of this his theory that farmers who work in warm
standing water become diseased — a fallacy, as we saw above, that confuses
the consequences of poverty with those of ecological settings.
The fairy tale (for it is that) which associates marvelous social
consequences with "rainfall farming" of the European variety will claim
our attention shortly. Here it should simply be noted that all of the '
supposedly dire effects that Jones — like Wittfogel before him — attributes
to irrigation societies are, in point of fact, the normal attributes of ancient
class society and ancient civilization. That is, when these civilizations
emerge, we find, as part of the process, reduction in peasant freedom,
recruiting of masses of people for various purposes, and the like. The
romantic image of free peasants is an image drawn from preserfdom,
prefeudal times. After Franco-Roman colonization European peasants
were as unfree as any peasants of the Asian river valleys or anywhere else.
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 87
And of course rainfall farming, along with forested frontiers, was
characteristic of much of Asia.
John A. Hall, in Powers and Liberties: The Causes and Consequences of
the Rise of the West, wants to distance himself from Wittfogel's "fantasy"
(as he calls it) about the inherently despotic nature of Oriental society.
He then promptly absorbs a good part of Wittfogel's theory into his own
formulation of reasons for the European "miracle." Hall, like most miracle
• theorists, tries to make use of the greatest possible range of traditional
arguments for the miracle, then pushes certain arguments forward as
supposedly the most important ones. He thinks that political forces and
■ Malthusian demographic forces are the most important, although he sees
as a deeper force the Weberian notion of European "rationality." Hall
| does not accept the formula that leads to the generalization that Oriental
, ; states were despotic. No, he says, they were arbitrary, cruel, and unwilling
| or unable to encourage economic development, and they held Oriental
society stagnant (or, much the same thing, going through repetitive
cycles). But they were not despotic. By this he means that Oriental states
were not truly strong, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding. We
will see, shortly, how he says that medieval European states had some sort
of inner strength, an organic quality, with progressive change somehow
teleologically prefigured in their medieval form. So, according to Hall,
there was Oriental despotism but the despots were weak. 81 Hall then
f introduces irrigation as another independent factor.
[In Europe] there was no need for irrigation. It is quite likely that this
encouraged, or at least allowed for, a decentred agricultural civilization
based on individual initiative." 82
Thus a "need" for irrigation in Asia, which must have been an
environmental need. Thus, the old Wittfogelian equation of irrigation
I with despotism (as against "individual initiative"). Then Hall moves to
si other factors on his very long list.
Michael Mann is another contemporary theorist of the "European
miracle," and he too has a long laundry list of factors which, he thinks,
contributed to the miracle. 83 He tends to emphasize the importance of
• ancient Europe's acquisition of political and especially military power.
Mann takes pains to distance himself from Wittfogel, but in the end he
incorporates most of Wittfogel's model — perhaps I should call it the
Marx- Weber- Wittfogel model — into his own theory. Like Marx, Weber,
Wittfogel, Jones, and Hall, he accepts the characterization of ancient
Oriental societies (from Egypt to China) as unfree and unprogressive. But
he points out that the despotisms did not extend to true large-scale
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
politicomilitary power. And the ancient Oriental civilizations, although
they were rooted in irrigation agriculture, also made use of other forms of
resource use in areas adjoining the river valleys. Mainly for these reasons,
Mann claims that Wittfogel "overextended his model." 84 Ancient irrigat-
ing societies were despotic but they were not powerful, and this, for Mann,
is what counts. Mann then rephrases the model and puts it, more or less
entire, into his own theory. The distinction that counts is indeed, he says,
the one between "irrigating" and "rainfall" farming societies. Asian
societies are sweepingly categorized as the former, European societies as
the latter. According to Mann, the fact that European farmers, starting
with the ancient Greeks, used iron plows and farmed unirrigated ("rain-
fall") land, is the one most fundamental reasons that Europe forged ahead
of Asia and North Africa. This was the first great miracle. It put Europe
ahead of all other areas, and Europe has remained ahead ever since.
Here, in brief, is Mann's argument. We start with the ancient Near'
Eastern civilizations, grounded mainly in irrigation. Conceding that
irrigation was the innovation that caused these civilizations to rise in the
first place, Mann argues that the irrigation base somehow "caged," or
confined, the population; this metaphor is meant to convey the idea that
these people are unfree, and also in some sense constrained from further
social progress. (It is a metaphor and not an argument.) Around 1800 B.C.,
says Mann, "the Middle Eastern empires of domination were shaken by
two immense challenges . . . from the north," from Indo-European invad-
ers — this seems to be a version of the discredited "Aryan migrations"
theory — who brought two revolutions with them, based in charioteer
warfare and the use of iron tools and particularly iron plows. The "balance
of power now shifted northward." 85 Mann concedes in passing that these
northern folk did not actually invent chariot warfare and ironworking
(which came perhaps from Anatolia), but he passes without pause (or
logic) to the thesis that the northern peoples, Indo-Europeans, acquired
dominance in politicomilitary terms and in terms of productive power.
From this point forward, Mann contrasts two civilizations, the "irrigating"
ones of the Middle East and the iron-plow-using, rainwater-farming
peoples of the north — Greece and, broadly, Europe. Mainly because the
Europeans were iron-plow-rainfall-farming peoples, they acquired, ini-
tially in Greece, modern civilization, including democracy, classes, private
(more or less) property, science, and a respect for human reason. 86 Why?
The centerpiece of the model is the image of an individual peasant-
farming family which is fundamentally independent. It gets its water from
the skies, not from a despotically managed irrigation system. Iron, says
Mann, is abundant, so the peasant farmer does not depend upon cities and
long-distance trade networks to acquire iron for plows and axes. This
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
independent peasant, a true yeoman farmer (as Weber also had said), is the
prototypical democratic, civilized, energetic, forward-looking European.
None of this makes sense. To begin with, it is geographically absurd
to imagine that the Middle East was a region without plow agriculture, one
basically of irrigated river-valley populations. Plows were used in irrigated
farming. Rainfall-based farming was dominant, not in Egypt and Mesopo-
tamia, but in most of the Levant, Anatolia, Iran, and of course much of
Asia farther east, not to mention Africa. Iron working was not invented by
Europeans and was used as much by non-Europeans as by Europeans. The
same is true of the iron plow, which was as important in early China, for
instance, as in early Europe. 87 (It is an old myth that Indo-European
speakers, Aryans, spread the use of the plow to, and only to, the regions
they settled or conquered.) Workable-grade iron ore deposits are not as
abundant as Mann thinks they are (except in certain special regions, such
as some of the laterite deposits of the humid tropics).
But the silliest part of Mann's thesis is the environmental determin-
ism. We have an image of an arid region fit for nothing but irrigated
farming, which is assumed to be a tether on the progress of civilization. We
have an image of an open region of good soil, forested, in which iron-using
peasant farmers not only produce an unmatched abundance but also
acquire from their ecology a democratic, bold, bright, form of society
I which marches forward then to modernity. Let me add just a word about
each of these images.
Irrigation, in the eyes of many miracle theorists, is somehow unpro-
ductive. Jones, Mann, and others make the assertion that more food is
produced per worker on rain-watered lands. This is not true. In fact,
irrigation was developed to increase food production, whether or not the
source of the process was the aspirations of village people themselves or the
surplus requirements of a political or religious superstructure. When an
irrigated district has reached the point where there is serious land shortage,
that is, late in its social and geographic evolution (along one possible line
of development), the productivity per person declines. This is obvious. It
means, first of all, that farm workers spend more time during the year
producing and have less time for nonfarming activities, including village
cultural life and work on such things as monumental structures. Eventually
this situation may lead to the collapse of the farming system, with
salinization, and so on, and finally, perhaps, starvation. Contrast this now
with nonirrigated agriculture. Normally, there is poorer nutrient status of
soil (irrigation brings dissolved nutrients in the water, and alluvial soils
tend to have good nutrient status). Normally, there is greater moisture
deficit, given the dependence on unpredictable rains. Thus natural fertil-
ity tends to be lower on nonirrigated land, all other things being equal
90 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
(which they often are not). Now it is true that early iron-age farmers,
clearing forested land and making new farms, achieved high production on
this fresh land, but that phenomenon is transitory, and in any case it did
not have much effect in the semi-arid valleys of Greece. Early European
farmers tended in fact to settle on alluvial lands and lowland terraces, and
quite early they were using irrigation and drainage — because it enhanced
labor productivity.
The notion that European agriculture was somehow conducive to
independent living in a way contrasted with Asian agriculture is another
part of this myth. Early European farmers were not to any great extent, as
Mann depicts them, living in isolation from one another, surrounded by
forest. In the cases where they did live this way it was, again, a frontier
phenomenon, in Asia as well as Europe. Farmers mostly lived in social
aggregates, villages, large or small, compact or linear, depending upon
many circumstances. There is no reason to doubt that the upland farming
communities of Asia were quite similar to those in Europe. We return to
this matter later in the chapter when we discuss the myth of the unique
European family. For now I will simply categorize as mythic the idea that
early European agricultural communities were somehow more individual-
istic, more independent-minded, more progressive than were communities
elsewhere.
The most fundamental error made by the nineteenth-century think-
ers and Weber and now mechanically repeated by historians such as Jones,
Hall, and Mann, is to believe, or assume, that one type of environment
produces a particular type of society and the latter then persists down
through history. You simply cannot contrast the very ancient irrigating
civilizations of Asia and North Africa with the later nonirrigating farming
civilizations of Europe — or indeed of Asia — and then suppose that two
contrasting civilizational types have been, thereby, created so as to remain
in place down through history. Culture changes. Farmers move from one
environment to another. In many places farmers practice both irrigation
and nonirrigated agriculture on different soil types when appropriate land
is available to them. 88 Thus the theory which asserts that arid Asian
agricultural civilization produces a stagnant, despotic form of society down
through later times, one which will not develop toward modernity, is
purely a myth.
Temperate Europe
We have already seen how historians constructed a mythic model of
"rainfall-farming" European society, supposing that rainfall brings
benefits not associated with irrigation and that Europeans alone, in their
hemisphere, practice "rainfall farming." Historians like Mann, Jones, and
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 91
Hall carry the argument farther along. Europe's rainfall-based farming,
combined with Europe's supposedly fine and fertile soils, produced an
environmental basis for agricultural production unmatched elsewhere.
Although these historians give a lot of credit to the supposedly uniquely
rational, inventive, European mind, they give much of the credit to
Europe's natural environment.
For example, Michael Mann draws a picture of a steady northwest-
ward movement of European history — what we described in Chapter 1 as
an Orient Express model — which he sees as an essential continuance
down into the Middle Ages of the northwestward trajectory of that
individualistic, creative, bumptious peasant society which, he thinks,
emerged in the Iron Age with the uniquely European marriage of farming,
iron, and rain-watered land. His model of the evolution of Europe's
society (its "miracle") is much more complex than this, but a key part of
that model is the inexorable, steady, historically pregnant geographical
movement — what he calls a northwestward "drift," with a permanent
northwest "leading edge." Eschewing philosophical determinism, he
nonetheless gives the whole process a strongly Hegelian, teleological
flavor. 89 One of two main reasons for this northwestward movement is the
beckoningly fine environment of northwest Europe. And the main reason
why this environment is so fine is its "deeper, wetter, more fertile soils." 90
John Hall, similarly, extols the "northern European clay soils," 91
northwest Europe's "deep and productive clay soils fed by rainfall"
("There was no need for irrigation"). 92 Eric L. Jones, in The European
Miracle, makes much the same claim, if slightly qualified. He writes of
Europe's "open-ended productive environment of forest land and rainfall
farming," 93 of Europe's "High, even rainfall and passable summers." 94
Jones (unlike Mann and Hall) recognizes the fact that Asian land
supports a higher farming population, with the implication that the land
is more productive, but he merely notes that Europe's productive land
comes in smaller, separated regions, and then he gives us one of the myths
■ of Oriental despotism:
The very impracticability of hydraulic agriculture freed a fraction of
European energies for other purposes. The rainfall farmers of Europe might
be fewer in number than the farmers of China and India, but the former
spent less time on all aspects of farmwork than the latter spent on water
control work. 95
The implication, of course, is that European peasant farmers didn't have
to spend much time at farm work in order to satisfy their needs and their
quota of surplus, whereas Asians worked much harder for the same
product. This is plainly absurd unless we abandon historical method and
92 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
try to compare Asian peasants under modern conditions of extreme land
shortage with ancient European frontier conditions or modern European
capitalist farmers. Stated differently, this makes no sense in terms of
actual agricultural technique — irrigation is intended to increase produc-
tivity per worker, and usually does so — and in terms of any model of the
historical European peasant as poor, oppressed, and overburdened.
The "wet soils" of which these historians speak are usually
excessively wet: acidic podzols and gleys that are difficult to work and
infertile until heavily manured. The "high, even rainfall and passable
summers" are in fact a climate so wet that solar energy is often severely
limited, grain crops sometimes cannot do well (recall how important was
the post-1492 introduction of the potato), and soils do not dry out until
late in spring, if at all. I do not want to caricature the situation. It is merely
the case that northwest European soils, across their entire range, of
variability, are not superior to the soils of many other regions. In
ecological terms, the lands of warmer, drier regions that have either good
rainfall regimes or possibilities for irrigation or drainage tend to be rather ,
higher in productivity. My point is more limited. There is nothing about '
Europe's agricultural environment that explains the so-called miracle, or
that might lead one to believe (as the authors I have cited believe) that
European history throughout its course has been favored over Asian
history by the European agricultural environment.
Europe's supposed environmental superiority is by no means limited
to farming. I will close our discussion of environmentalism by briefly
commenting on four other comparative judgments which are routinely
made by present historians of the European "miracle."
First is the classical "capes and bays" argument, familiar to most
European and Anglo-American schoolchildren. Supposedly, Europe's
configuration of peninsulas and bays, and Europe's possession of navigable
rivers, gave this continent a natural basis for communication, trade, and
accessibility denied to other continents. This, then, is supposed to have
had a lot to do with the rise of markets and eventually capitalism in
Europe. 96 Part of the argument, like the emperor's clothes, is transparently
false when looked at directly. For instance, accessibility by sea along the
coasts of the Indian Ocean and much of the South China Sea was
considerably easier in the Middle Ages than it was in Atlantic Europe. (If
monsoonal wind patterns posed a problem in the Indian Ocean, storms
posed a greater problem in the North Atlantic.) Trading cities dotted the
Indian coast, and trading vessels plied up and down this coast, and on to
Indonesia and Arabia, carrying bulk commodities like rice and iron as
well as high-value goods, long before Italian galleys inaugurated a regular
commodity trade between the Mediterranean and the northwest
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
Atlantic. I do not belittle the great seamanship of the Atlantic fishermen,
the Iceland traders, and the Hanseatic League when I note, simply, that
other regions were using the sea as effectively as the Europeans were at
comparable times.
As to rivers, Europe's endowment of navigable rivers is impressive
but not unique. It is not better than India's and China's. Interisland
navigation in insular Southeast Asia was much easier than was navigation
up and down the Rhine, say, or the Danube. Again it is a matter simply
of reducing comparisons to reality. The "capes and bays" errors are
normally followed by another error: the idea that Europe had, in early
times, an advantage over civilizations that had to transport commodities
overland. Many of the "miracle" historians repeat the theory that
overland transport necessarily was much more costly than water transport.
This is in fact a multiplicity of comparisons. When Mann and others
quote the old formulas about draft animals consuming their weight in
fodder over a limited distance (some say this takes place within 100-150
km), they ignore the fact that most draft animals graze or browse along the
way: hence the great Inner- Asian Silk Road and the Sudanic caravans are
easily comprehensible. 97 Canals in China were much more effective than
circuitous coastal shipping routes in Europe. And water transport —
particularly upwind and upriver — may not have had advantages over land
transport 1,000 or so years ago.
Eric L. Jones, in The European Miracle, makes the large claim that
Asia suffered so much more than Europe from natural disasters of all sorts
that Asian development was strongly inhibited by this presumed fact. 98
He carries the argument to the point of claiming that the risk of natural
disaster was so high as to frighten ordinary people into unusual
demographic behavior, to close off trade possibilities, and more. Setting
aside the fact that we have very little historical data on this subject, the
main error is a simple matter of scale. Jones's "Europe" is really West and
Central Europe. This region is roughly the size of the Indian subcontinent
and perhaps one-fourth the size of the settled portion of Asia. So it might
well have one-fourth as many natural disasters, ceteris paribus. It is true
that floods are more serious in regions where people farm river valleys, but
populations make adjustments which keep this one risk small enough so
that it does not affect long-term development, and I suspect that
winter- weather dangers in rural Europe were as great as flood risk in Asia,
on a per capita basis. Hurricanes are no worse than the worst North
Atlantic winter storms. The theory as a whole is unsupported by evidence
and empty of credibility as an argument for the European "miracle."
The miracle historians point repeatedly to Europe's environmental
differentiation, claiming that this leads to a unique potential for
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
interregional trade and thus, again, for capitalism." One need merely
note that Europe does not possess an unusually large range of
environments, and natural products, by comparison with other regions of
comparable size. China, for instance, has roughly the same range of
midlatitude environments plus a tropical south coast.
The last environmentalistic fable to be discussed here is the claim
that Europe's topographic differentiation into many small "core regions,"
separated by mountains and forests, somehow led to a number of
supposedly unique features of ancient and medieval European society,
including even the development of a unique trading system and a unique
system of moderate-sized states and the many benefits supposedly deriving
therefrom. Since this issue ties in with the parts of the "miracle" literature
that concern Europe's supposed uniqueness in economic and political
development, I will postpone discussing the geography of the matter until
later in this chapter. Suffice it to say now that this idea of "cores" is partly
a myth, and insofar as it is valid the same sorts of "cores" can be found in
other continents.
Rationality
We turn now to the theories about Europe's historical superiority or
priority — Europe's "miracle" — which ground themselves, not in biology,
not in environment, but in culture. First I will deal with theories which
start from a conception of the superior "rationality" of Europeans.
"Rationality" in such theories embraces many psychological attributes,
always including inventiveness and innovativeness (or progressiveness),
usually a capacity for abstract thought, and often a certain ability to make
moral or ethical judgments. The issue is not whether such things are or are
not fundamental causes in history; the issue is whether Europeans had
more rationality, or higher rationality, than every other human commu-
nity, and whether this was the principal reason, or at any rate one of the
principal reasons, for the unique rise of Europe. The plain assertion that
Europeans are smarter than everyone else seems to have a certain antique
or Victorian ring to it, but this is deceptive: theories about "Western
rationality" and the like are just as important today as they were for prior
generations of scholars. Sometimes they are difficult to identify as
rationality theories because they display other plumage. An explanation
may focus on, say, technology, arguing that European technological
innovations produced various forward movements in European history;
looked at closely, however, the technological explanation usually
dissolves into a theory about the inventiveness of Europeans, that is, their
rationality. By the same token, an explanation may start with the state, or
free markets, or the family, but usually (not always) it derives such
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
structures from the more basic trait, rationality. Sometimes it works the
other way around. Classical racist theories were rationality theories: to be
white is to be more intelligent. Some (not all) Marxist theories are
rationality theories: the defeat of feudalism released creative energies
which then led to technological innovation, etc. Another complication
is that superior rationality may be posited just for one crucial period and
place, a magic key that started the whole process: Periclean Athens,
Gutenberg's workshop, etc. I will try to sort these matters out by dealing
first with the category "rationality theories" as such, then turning to other
sorts of theories, technological and institutional, some of which are also
rooted in the idea of European rationality.
The Rationality Doctrine
At the beginning of this century most European scholars accepted the
basic proposition that Europeans are more rational than non-Europeans.
This was explained by a great variety of competing theories, biological
racism being perhaps the most prominent, but I suspect that most
Europeans accepted the proposition as indisputably correct regardless of
the explanation. It was simply obvious that European countries had
attained a higher level of wealth and civilization than other countries and
had done so on their own, mainly through invention, innovation, and
creativity. Europeans also now controlled the entire world and this, too,
had to reflect some intellectual and probably also moral superiority. This
was the heyday of the doctrine of classical diffusionism (discussed in
Chapter 1), and few people doubted the doctrine's basic propositions:
Europe develops; non-Europe does not develop or does so more slowly;
Europe's development is based ultimately in some intellectual or spiritual
principle; the normal and natural way for non-Europe to modernize and
progress is by receiving the diffusion of rational European ideas, brought
by European colonial administrators, settlers, planters, missionaries, and
purveyors of commodities.
By this time most European thinkers had come to accept the
doctrine of "the psychic unity of mankind," at least to the extent of
agreeing that all of humanity shares a common ability to progress toward
modernity. This doctrine crystallized into a theory, widely though not
universally accepted in the early part of this century, that can be called
the dualistic-developmental conception of human rationality. The
elementary dualism was a distinction between the mentality of child and
that of adult. The human mind has developed from a prehistoric
condition which was mental childhood. European history is either to be
explained as the fruit of human mental development or has been
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
intimately accompanied by such mental development, in a process that
was fundamentally the same as the psychological development from
childhood to adulthood. Europeans became more rational as history
progressed, just as children acquire rationality in the course of
ontogenetic development. Ancient people had been not merely less
intelligent but also much more governed by emotions and passions than
by intellect, just as is the case with modern children. With some
modification, the same was thought to be the case for modern European
women, who were less intelligent and more governed by emotion than
men, that is, they were less rational than men. But women, too, would
experience mental development, and would eventually be rational
enough to vote, hold public office, etc.
Non-Europeans, within the same theory, were seen as psychically
undeveloped, as more or less childlike. But, given the psychic unity of
mankind, non-Europeans could of course be brought to adulthood, to
rationality, to modernity, through a set of learning experiences, mainly
colonial. (The phrase "colonial tutelage" was a signature of the doctrine,
and this conception is encountered in most history and geography
textbooks of the time.) It was not simply a case of "the natives are like
children." The idea of non-European nonrationality was a definite,
putatively scientific principle, widely accepted: non-Europeans think
somewhat like children, and will be led toward adulthood by Europeans.
Non-Europeans were of course graded. "Savages" were mental children
without qualification. Problematic peoples, like the Indians, Ottomans,
and Chinese, were thought to be childlike in some respects and not in
others. Indeed they were governed by emotion and passion much more
than Europeans. (Colonial revolts were obviously irrational — were
outbursts of childlike emotion.) As far as scientific and abstract
philosophical thinking was concerned, the people of these cultures were
clearly not up to full adult standards, but in some respects, notably in arts
and crafts, they were perhaps gifted adolescents.
So we have a model which has, as its centerpiece, the Rational
Modern Adult European Man. History is his progression to mental
adulthood. He is contrasted with ancient European man; with modern
European children; with modern European women; with modern
non-Europeans. The contrast was often extended, also, to psychotics; in
some schools of they thought were explicitly seen as having a
developmentally arrested mentality and this was indeed used as a
therapeutic principle. 100 What needs to be emphasized is the fact that this
was considered to be a scientific theory. Thus it was valid to exchange
principles across these various dimensions of contrast. For our purposes,
the most important of these principles was the attribution of mental
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
development to European history and the attribution of mental
nondevelopment to non-Europe, past and present; hence Europeans had
naturally acquired a unique rationality.
It would be wrong to reduce to caricature the scholarly theories of a
few generations back, and the model I have just described looks, on the
face of it, like a caricature. Most scholars did not literally believe, say, that
the American Indian was a mental child, or that ontogenetic mental
development exactly recapitulates the mental development of our species.
But the model was a dominant force in European thought in certain
precise ways. The equation of child, ancient, and non-European was
explicitly accepted in nonscholarly discourse (newspapers, Tarzan novels,
and so on). American educational policy toward Indians and other
colonials was explicitly grounded in this model, even if it was a
smoothed-down version of it. A very large number of writings in history,
geography, and all of social science made use of one or another part of the
model. And several very widely accepted theories were really forms of the
same model. Three examples will be helpful.
Most anthropologists accepted the idea that there are two distinct
mental types, one being the so-called "primitive mind," the mind of tribal
peoples just about everywhere (some added: peasants everywhere). The
"primitive mind" was very explicitly described — the most famous descrip-
tion is found in Levy-Bruhl's influential book, How Natives Think — as
being incapable of higher theoretical and abstract ideas, as being emotion
driven, and so on. 101 Some anthropologists opposed this notion (Boas,
Radin, and Mead perhaps most notably 102 ); most anthropologists accepted
it with some qualifications; some accepted it literally. Levy-Bruhl's rather
stark form of the theory had great influence on psychologists and all of
social science. Closely connected to this theory was the notion that there
are "primitive languages," languages incapable of expressing higher theo-
retical and abstract thought. This old notion (which had been used in one
form by William von Humboldt) was joined to the proposition that people
cannot think beyond the limitations of their natural language, and so a
primitive language entails a primitive mind. 103 Beyond that, the old
philological theory about the innate superiority of Indo-European lan-
guages still had many adherents, and this theory extended the notion of
primitive language to most of the non-European languages of the world.
The third example is a broad family of theories in psychology that made
use of the idea that mental development in the individual is homologous
to mental development in the species, and that modem primitive peoples
have the mentality of children and ancients, sometimes extending the
concept to the putative psychological makeup (and limitations) of non-
European peoples in general. In the twentieth century this theory received
98 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
its most influential expression in the psychoanalytic viewpoint of Carl
Jung and his followers. Jung swept broadly across non- Western cultures
(Arabs, Indians, Africans, African-Americans, and others) declaring,
basically, that only modern European man has fully developed an individ-
ual consciousness, an ego, an ability to think, even an ability to conceive
of himself as an individual separate from the external world. Only
European man is rational. 10 4
The doctrine went through some important changes as it became
absorbed into the "modernization" paradigm, the body of ideas which, as
we have seen, came to dominate European social thought in the 1950s
and still does so to some extent today. "Colonial tutelage" gave way to
"diffusion of modernizing innovations." Non-Europeans no longer were
"natives," and no longer were described as "childlike." In place of the
notions of "primitive mind" and "primitive language" came the notion of
traditional mentality. Non-Europeans are "traditional" in two senses: they
lack "modern cognitive abilities," that is, the ability to think theoretically
and scientifically, and they lack "modern attitudes" of the sort that push
a person to achieve higher things, to reject the old, and so on.
This appears still to be the primitive mind, but there is an important
diffetervce. "Traditional mvtvds" ate simply waiting to Vje awakened, to t>e
modernized. The larger picture was one of a vast landscape of traditional
societies, containing people with traditional mentalities, and moderniza-
tion would set the drama into motion. Mentalities would change. Social
structure would change. New ideas and technology would diffuse into the
modernizing societies from the already-modernized European societies,
and so on. Recall that the modernization doctrine is not only a concept of
the spatial spread of European ideas, attitudes, and the like, in the
present-day postcolonial world. It is also a historical concept: moderniza-
tion as history. "Traditional society" and "traditional mentality" came to
be used to describe early Europe, the rise of Europe was now seen as a
modernization process, and the start of that process was a much debated
matter of deciding when Europe began its "takeoff" — its rise from the level
of traditionalism and toward modernity. History is appealed to for the basic
causal principle: Europe modernized, and now non-Europe will follow —
though not slavishly — in its path. We will come back to this point in a
moment. First I want to comment on the main causal principles that are
thought to lead in the other direction. I will show that schools have arisen
in psychology, sociology, and other disciplines that claim to provide t
scientific demonstrations as to what, exactly, is the nature of the "tradi-
tional mind," and the output from these scholars tends, then, to seep back
into history, where it finds its way into the newer writings about the
European miracle.
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 99
In psychology, the important figure is Jean Piaget. His basic theory of
mental development postulated an invariant series of "stages" of develop-
ment through which all children must progress. Piaget was influenced by
LeVy-Bruhl and the primitive mind doctrine, and as late as 1971 he
r thought that
it is quite possible, and this is the impression we have from known
ethnographical work, that in many societies, adult thought does not go
beyond the level of "concrete" operations, and therefore does not reach
that of propositional operations which develop between the ages of twelve
and fifteen in our milieus. 105
"Propositional operations" means, roughly, logic. "Concrete" is childish
prelogical thought, unable to deal with the abstract and the theoretical.
Now Piaget was a great psychologist, but he did not have, or claim to
have, direct knowledge of non-European psychology. He was arguing
i from the traditional dualistic-developmental model that equates the
child and the primitive. (And he was about 30 years out of date as to
ethnography.) But many of his disciples, seeking to connect their theory
with the modernization doctrine, took up the theme and began to carry
out research to find out whether non-Western people (particularly
Africans) do, indeed, have inferior cognitive abilities. It is no
oversimplification to say that virtually all of these studies made the same
mistake and came up with the same, predictable conclusions. They used
I the tests of cognitive ability that Piaget had used with European children
and, scarcely modifying them, administered these tests to non-European
children and adults and found, predictably, that these people do not have
full adult cognitive abilities. By now the error has become well known,
and most present-day Piagetian psychologists do not seem to assert that
! non-Europeans are cognitively childlike. Along with the Piagetian
studies of the 1960s and 1970s, there appeared, in this era, many studies
' carried out by psychologists from other schools of thought (like the Heinz
! Werner school) which took the old primitive-mind doctrine as fact, 106
along with studies carried out by white South African psychologists
j comparing white and black subjects, other Europeans studying other
African populations, and a few Israeli psychologists comparing the
cognitive abilities of Arabs and Jews. With few exceptions, the European
psychologists found the non-European subjects to be deficient in
cognitive ability, and so to be "traditional." 107 In nearly all of these
studies the testing was such that the "natives" didn't really stand a chance
because the tests were European, administered by Europeans or their
. native assistants, in Europeanized settings. The error became so well
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
known that the entire field of "cross-cultural psychology" gained a bad
name — as an apologia for ethnocentrism — until, in the 1980s, it changed
direction. The point is that while most cross-cultural psychologists today,
apparently, deny that non-Europeans are less rational than Europeans,
they established a body of publications that are still used by others to
make the opposite point.
The rationality doctrine was perhaps most influential in those parts
of sociology and economics that were closest to the modernization
doctrine, particularly among academics who were involved in making and
implementing the policies being put into place in the 1950s and 1960s to
develop the underdeveloped countries. As we saw in Chapter 1, this
sphere of ideas was crucial to the politics of modernization for at least
three reasons: First and most basic was the need to validate diffusionism.
Second, development of the sort that involved only the spread of new
ideas and new techniques was much cheaper, in principle, than
development involving massive flows of capital, industrial development,
and the like. And third, along the same lines, development at the level of
ideas, of research, extension, education, and so on, was not threatening; it
would not produce the dangers of revolution and counterrevolution
implicit in efforts to change the relation of power groups, to effectuate
land reform, and the like. For these reasons, scholars were encouraged,
indeed were given lavish grants and were well paid, to produce analyses of
modernization that would lead to workable policies for bringing about
development mainly through an influence at the level of ideas.
Everett Rogers, a rural sociologist; David McClelland, a social
psychologist; and Everett Hagen, an economist, provided highly
influential contributions that I will describe briefly and with some
caricature. Rogers was one of the leaders in a movement to sort out
peasant mentalities into those that are prodevelopment ("cosmopolitan")
and those that are noninnovative and "laggard." The crucial notion was
the idea of the diffusion of rationality into rural non-European
communities. The key to development (with some qualification) was the
transmittal of new ideas to innovative "adopters." The fact that most of
the ideas were not, themselves, workable (thus were not rational), and
that adoption of them would have required of peasants not more
knowledge, but more power and landownership, was ignored. McClelland
claimed that non- Western peoples in general have not modernized
because they lack the proper "need-achievement" motivation. They will
modernize when and if they acquire this need to achieve, which had been .
of crucial importance in earlier European development, from ancient
Greece on up. Hagen produced an elaborate theory, based in no evidence
whatever, that non- Western peoples, and particularly peasants, have a
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
traditional mentality that resists change of all sorts. The model starts with
a mythic peasant unconscious mind that is uncreative, submissive to
paternal authority (and therefore oppressive of innovative children), and
unwilling to change. All three of these scholars, and dozens of their
acolytes, produced a general model of peasant mentality as defective in
both cognitive and attitudinal (affective) characteristics, but, of course,
not hopelessly so. 108 One of many recent outgrowths of this doctrine is
Stephen Marglin's theory of the Western mental "episteme," a marriage
of the old "primitive mind" idea and the newer ideas about traditionalism,
which argues, in essence, that the Western mind is, and historically has
been, scientific, rational, and intellectually hardheaded — the "epis-
teme" — while the non-Western mind is traditionally given to technique
and art ("techne") but not to science. Marglin's new twist on this old
doctrine is to say that some of the non- Western "techne" should be
incorporated in development along with the Western "episteme" because
"techne," less intellectual but more feeling, is less likely to destroy the
natural environment and causes less psychic damage to non-Western
people, a distinction rather like the older duality between scientific
thought and emotion-laden concrete thought. 109 Marglin's ideas provide
an example of much theorizing in the economic development world (like
Hagen, he is a development economist) about non- Western nonrational-
ity-
It would take us far afield to examine the parallel arguments in all
the other fields of social thought. The following should suffice: In
geography, the diffusion-of-innovative-ideas approach has been im-
portant since the 1960s and remains so today. The same old assumptions
about peasant and non-Western traditionalism are still dominant. Some
geographers claim even that non-Europeans are mentally not capable of
using all available means of coping with natural hazards like drought and
hurricane. One geographer, Robert Sack, has come up with a classically
Eurocentric theory about spatial cognition: most non- Western people
(primitives and most peasants) cannot think in spatial terms the way
modem Western adults can. Among the authorities he uses — the
argument is from authority, not evidence — are Levy-Bruhl and Piaget. 110
In the field of education in the United States the newer forms of the
dualistic-developmental theory of (Western) rationality are highly
influential in many areas, including testing. 111 In the field of philosophy,
there is a strong relationship between the stream of ideas about
rationality, discussed above, and the resurgence of mind-body dualism,
such as one finds in the Cartesian and Kantian traditions and particularly
in the modern neo-Kantians. 112
I do not suggest that the doctrine of non- Western nonrationality is
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
fully hegemonic in modern scholarship, or that the above formulations
have not been challenged. In general, however, the doctrine remains
somewhat dominant in all fields of thought except, perhaps, anthropology
and economics. Anthropology in recent decades has, with some lapses,
maintained quite firmly that primitive minds are not primitive. 113 And
some schools of economics need the principle of universal economic
rationality so badly, as axioms for their theories, that they are willing to
concede rationality to everyone.
Rationality and the European Miracle
The idea of European rationality is often called "Weberian," because Max
Weber made important use of the idea in various explanations for
European social evolution and various negative judgments about the
lesser rationality of other societies. The rationality doctrine was, however,
widely held in early twentieth-century Europe when Weber's important
writings on this subject were published. But he codified the traditional
doctrine and added something of his own to it, so the doctrine can indeed
be called Weberian from the present-day perspective. It is also Weberian
in another and perhaps more important sense: Weber placed European
social evolution in a framework emphasizing the modernization process,
and contrasting Europe's modernization with the "traditionalism," as he
sometimes called it, of Asian civilizations. When the modernization
paradigm locked into place among scholars just after World War II, Max
Weber was the most obvious, and most logical, source of basic sociological
doctrine for the paradigm. From that time on, scholars who wrote about
the rise of Europe and chose to emphasize the individual trait of
rationality, or social-level traits and institutions which Weber had treated
as primary (and, in the main, as consequences of European rationality),
were Weberians to one degree or another (even if they rejected some parts
of Weber's model). The importance of Weber for our discussion of
present-day theories about the "European miracle," is the fact that the
most influential, probably dominant, school of thought concerning the
"miracle" today is more or less Weberian. Weber's views about rationality
therefore require at least brief discussion.
Weber analyzed Western capitalist society of the late nineteenth- to
early twentieth-century epoch in meticulous detail and with great insight,
although there were important limits to his insight. He held to the typical
conceit of his time and place and class in thinking that contemporary
European capitalism is the culmination of a process of social evolution
that was, at root, an intellectual progression, an ascent of human
"rationality," meaning intellect and ethics, from ancient to modern
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
society. (He had doubts about the likelihood of further ascent in the
future.) At each stage of that progression people invented new social
forms, such as higher forms of the state, the legal system, the bureaucracy,
the economy, the city, and so forth, but these forms were, basically,
products of evolving rationality rather than primary causes of progress in
their own right. But the march toward ever more rational society took
place in Europe, among Europeans. Outside of the European tunnel of
time, all societies were in varying degrees traditional and in varying
degrees irrational.
Weber said rather little about the question of why Europeans came
to display this rationality in the first place, that is, as a basal cause. He
invoked several factors, one of which, as we noted previously, was race
and another, the natural environment. Others seem to lie deep within
culture. Yet Weber rarely discussed causality at this basal level, that is,
attempting to explain why Europeans have unique rationality, and have
had it since a long time before the Protestant Reformation and
modernity. 114 One reason seems to lie in his view of social causality, with
ideas and values, and the evolution of ideas and values, treated as prime
causes of social processes, social structures, and social change. Given this
conception, he would not be expected to look for nonideological-level
causes for ideas and values. Doubtless there were other reasons.
Whatever Weber considered to have been the basic cause of the
differences between rational, progressive European society and irrational,
traditional Asian society (Africa and America were scarcely noticed), he
delineated these supposed differences very carefully. The most crucial
arguments are found in his General Economic History and The Protestant
Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. The development of rationality among
Europeans — however that had happened — led to a special sort of
"economic ethic," a body of values, aspirations, and logical thought
processes that emerged primarily in connection with the Reformation
(and particularly Puritanism) but which, more fundamentally, produced
capitalism. The important point here is that basal rationality produced
both the "economic ethic" of capitalism and the Protestant movement:
Weber is not (as some think) explaining capitalism and modernity in
terms narrowly of religion. He does invoke religion to explain many
aspects of the supposed traditionalism of Asians, but here too a primordial
irrationality is seen as underlying religion. (He writes, for instance, of the
"magical traditionalism" of Indians and Chinese. 115 )
The superior rationality of Europeans produces other major
historical differences between Europe and non-Europe. Europeans are
basically freedom loving, not ground under by Oriental despotism; this
devolves into a form of city that is much freer than the Asian city, the
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
latter being conceived by Weber as (in essence) merely a physical entity
wholly controlled by the overarching empire, and the former as a truly
new form of society, emerging in the Middle Ages and inaugurating
modernity. 116 (As we discuss in Chapter 3, Asian cities were not as Weber
described them. Some were free city-states, others were virtually free
under a loose imperial umbrella. European cities, on the other hand, were
much less independent than Weber thought.) Landholding systems were
also different because of differences in rationality: only in Europe, says
Weber (here putting forward a purely traditional European view) does the
concept of private property truly emerge. The feudal estate is almost
genuinely private property. The Asian estate is seen as merely a temporary
assignment of land as a source of revenue for dignitaries, a form of salary
given for service and ordinarily returned to the state. But European feudal
estates were also, legally and actually, granted on service tenure, and in
both continents these sorts of estates tended in general to become
hereditary and thus eventually private property (see Chapter 3). Of
course, Weber talks about other supposed differences between Europe and
non-Europe, but the examples given here will suffice to show his overall
approach.
Weber did not originate most of these arguments, although he
codified them and developed them in a brilliant way. Yet Weber is given
credit overall, and "Weberianism" is now the most important form of
theory in explaining the European "miracle." The basic form can be
summarized very simply. Rationality is the causal root. The effect of
differential rationality is, in Europe, permanent progress, modernization,
and capitalism. In non-Europe it is stagnation, traditionalism, and various
irrational cultural attributes such as superstition. The model here is simple
diffusionism: rationality and therefore modernization are permanent in
Europe. Non-Europe does not modernize except by the diffusion of these
traits from Europe.
The doctrine of "Western rationality" is widely used today in
explanations for Europe's unique rise, its "miracle." No longer is the
superior rationality of Europeans attributed, even implicitly, to racial
superiority, but how the historians manage to assert the one without the
other is not an easy question to answer. Generally, causality is consigned
to the impenetrable mists of ancient history, with perhaps an occasional
speculation about ancient free-living European peasants or the evils of
Oriental despotism, or with a ritual citation of Max Weber. For many
historians, I suspect, the idea of European rationality is simply axiomatic.
Europeans, for whatever reason, are just built that way.
Eric L. Jones dwells very heavily on rationality as an explanation for
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
Europe's historical superiority in The European Miracle. His claim is that
there is a fundamental lack of rationality among Asians and Africans. The
assertions are laid on so thickly, and with so little attempt to account for
this putative irrationality, that it is difficult to avoid the suspicion that
Jones, perhaps alone among modern "miracle" historians, holds some
deep prejudices. Africans are dismissed, in a brief discussion, as having
had no significance in history. They are characterized in a way that
suggests, not very subtly, that they are closer to the beasts than are other
humans.
In Africa man adapted himself to nature. The hunter felt part of the
ecosystem, not outside it looking in with wonder, and definitely not above
it and superior. After all, there were large carnivores who sought man as a
prey. The most evocative symbol of this ecological oneness may be the
honey guides . . . birds commensal with man. They fly, chattering loudly,
ahead of bands of hunters, leading them ... to the tree hives of wild bees
and feeding on the wax after the men have broken open the hives. (154) 117
;" This is a Tarzan image. Most Africans were farmers, not hunters (we
discussed this previously). The scavenging house sparrow is also
commensal with humans in the suburbs of London, but Jones speaks of
. "commensalism" only for Africans. (Ethology, as we will see, is evoked
somewhat similarly for Asians. 118 )
There was scant incentive or pressure for development or invention. . . .
Any pressure . . . was apparently offset by the use of slaves instead of the
improvement of methods. . . . Otherwise wealth was spent on luxury items.
. . . [There was] pervasive insecurity as a result of conflict and slave-raiding.
(155-156)
Africans thus were noninventive, were aggressive, were lovers of luxury,
were slavers and slaves. And also hunters close to the beasts they hunted.
So: it "is not clear what indigenous developments were possible" (156).
Asians do not think logically. There is "relative absence of the
empirical enquiry and criticism of the Graeco-Judeo-Christian tradition"
(161 ), and "lack of a crisp tradition of logical debate," which may explain
the "failure" of Asian science" (162). "The notion of a consensus in
interpreting nature may have seemed absurd" (162) — that is, Asians may
not even have had an ability to conceptualize scientific verification, to
distinguish empirical truth from falsity. They were uncreative: "Asian
institutions suppressed creativity or diverted it into producing voluptuous
. luxuries" (231).
Asians have attitudes and values that inhibit progress. "Oriental
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
philosophies [emphasize] emotions, values and cosmologies," at the
expense of empirical thought (161). Orientals are lazy (163). They (like
Africans) have a "love of luxury" (170), and they love to buy things like
"kingfisher feathers . . . precious stones . . . drugs no modern pharma-
copeia would own" (164). They have a "servile spirit," their armies lack
"tough" petty officers (167). They are, as a rule, introverted, inward
looking; they are "increasingly immobile societies undergoing 'curious
experiences,' " given to self-imposed "isolation" (170), lacking an urge to
explore (168, 177, 203, 231). They are given to senseless warfare (169,
188, 197), do not have a written legal system (164, 188, 197), and do not
have a concept of political boundary (167, 194). There is much thievery
and piracy (189, 199, 209, 229-30).
In most judgments of this type (of which I have given only a sample),
Jones is referring to Asians in general and through all times in their
history. 119 Some judgments are more specific. Islamic society was for a
time somewhat innovative, borrowing technology from other societies,
and preserving ancient Greek sciences. (This is a standard Eurocentric
belief: Arabs preserved Greek science during the Dark Ages and then
handed it back to Europe for further development, something like an
intellectual left-luggage office.) The Ottoman Empire (the single real
example of Islamic culture discussed by Jones, with the imputation that it
stands as symbol for Islam as a whole and at all times) stamped out original
thought. It produced unreason, backwardness, and retrogression, a "mist
of obscurantist thought" (183). Ottomans didn't even know "the
elementary facts of geography" (184) and couldn't even make decent
maps (179). (Jones himself doesn't know much about geography and
maps.) Rulers were often "degenerates," "drunkards," "mental defec-
tives," "lechers," ruling with despotism and terror (186-187), their
"philosophy" being theft and despoilment, against which there was "no
legal shield" (187-189).
Indian society was socially and psychologically "frozen" (192), with
values that were deleterious to economic progress. Religion was invoked
to sanction all acts, but the advice of religious counsellors was "malicious
or random" (195). The Mughal rulers were, like the Ottomans,
degenerates, running society for their own benefit, given to "voluptuous
selfishness," harems, jewels, menageries, intrigues, treason (196). The
state was purely predatory. Technology was "almost stagnant," not even
copying from abroad (199). "No written legal code existed," says Jones in
a quite bizarre misstatement (197).
China was technologically inventive and innovative until the early
Middle Ages, when progress stopped. There was thereafter a "retreat"
(203); some skills were even forgotten. Chinese became "inward-looking"
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
(203, 216, 220). China "backed away" from technology, from trade, from
exploration. Technological development stopped even in agriculture, and
only the cultivation of new land, with irrational cutting of irreplaceable
forests, and the fortunate, timely, arrival of New World crops such as
maize and sweet potato, saved the Chinese temporarily from disaster,
although cutting down these forests was "one of mankind's greatest acts of
ecological stupidity," stupidity which led to "soil erosion, gullying, silting
and floods" (213). (Apparently the deforestation of Europe and North
American was not "stupid.") Peasants were given to "envy and suspicion"
(206), were stupid as farmers (212-217), and were stupid also in preferring
"maximal reproduction" over "affluence" (218). The state was despotic,
a "revenue-pump" for the rulers, providing no services (206). There was
(again) a love of luxury, an attitude of "empty cultural superiority" (205),
a corrupt, venal, parasitic ruling class. Chinese had "anti-social customs"
(7) and were diseased.
Ethology, the science of comparative animal behavior, is invoked
repeatedly by Jones in his characterization of Asians and Africans.
Oriental courts were given to displays of "the dominance relationship"
(109, 209). Multiple wives had "ethological significance," as also,
perhaps, did the "amassing" of slaves for "display purposes." "Great
attention was paid to submission symbols, kneeling, prostration, the
kotow" (209). In India, a "similar calculus . . . underlay human
demographic behavior and veneration of the cow" (19). Recall the
"commensalism" in Africa.
These beliefs about the intellectual and moral inferiority of
non-Europeans are old colonial-era prejudices, which Jones merely
recites. The fact that The European Miracle is taken seriously by some
historians is partly, I think, a reflection of the degree to which these old
prejudices still lurk within our scholarship as implicit beliefs.
Many other historians of the "miracle" try to insert European
rationality at or near the base of their explanatory theories. Michael
Mann can be taken as a typical representative of the genre. We have
already discussed his contrived little theory about the marvelous Iron Age
Indo-Europeans of the northern forests, uniquely individualistic, aggres-
sive, freedom loving (all notions from nineteenth-century and earlier
scholarship, none grounded in solid evidence for Europe or, compara-
tively, for non-Europe). Mann moves smoothly to ancient Greece, which
he sees as the product of this earlier Indo-European root rationalism. The
Greeks invented most things rational, from science to democracy to
ethics (a respect for humanity). Other Mediterranean peoples contributed
rather little by comparison with the rational Indo-Europeans who swept
down from the north. (Even the Roman influence, which subjugated the
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
European peasant, is seen as vaguely "un-European." 120 ) History then
moves northwestward as northern Europeans clear the forest and move
what Mann calls the "leading edge" of European society forward toward
what seems to be its foreordained goal, Britain. 121 Early in the Middle
Ages, around A.D. 800, a newer stage of rationality emerges, combining the
old culture and the new Christianity. Europeans now demonstrate their
"rational restlessness" and their unique inventiveness, producing a
revolutionary agricultural system and much more. The explanation is the
ancient rationality, the newer Christian rationality, and the marvelous
European environment. 122 This, for Mann, is the kernel of the European
miracle. The only part of this construct that requires further comment is
the theory of a medieval technological revolution; this we discuss in the
following section.
Lynn White, Jr., contributed a very influential form of the
rationality doctrine with his theory about the unique technological
inventiveness of medieval Europeans, a theory we discuss in the next
section. John Hall contributes another version, much like Mann's except
for its emphasis on the invention of rational politics by Europeans and its
tendency to follow Eric L. Jones in various negative judgments about
Asian history. Space does not permit me to review the way some other
present-day historians invoke, and use, the theory of Western rationality
as grounding for their theories about the European miracle. I should
simply note that some of them are Marxists and near-Marxists. Perry
Anderson, for instance, argues from ancient Greek rationality to
European medieval progress. So does M. I. Finley. Robert Brenner
contributes a very different Marxist rationality theory: there was no
rationality until, quite suddenly, capitalism appeared among the English
yeoman farmers, who promptly became amazingly inventive and started a
technological revolution that has not yet ended. 123
Technology
Among all of the narrow-minded ways of looking at history, technological
determinism is the one most congenial to Eurocentric tunnel vision. It
has the appearance, the illusion, of cold-blooded scientific fact. "X was
invented here, on this date, and produced these effects." In talking about
matters of technology, one can deny that ethnocentrism enters the
picture: "this is hard fact, indisputable." And the significance of
technology seems equally indisputable: a new toot does produce more
food, a new weapon more casualties, whereas a new social form might have
historical significance; then again, it might not. But technological
determinism gets its greatest strength from the error known as
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
"telescoping history." When we travel, mentally, back to medieval
Europe, we pass backward through the eras in which Europeans clearly
were technologically superior to everyone else, and so we tend to expect
that superiority to have been the state of things at all prior times. But
Europe advanced technologically beyond Asia and Africa mainly after
the beginning of the industrial revolution. Europe did not even begin to
forge ahead of other civilizations in technology or science until the
seventeenth century or even later. By telescoping history we imbue the
Middle Ages with the marvelous technological attributes of modern
Europe. It is then but a small step to the conclusion that, since technology
is so obviously a powerful cause in history, and since Europe has always
been so technological, here is the root of the European miracle.
But tools do not invent themselves or reproduce themselves. If you
invoke technological determinism, you must not only show that the
technology appeared and had such-and-such effects, you must also
explain why it was invented, and by whom. In nearly all (I think)
technologically deterministic arguments made as part of some explana-
tion for Europe's historical progress, technological arguments end up
being arguments about the inventors, not the inventions. They end up in
some Weberian claim that Europeans are more inventive, innovative,
"rational," than non-Europeans. Technological determinism then differs
from other kinds of tunnel-historical theories mainly in its claim that
rational Europeans moved their society forward by inventing new
technology, rather than doing so by inventing new political systems, new
forms of social organization, new religions, or whatever.
Claims are made by Eurocentric historians that technology was a
prime mover in all epochs from the post-Neolithic on down. Nowadays it
would be hard to ignore the evidence that in ancient times the greatest
technological innovations, in agriculture, transportation, and other
spheres, entered Europe from the south and east, so technological
arguments tend to begin with the Middle Ages. There are, however,
exceptions. Michael Mann, as we noted previously, has revived the old
notion that the invention of iron somehow revolutionized European
peasant society in a way it did not do elsewhere, that it produced a
wondrously inventive, acquisitive (etc.) type of society, rooted in
iron-plowing Indo-European-speaking peasants, and he claims, in
parallel, that Oriental despotisms of the ancient Middle East held back
technological inventiveness, where peasants were supposedly held in
tight control by the political system that irrigation technology necessi-
tated. But this theory is contradicted by a great deal of evidence. So much
is known about technological progress in the Middle East during this
period (from the late Neolithic to the "Iron Age" and beyond) that the
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
notion of noninventiveness is unreasonable. But iron working was not
invented in Europe. Probably it came from tbe Middle East, but there are
hints from farther afield (including West Africa). Plows were used in
Middle Eastern agriculture, irrigated and nonirrigated, as well as in
European agriculture. Plows may have been used earlier in China than in
Europe. So the technological argument put forward by Mann (and others)
is unsound and the psychological and social deductions are fallacious.
Many other "miracle" historians are prepared to start with the
ancient Greeks and define these folk as the original uniquely inventive
Europeans, but the Greeks did not contribute more to technological
progress than their neighbors did to the south and east, so arguments of
this sort must revert to the abstract idea of "rationality," thus, of
potentiality, not actuality, a point we have already discussed. The
Romans, in turn, were moderately inventive, but so were their neighbors.
In the European Dark Ages, as everyone agrees, technological progress
was hardly impressive, and was in fact going on at a healthier pace in parts
of Africa and Asia. I suspect that the majority of historians today are not
willing to go along with Michael Mann and others who claim to find a
unique technological progress in Europe prior to the Middle Ages,
although this view was quite widespread until a few decades ago. Most
would disagree with Eric L. Jones, in The European Miracle, that Europe
has always been "a mutant civilization in its uninterrupted amassing of
knowledge about technology" (p. 45), since there is nothing unusual
about this process in human society.
It is with the Middle Ages that technological arguments come to
prominence. It is here that the notion of a technological "takeoff to
modernity" is most frequently encountered among historians of the
European "miracle." The common argument form is about as follows:
Northern Europeans indeed were rather backward folk until late in the
Dark Ages, the early Middle Ages, when a kind of awakening occurred,
and northern Europeans now suddenly emerged as the people we
know — the most dynamic, most progressive, most innovative, most
rapidly rising (etc.) people in the world — and the key to this rise was a set
of early medieval technological innovations, based mainly, these
historians claim, on European inventions, neglecting non-Europe and
thus presenting us with a typical sort of Eurocentric tunnel history.
Lynn White, Jr., is an American historian whose book Medieval
Technology and Social Change presents this kind of technologically
deterministic tunnel-historical argument in perhaps its purest form. This
book, published in 1962, has been highly influential; its arguments are
built in to the theories of many "miracle" historians, including Mann,
Jones, and Hall (who not only cite the book repeatedly in their writings
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
but rely on it for many technological arguments they invoke in support of
their theories). The book is an effort to show that technological
invention and innovation was the central cause of the rise of Europe
during the Middle Ages. White lists a series of supposedly European
inventions, and shows, for each in turn, what marvelous effects it had on
European history. Here, for starters, is an example. The early medieval
invention of the iron stirrup had a "catalytic . . . influence on history." It
permitted a new form of mounted warfare, created the phenomenon of
the medieval knight, and produced feudalism (knights became manorial
lords). And so, "The Man on Horseback, as we have known him during
the past millennium, was made possible by the stirrup." 12 ^
But White's crucial arguments concern productive technology, and
particularly agricultural technology. He claims that an agricultural
revolution occurred in Europe (or rather in northern Europe) in the early
Middle Ages, and this quite revolutionized European society and became
a large part of the explanation for modernization and the rise of
capitalism. He believes that three European inventions were the crux of
the matter: the heavy plow, the horse collar (and therefore the use of
horsepower), and the three-field rotation.
The heavy plow, pulled by teams of (typically) eight oxen, is
assigned, by White, a tentative central European origin in the sixth
century; it then diffused quickly throughout northwestern Europe, and
"does much to account for the bursting vitality of the Carolingian realm
in the eighth century." 125 White is correct in calling attention, as others
before him have done, to the importance of the heavy plow as an
agricultural innovation in the wetter and colder parts of Europe. It was
highly advantageous in opening the deep, heavy soils of the North
European Plain and the deep-working of soil was critical in view of
northern Europe's moist weather. It was in fact necessary for the areal
spread of farming into some of the wetter soils. Therefore, the heavy plow
had much to do with the overall increase in medieval agricultural
production. But the heavy plow was not in fact invented in Europe in the
Middle Ages. Plows pulled by teams of 24 oxen were used in northern
India before the time of Christ. 126 Southern Europe used lighter plows,
because the soils were generally lighter and drier, but the technology was
not significantly different. It seems certain that the heavy plow was either
diffused into northern Europe from elsewhere or was a local adaptation of
a widely used tool-form. So this is not a European technological
revolution. And the effects of the innovation in northern Europe
probably should be attributed to the social forces that led to the
introduction of the heavy plow, not to the technology itself. We know,
for instance, that the growth of feudalism led to massive expansion of
112 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
cultivation, partly at the incentive of the lords, who wished to increase
their wealth and power by expanding their demesnes, partly as a reaction
by peasants to the persistently increased demands from the lords for
surplus product, increments of demand which could not be met without
endangering the subsistence of the peasant family unless the peasants
found a way to increase their total production. It appears that whatever
historical effects are attributed by White to the plow should rather be
attributed to feudalism as a social system. And the effects claimed by him
are indeed quite miraculous.
Thanks to the adoption of the heavy plow, says White, there was a
tremendous growth in population. Then there was a changeover to the
"open field" system of cultivation and this led, according to White, to the
invention of "communal patterns" of human cooperation (as though
communal life had not been known previously and was unknown
elsewhere). This was a social revolution, a "reshaping of peasant society."
It was "the essence of the manorial economy," ignoring the fact that the
manors were owned by lords, not villagers. 127 More important still, there
came then "a change [in] the northern peasants' attitude towards nature
and thus our own" (my emphasis). Why? Because many families had to
collaborate to mount one plow team, and so their allotments now were
proportional to their social contribution, not to their needs. ("No more
fundamental change in the idea of man's relation to the soil can be
imagined: once man had been part of nature; now he became her
exploiter." 128 )
But all of this is nonsense. Neither the technical arguments nor the
social deductions make any sense. The Domesday Book gives household-
to-plow-team ratios of between 2:3 and 3:5. 129 The open-field system
seems to be quite old and was widespread in Europe and known in Asia
and North Africa in early times. 130 Northern villages, using big teams and
heavy plows, were no more cooperative than southern villages, using light
plows. Communal ownership of fields in some societies implied greater
cooperation than that found in the European open field system. The
manorial economy was a social system, not a technological invention.
And so on.
White's second revolutionary advance is labelled "the discovery of
horse-power." 131 Horses had been around for some time, of course. The
essential innovation, for White, was the modern horse collar, which he
thinks was probably developed in the Occident some time before the
ninth century. According to White, the horse collar transformed
agriculture and grain transport in northern Europe by permitting horses to
replace oxen in pulling plows and wagons. Horses pull about the same
weight as oxen but do so about 50% faster. From this fact White draws
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 113
awesome conclusions. There was, he says, a large increase in agricultural
production. Commerce became intensified because transport by horse-
power was vastly cheaper than by ox power. Villages became much larger,
almost townlike, because now there could be a larger radius of travel from
home to field. The enlargement of villages yielded the "virtue of a more
'urban' life," permitting the village to have a church, tavern, school (now
boys "could learn their letters")- 132 And now there could be "news from
distant parts." A transformation, overall, of profound importance. It
"urbanized" the village, giving peasants the "psychological preparation"
for "the change in Occidental culture from country to city." 133 All this
and more from one innovation: the horse collar.
But the horse collar was widespread in Eurasia from an early date,
and probably was invented for harnessing not horses but camels. 134 And
the presumption that horses held advantages over oxen in plowing and
transport is widely disputed: the horse was more efficient, but more costly
in upkeep, and generally required that cropland be devoted to feed crops.
In England the horse did not replace the ox. Village size had nothing to
do with horsepower. In many parts of the world where horses were not
used, villages were much larger than they were in northern Europe. In
countries like China, long-distance grain transport was often by canal,
much more efficient than horse-drawn wagons. And so, again, neither the
technical arguments nor the social deductions make any sense.
Finally, White attributes equally marvelous effects to the introduc-
tion of the three-field system. Part of this argument is familiar to every
European schoolchild, who learned that the three-field rotation was a
great advance over the older two-field system because (mainly) it reduced
the proportion of the land in fallow from roughly 1/2 to 1/3. But White
adds a cornucopia of additional blessings. Oats could now be planted
widely, hence there was greater use of horsepower. In a section of Medieval
Technology and Social Change, "The Three-Field Rotation and Improved
Nutrition," he claims that the three-field system somehow permitted
farmers now to grow legumes, and this vastly improved the European diet,
which, in turn, "goes far towards explaining . . . the startling expansion of
population, the growth and multiplication of cities, the rise of industrial
production, the outreach of commerce, and the new exuberance of spirits
which enlivened that age." In short, says Lynn White, Jr., "the Middle
Ages were full of beans." 135
But none of this (least of all the pun) can be taken seriously. There
is no basis for White's argument that population was held down by an
unbalanced diet (overloaded, he says, with carbohydrates, undersupplied
with proteins). Farmers using the two-field system were not protein-
starved, because legume cultivation long antedated the three-field system,
114 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
grains also contained proteins, and fruits, animal products, and so on,
were widely consumed. The three-field system was not a technological
revolution. First of all, even more intensive rotations, including fallowless
systems, were in use in many parts of the world long before the Middle
Ages, and I suspect were common in parts of Europe (such as portions of
the Po plain) where deep, nutrient-rich soils and good soil-water
relations were found. Second, the two-field system was preferred, and was
not supplanted, in many ecological situations, and in areas where fallow
was needed for grazing. The picture is complex, but the generalization is
clear: the three-field system was neither a technical revolution nor a
fountainhead for social change. And it had close relatives in other
continents, so it cannot be said to have been something uniquely
European.
In Medieval Technology and Social Change, White says little about the
causes of the revolutionary technology. He does so elsewhere, however,
and we find that his basic argument is really quite Weberian. 136
Technological determinism dissolves into an ideological determinism,
focused on the inventiveness — the rationality — of Europeans. This
White attributes, basically, to religion: in part to "the Judeo-Christian
teleology," and in larger part to "Western Christianity." The former
underlies the European's unique "faith in perpetual progress," which leads
to a faith in the virtues of inventiveness and technology. 137 The latter
produces "an Occidental, voluntarist realization of the Christian dogma
of man's transcendence of, and rightful mastery over, nature" — that is,
the separation of Man and Nature. To a Western Christian, nature is
inert, valueless. It is blasphemy to "assume spirit in nature." 138 This gives
the Western Christian a desire and right to manipulate, use, transform
nature — to invent new technology. The errors here are glaring. First,
there is ignorance of the teachings of religions other than Christianity.
Second, White resurrects the ethnocentric myth that ancient pagans and
followers of modern non-Christian religions somehow are unable to fully
separate Man from Nature and share the primitive view that spirits reside
in all things. Actually, medieval Christians did perceive spirit in all
things. (It was God's way.) They did not treat humans as absolutely
separate from nature. This dualism is a product of modern times, mainly
of the commoditization of nature with the rise of capitalism. Dualism is a
doctrine of post-Cartesian thought, not something residing deep in
"Western Christianity." Medieval Christians believed that the world is
one, a plenum, an uninterrupted chain of being. Medieval folk did not, in
general, believe, as White claims they did, in "perpetual progress": they
believed in the Fall, and they believed, on the whole, that Creation had
been perfect and complete. White is simply telescoping history in order to
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
claim that modern European attitudes about technology and technologi-
cal change are actually basic and ancient attributes of the culture of
Europeans, and only Europeans. His central thesis is basic tunnel history:
Europeans are uniquely inventive, so they create unique technology, so
they progress.
I believe that all of the claims for European technological superiority
in the Middle Ages can be countered, and eventually disproven, in much
the same way. I think it will become clear that all of the civilizations of
the hemisphere were inventing new technology and sharing it around;
the "sharing" being the usual mechanisms of diffusion as they operated in
two spheres of reality: agricultural techniques passed from farmer to
farmer and other techniques (including some of those involved in
commercial agriculture) moving through the mainly urban network of
trade and transportation, or occasionally (as with some military
technology) moving around the map along with conquest. Thus I see a
rather even building up of technology in Europe, Africa, and Asia. It was
only after 1492, with its utterly revolutionary consequences, that
European technology acquired the beginning of an edge over Asian and
African. Did medieval technological evolution produce, as cause, the
major medieval social changes? I leave the answer to that question to
others. My purpose in this book is not to defend any one theory of social
change, merely to show that the processes were not uniquely European.
In Chapter 3 I will discuss this matter further, showing how
technological and economic surfaces emerged in medieval Europe, Africa,
and Asia, and that processes of change in all three continents were — as to
technology and economy — quite similar.
Before we leave the subject of technology, something must be said
about one fascinating issue: what I will call "the China formula." Since the
end of World War II a great deal has become known about the history of
technology in China, much of it through the work of Joseph Needham and
his associates. 139 In prior times, the European miracle theorists were prone
to ignore Chinese technological achievements. (Weber did so less than
most. 1 "' 0 ) The usual pattern was to admit Chinese priority for some
innovations but claim that, overall, the main technological advances took
place in Europe and the Mediterranean. Where there were truly notable
Chinese inventions, it was often claimed that the Chinese invented these
things in a ludic vein whereas the Europeans put these things to work.
(The paradigm, of course, is gunpowder, which the Chinese were supposed
to have invented merely for fireworks.) One could bundle such proposi-
tions into a classical diffusionist model of the Chinese: they had, in prior
ages, progressed somewhat, but then they slowed to a stop, starting up
again only when Europeans brought new ideas.
116 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
It is now known beyond doubt that Chinese technology was on a par
with that of the western part of the Old World, in some ways superior to it
and in other ways inferior, during and before the Middle Ages. 141 This new
knowledge is devastating to many of the European miracle theories, those
that claim that ancient and medieval European progress in technology was
a crucial cause of the "miracle." (If the Chinese were doing the same things
at the same times, the argument about Europe's uniqueness just crumbles.)
The result has been a general modification of many of the miracle theories
to take these newly known facts into account. Typically, the formula runs
as follows.
1. "If indeed the development of technology in medieval China
forces us to ask why China did not, then, have its own miracle, we can at
least assert that China was the only civilization outside of Europe about
which such questions arise." In other words, European superiority over
everybody else is not put into doubt. This is convenient for those, for
instance, who want to show that India, Africa, the Middle East, and so on,
had no potential for development.
2. "Whatever technological advances took place in medieval China,
the important point is that they stopped." In the formula, this argument is
expressed in different ways for different spheres of technology, but the
central argument is fairly standard: something characteristic of Chinese
medieval culture forced it to cease developing and so to stagnate. In other
words, what is plugged in here is the old doctrine of Oriental stagnation.
Most typically, Weber is used to make this point: just about all of the
Weberian claims about the reasons for Chinese lack of progress are
regularly paraded at this point. Some historians balk at using Weber's thin
argument about the stultifying effect of Confucianism. Others prefer not
to notice Weber's ethnocentrism when he describes Chinese personality
traits. But Weber's arguments about the city, landowning, bureaucracy,
and empire are still quite regularly employed. The Chinese city was not
"free" and did not have a real bourgeoisie. Chinese landowning was not
close to private property. The Chinese bureaucracy and the Chinese
imperial state were not "rational" and so held back the society from
progress.
One can respond to this argument in two steps. First, as Purcell has
pointed out, the important question really is how and why these Chinese
advances happened, not how and why they stopped happening (if indeed
they did stop). In other words, historians must explain how China came to
be such a technologically innovative society that it outstripped other
civilizations in many spheres of technology for many centuries. Weber
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
doesn't help in this process one bit. The whole Weberian scheme is an
explanation for stagnation, and what we are talking about is impressive
progress, not stagnation.
The second step in the argument requires a focus on the precise period
when, according to European miracle historians, the Chinese advance is
supposed to have stopped. According to Elvin, broad-spectrum technical
advances in China ended after the early fourteenth century. China at this
time had perhaps the most advanced and most highly commercialized
agriculture in the world. Chinese industrial technology was unexcelled in
such fields as textile manufacture. Mechanical clocks were well known. 142
Chinese merchant ships were plying throughout Southeast Asia and into
the Indian ocean. Chinese guns were unexcelled. Canal technology was
impressive. And so on. Broadly, the changes associated with the rise and
travails of the Ming dynasty are associated with the slowing of technical
advance, although advances continued to take place in some spheres of
technology (shipbuilding, cannons, printing with movable metal type —
invented circa 1400, probably in Korea 143 — and much more). But Europe
at this time was not experiencing a major technical advance either. After
1350 Europe stagnated both economically and technically. There is little
evidence that European technology was advancing prior to 1492. The
Renaissance was not a technological revolution, as historians have long
realized. 144 After 1492 important European advances began again in some
technical spheres (notably shipbuilding). Whether truly revolutionary
technological change really began before the eighteenth century is a
matter of contention among European historians.
What does this say comparatively about China? It suggests that there
is no problem of "stagnation." There was, instead, a slowing of progress
during two centuries, in a scenario well known in all human cultures,
because uneven progress is the norm. It suggests, rather, a problem that
Third World historians focus some attention on but European historians
tend to ignore. As a result of the European commercial expansion in the
sixteenth century — we argue in this book that the year 1492 was the real
birthdate of this process — aggressive European merchant communities
began competing and trading with the Chinese in various places, notably
Manila and some South China ports. Why did the Chinese merchant
community not assert its dominance in this trade? Why did the commer-
cial advantage steadily move in the direction of Europeans, not Chinese
(and other Asians)? In other words, there is no stagnation to be explained.
There is, rather, a problem as to how and why Europeans gained substantial
control of long-distance trade in Asia after about 1600. Anticipating the
discussion of later chapters, I will comment simply that this process does
not reflect any internal cultural "blockages" in any Asian civilizations.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Rather, it reflects the tremendously rapid increase in the profitability,
scale, and organization of European enterprise overseas after 1492, which
nobody else could really take advantage of, because of the constantly
increasing flow of New World bullion into European mercantile coffers (a
point we will discuss in some detail in Chapter 4).
During the first half of the fifteenth century, a number of Chinese
fleets of combined military, diplomatic, and merchant character were sent
into Southeast Asia and the Indian Ocean. Some of the ships held
hundreds of men; some were so large that vegetable gardens were placed on
the decks. We will discuss the significance of these great voyages in the
next chapter; my point now is to notice the way European miracle
historians try to accommodate these facts into their theories about
Chinese nonprogress. The standard comment is: "But they stopped." In
fact, the last voyage did end around 1440. But the purposes of the voyages
had been accomplished. Chinese merchant ships continued to trade in
Southeast Asia. Nothing stopped. It is true that the emperors banned
Chinese shipping for a time (mainly the early sixteenth century), but such
bans were a means of extracting bribes (in effect easements) and they were
not, in any case, enforced. For the "miracle" historians, the fact of the
imperial ban is proof that China had stopped progressing, and that only
Europe contained the potential for the "miracle." This does not accord
with the facts.
Chinese may have invented guns; in any case, they were as advanced
in firearms technology as any other culture down to the end of the Middle
Ages. Typical of the way European miracle historians deal with this sphere
of technology (as with others) is Carlo Cipolla's account of the process in
his well-known and influential book Guns, Sails, and Empires: Technologi-
cal Innovation and the Early Phase of European Expansion, 1400-1700. He
concedes, to begin with, that "Chinese guns were at least as good as
Western guns, if not better, up to the beginning of the fifteenth cen-
tury." 145 But when the Portuguese appeared off Canton and fired off their
cannon in salute a century later (1517), the Chinese had, magically,
retrogressed:
The roar of European ordnance awoke Chinese ... to the frightening
reality of a strange, alien people that unexpectedly had appeared along their
coasts under the protection and with the menace of superior, formidable
weapons. . . . How to deal with the "foreign devils"? To fight them or to
ignore them? To copy and adopt their techniques and give up local habits
and traditions or to sever all contacts with them and seek refuge in a dream
of isolation? To be or not to be? ... a dilemma that was tragically
unanswerable. 1 ' 16
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 119
Thus does rhetoric replace fact in the mythology of Asian stagnation and
the European miracle.
The "Chinese formula" seems to be losing credence. But I have no
doubt that an "Indian formula," an "Islamic formula," an "African
formula," and so on, will be contrived to shore up Eurocentric history as
we learn more about Indian, Middle-Eastern, and African technological
development prior to 1492.
Society
In Chapter 3 we will take a look at medieval European society and
compare it to medieval Asian and African society in terms of those social
categories that seem to be important in the process of change toward
capitalism and modernity. Among these categories (forms, facts) are class,
the state, landholding, trade, and urbanization. Our present task is the
more modest one of criticizing theories that claim that one or another
social category somehow led Europe to rise above all other civilizations
before the end of the Middle Ages, before 1492. For this task we can select
a few of the categories that present-day historians of the European miracle
claim as favored candidates for this role of historical leadership, of causal
motor propelling the so-called "take-off to modernity." The favored ones
seem to be the state, the church, class, and the family. Most frequently
these categories are, themselves, explained in terms of supposedly more
basic forces: European rationality, European technology, European
demographic uniqueness, or European environmental superiority. These
have been discussed at sufficient length already. The following discussion,
therefore, will be brief.
State
A typical sort of argument begins with a model of the modern European
nation-state, the kind of medium-sized, well- integrated, moderately
democratic state that emerged after the rise of capitalism, after
modernization, after the French and American revolutions. Nobody
denies that this form is unique. But European miracle historians tend to
make one of two claims about this state form: either it appeared very early
in European history, early enough to play a causal role in modernization,
or it was somehow immanent in European culture, a state form that was
created, naturally and rationally, by freedom-loving, individualistic,
antidespotic Europeans of medieval or earlier times. Sometimes both
claims are made: a reduction to European moral rationality and, at the
same time, a holistic argument at the level of the state itself.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Eric L. Jones, for instance, does precisely that in The European
Miracle. Europe's medieval political system, says Jones, was near "the
heart of the European miracle." 147 Here the argument combines the
traditional prejudice about Europe's innate and unique love of freedom
with some very odd environmentalistic arguments. First the latter. Jones
takes the familiar argument that Europe in early times had a number of
fertile core areas, each of which became the hearth of a regional culture,
and he turns it into a curious argument to the effect that Europe's
ecological core areas naturally led to a pattern of medium-sized states,
unlike, he says, the "imperial" pattern of Asian societies. Empires, in
Jones's view, are innately despotic, and innately given to interfering with
the development of the economy. Europe's geography saved it from this
fate. If a number of Europe's modern states have ecological "core areas,"
most do not, and rather few of these core areas became states. The model
is environmentalistic and invalid. In any case, comparable core areas are
found in many other parts of the world. Medium-sized, separate units of
productive agricultural environments are, for instance, typical for
Southeast Asia, including the rather discrete mainland cores, like the
Irrawaddy and the Chao Phraya basins, the middle Mekong, and the Red
River, and even more so the insular region, with cores in Sumatra (two or
three), Java (three), Bali, Lombok, Sulawesi, Luzon, and so on. India and
China too are moderately dissected in this way. Distinctive cores in
Africa include the Middle Niger, Chad, and Congo, among others; in
western Asia, Mesopotamia, the Iranian Plateau, and so on. 148
Next, Jones builds the image of these natural European L/r-states as
somehow naturally forming into what he calls "a states system," a grid of
roughly equal-sized independent states. These, in the Middle Ages, acted
toward one another as though they were Hegelian individuals, competing
yet cooperating, and marching forward, together, as a kind of members'
club, toward modernity. Thus Jones discerns deep in the Middle Ages
what amounts to the modern nation-state and the League of Nations.
Telescoping history, he imbues the medieval European polities with all
the virtues of the modern state: they provided public services, they
encouraged the free development of the economy, they were incipiently
democratic, and so on. All of this because of their environmental basis
and because freedom-loving Europeans lived in them. In reality, the kind
of state, and state system, that he describes does not appear until roughly
the seventeenth century. Jones finds political characteristics of already-
modernizing Europe, falsely claims that these were present long
before — some, being environmental, were always present — and so claims
to have proven that Europe's modern democratic political system was,
somehow, always present in Europe (and nowhere else). In fact, medieval
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
Europe was a hodge-podge of semisovereign feudal political units, a map
so confused that states as such were not always identifiable, and with few
■ of the modern state characteristics attributed to these polities by Jones.
But to understand the absurdity of this model of political history, we
must notice the way Jones talks about the supposedly barbaric, despotic
states of non-Europe. In non-Europe, a natural irrationality combines
with environmental disadvantages to produce the opposite of the
r wonderful European state and system of states: the huge Oriental empire.
Why did Asia not develop politically as Europe did? The political
"infantilism" of Asia is explained by Jones in terms of ( 1 ) a psychological
deficiency, consisting of irrationality in matters of intellectual vitality
and innovativeness and a sort of moral failing in attitudes relating to the
desire for progress, resistance to domination, will to forego animal
pleasures, and the like, and (2) an inferior natural environment. The
effects of these failings (and some lesser ones), and thus the effective
reasons for Asia's political nondevelopment and nonprogress, are (1)
uncontrolled population growth, and (2) bad government, "Oriental
' despotism" or, as Jones prefers to label it, empire. Throughout The
European Miracle, the main argument supporting the theory about how
Europe's system of states favors development is Jones's countertheory
about the evil nature of the Asian imperial state. Yet, in the end, the
countertheory turns out to be as empty as the theory. Jones does not, in
fact, give any credible explanation as to why such large empires exist in
Asia and not in Europe. But neither does he give a credible argument as
to why large states are worse for progress than medium-sized or small ones.
(And he is blind to the very real progress that occurred in Asia, and to the
many nonimperial states in Asia.) When we examine Jones's theory about
Asian empires, then, we find that it has nothing to do with size or kind of
state and everything to do with a conception about the basic nature of
politics in non-European societies. This is nothing more than the old idea
of "Oriental despotism." Asians, and indeed all non-Europeans, naturally
suffer nasty, despotic, capricious, irresponsible, evil governments. Only
Europeans understand and thus enjoy freedom.
This is not an atypical theory among historians who wish to argue
that European political processes and forms were causal forces leading to
a medieval "miracle." The basic form of the theory is traditional. It
consists mainly of three propositions: Europeans have an old, deep-seated
rationality that impels them toward modern, implicitly democratic,
political forms (or, less directly, toward individualistic economic behavior
and thus a preference for a minimalistic state); non-Europeans suffer
. gladly and naturally a despotic, imperial form of state, sometimes powerful
but always arbitrary; and Europe's natural environment gives political
122 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
modernization one or another sort of unique boost (ecological cores,
fertile soil, capes-and-bays accessibility, or whatever). Other propositions
figure in most arguments, but these three seem to be the most widely used.
They combine with a methodological principle of great significance:
whatever causal forces were at work, they were at work early — that is, they
set the process of modernization in motion long before the end of the
Middle Ages. This, of course, is the crux of the matter. In the present book
I argue that modernization (or whatever you want to call it) was indeed ,
going on in medieval Europe, but not only in medieval Europe. Thus the
events after 1492 did not start modernization but enabled European
changes to increase in magnitude and effect and eventually produce a
uniquely "rising" society. Therefore we argue from the uniformitarian
hypothesis that Europe had no potential greater than that possessed by
non-Europe during the Middle Ages. The fact that there were forces
pushing toward democratization and the modern state in medieval Europe
tells us nothing about European uniqueness.
John A. Hall uses the basic Jones model, emphasizing what he calls
the "blockages" that prevented China, India, and the Islamic Middle East
from developing modern state forms. In brief: China suffered under
empire. India suffered under caste (and so had no politics whatever). ^ 9
Islamic-region politics reflected tribalism. Hall describes very old and not
really typical forms for each of these civilizations, assuming them to be
frozen and permanent, contrasts these with late postmedieval European
forms with the inference that these too have been present at least in
embryo for a long time, and then builds an argument that non-Europe
always lacked the potential for a "miracle," while Europe always had it. 150
Michael Mann addresses himself to the abstract entity "power"
instead of the more visible "state," but his argument is not fundamentally
different. Mann, like a number of other "miracle" historians, tries to
interpret the political chaos of early medieval feudalism, with its
fragmentation of polities and sovereignties, into an argument for
incipient modernity. The smallness of these politicosocial units implies,
somehow, that they were more "intensive," more meaningful, more
pregnant with development potential, than the supposedly vast imperial
polities of non-Europe. Mann's notion of "intensiveness" is basically a
notion of value, not of fact. 151 In this context we may recall the Magna
Carta myth: devolution of power from king to barons is traditionally
described as a movement toward democracy, even though the barons in
those times were hardly democratic, and poor people preferred to be able
to appeal above their heads to the king. (And later the rise of royal power
is described as a further step toward democracy, except that you can't have
it both ways. 152 ) Jean Baechler uses roughly the same model — although,
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
unlike Hall and Mann but rather like Jones, he downplays the role of
Christianity in political evolution — with one additional argument:
Baechler believes that the medieval European aristocracy (originally an
Indo-European "warrior aristocracy") was itself the original source of
democracy, claiming, in a curious reading of history, that aristocrats not
only dealt democratically (respectfully) with one another, but they also
respected the rights of their peasants. 153
Yet there was no democracy in the Middle Ages: European states
were as despotic as any found anywhere else. Just as we noted with regard
to the ancient Greeks, political forms found in Europe had counterparts
elsewhere. If city-states were (perhaps) the closest to democracy — some
of them were republican, and were in essence merchant-oligarchies — one
need only note that city-states of many sorts lined the coasts of the Indian
and Pacific oceans. Nor was the republican form unknown in Asia and
Africa.
Church
Many theories assign one or another causal role to the church as a social
institution in the modernization of Europe and the rise of capitalism. 154
(Many other theories assign such a role to Christianity itself, but I will not
comment on these.) Of course, the church did have such a role. The
problems lie elsewhere. Most of them concern the question whether the
church (or churches) provided Europe, and Europeans, with something
that was not provided to non-Europeans by their own religious
institutions or by other institutions in their own cultures. For instance,
the claim has been made that the Catholic church in the Middle Ages
I unified Europe in cultural terms, to a degree not found elsewhere. But
elsewhere comparable or parallel processes were at work. For instance, the
much-maligned empires, such as the Chinese empire, provided unity in
many ways, while the Islamic religion provided it in the Muslim world. It
\ has also been argued that the medieval church compensated for the
political fragmentation of Europe, allowing pan-European development
■ to take place in spite of the lack of a clear pattern of strong states. True.
The question is comparative: did the church thereby give Europe some
developmental advantage over other civilizations, in which, quite often,
there was political unity throughout most historical epochs? I think the
answer must be that the church did not give Europe some special cultural
quality, lacking in other civilizations, such that Europe could thereby leap
into the forefront of social evolution.
Therefore I see no basis in fact for suggestions that the medieval
church led to European historical superiority in a way that other religious
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
institutions, in other civilizations, did not do. John A. Hall, for instance,
asserts that "Christianity provided the best shell for the emergence of
states." 155 Michael Mann claims that the medieval church "encouraged a
drive for moral and social improvement even against worldly au-
thority" — a statement that one might question not merely as a
comparison, but also as a factual assertion about the role played by the
church in Europe. 156 For H. E. Hallam, "the medieval Latin church was
the seed-bed of the early modern idea of capitalism." 157 K. E Werner
maintains that "the 'European miracle' [took place] . . . because of the
existence of a Christian world dominated in the west by Catholic
doctrines." 158 Such statements fail as comparisons with other religions,
and other civilizations; but they also fail because the postulated rise of
Europe did not take place in the Middle Ages but somewhat later. That
Christianity helped in that eventual rise is not at all in question.
It is not necessary to discuss Max Weber's celebrated argument about
the role of religion in the rise of Europe, or his celebrated argument about
the special role of the Protestant Reformation in the rise of capitalism.
Weber of course held the views that I criticized above. But the causal role
of religion is not at issue in this book, the concern of which is a
uniformitarian view of European and non-European civilizations and
their dynamism.
Class
Three kinds of argument concerning class are relevant to our discussion.
The first of these is a two-tiered argument for Europe's ancient and
medieval historical superiority that can be summarized as follows: (1)
Classless (or "preclass") regions and peoples are simply irrelevant in the
matter of explaining Europe's superiority and the world's historical
progress, because classless societies are necessarily both unprogressive and
primitive. (2) Therefore, the real problems calling for explanation
concern the question why some class-stratified societies (the European
ones) are progressive while others (principally Asian) are stagnant and
backward. Africa below the Sahara is then declared sweepingly to be
classless and thus irrelevant to world history. This argument is still widely
used, in some analytical works (among them Eric L. Jones's The European
Miracle), in some world-history textbooks (as we noted in Chapter 1), and
in some (probably most) modern atlases of world history. (Many of these
atlases have no maps of Africa for the whole of history from the Upper
Paleolithic to 1492 ! 159 ) In place of an extended discussion of this issue I
will just offer these comments: Africa was not classless in 1492 (a point to
which we return in Chapter 3), classless societies are not stagnant, 160 and
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
the historians who make this sort of argument about classlessness quite
regularly contradict themselves by declaring that the classless European
peoples of ancient and medieval times — the "barbarian tribes," Germans,
Celts, Slavs, etc. — were very progressive: after borrowing the idea of
classes and a few other things from the Romans, these primitive but
supposedly progressive, innovative, aggressive, inquisitive, achievement-
oriented Europeans than surged forward to modernity.
It is customary and quite proper to examine the class structure of a
society in history and ask how the different classes acted to favor or resist
change, and in which directions. In the absence of such an examination,
we usually get an analysis with a bias toward ascribing causality solely to
kings and other sorts of elites. Eurocentrism becomes a problem only if the
assertion is made that a given class did something historically efficacious
in Europe but that this class did not exist in civilizations outside of
Europe. This kind of argument is very common in the European miracle
literature. Although especially favored among conservative historians, it
is also found quite often among those Marxists who cling to the old
formulas about the "stages of class society." Fairly representative of the
latter is Padgug's argument that a slave mode of production, in its pure
form — with slavery dominant in commodity production and with
implications for economic progress, the development of private property,
and class struggle — existed in ancient times only in Greece and Rome,
and that lack of this feature in Asia accounts in part for the tendency of
Asian societies to "stagnate." 161 (Roughly the same argument is then used
by some Marxists to assert that the slave-plantation system of later times
was not properly capitalist because the workers were slaves, not
wage-earners. We deal with this point in Chapter 4.) This issue is
important, but I will set it aside after one comment: I believe that those
scholars who assert that the slave class was more important in the classical
Mediterranean than Asia make a very elementary error, perhaps easiest to
do if one is not a geographer. It may just be a question of geographical
scale. The Athenian empire was perhaps one-hundredth the size of the
Ch'in empire. In small, highly developed regions of China, slavery was
very likely as important as it was in Attica or in the plantation regions of
Roman Italy.
Jean Baechler, a French historical sociologist, has argued that one
uniquely European class, the medieval aristocracy, was the central causal
force in the European miracle. 162 He dismisses Africa out of hand, then
asks why it is that modernity arose in Europe and not in Asia. 163
Accepting many of the standard arguments as partial explanations, he
argues that the most important reason the miracle occurred was the
existence in Europe of a true aristocracy. Baechler describes an ancient
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Indo-European society characterized by its warrior aristocracy. In India,
the aristocracy became corrupted, but not so in Europe. 16- * He carefully
defines the medieval aristocracy and its special social quality, "feudality,"
in such a way as to distinguish it from a mere landlord class, or a class of
landlords with added seigneurial powers. The aristocracy was a band of
comrades, equals joined by bonds of feudal loyalty, a democracy in its own
right. It did not, he says, hold the political power in society, and this was
a key to its unique character. Elsewhere, either the aristocracy was ground
under by the (imperial, despotic) polity, or it became corrupted into a
caste form, as in India; in such cases there was to be no modernization.
The European aristocracy had a special sort of private power, one original
source of capitalist power. (Baechler contradicts himself here, since in the
feudal era the aristocracy was indeed the political power. He simply notes
that there was a time of political chaos, and passes on to other matters. 165 )
In sum, the aristocracy invents democracy and incipient capitalist
property. The European peasants are also incipient capitalists from early
on. Baechler casts aside the idea that Europe's peasantry was an unfree,
oppressed community in the Middle Ages and gives it quite remarkable
qualities: The peasant village was self-governed, a kind of "republic," with
characteristics reminiscent of urban life. 166 "A peasant is an entrepreneur
in miniature." 167 By the fourteenth century this incipiently capitalist
peasant is the real peasant of Europe. The peasant village is a little
democracy. The peasants are autonomous decision-makers. Baechler
simply ignores serfdom, ignores, likewise, the importance of the fact that
the lords owned the land, exploited the peasants, and controlled their
lives. Feudalism becomes a kind of democratic society in which the
aristocrats play a democratic role and the peasants live as free people.
Moreover, these peasants, deep in the Middle Ages, had all of the
attributes of the capitalist farmer that we associate with the eighteenth
century and thereafter: investment, profit orientation, capital accumula-
tion. (And they were smart enough, Baechler says, to avoid the extended
family.) All of this is fantasy. It is a simple telescoping of history, pushing
the modern world (and particularly the modern capitalist farmer) back
into the Middle Ages.
Baechler contrasts all of this with India. His depiction of India is
bizarre. India had no aristocracy throughout history, as a result of the caste
system, and this is the "deepest cause" for its failure to develop throughout
history. 168 (India did have a very formidable aristocracy.) Indian society
had no political dimension: "The polity .... is not a reality in India."
Therefore "the sense of identity in India could never be political" — not
to say democratic. 169 (Nonsense.) Caste was invented to take the place of
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
the missing polity. (More nonsense.) India didn't have a peasantry, it
merely had "agricultural workers." 170 How can this be true? Because real
peasants were entrepreneurial decisionmakers, something supposedly
absent in India (but in reality no more so than in Europe). Baechler thus
uses a mythical India as a counterpoint to his basic argument: In Europe,
aristocrats and the free society created by them (and their allies the
peasants) were the principal source of the "miracle." But Europe's
aristocracy and peasantry did not have these romanticized qualities, and,
more crucially, comparable classes existed in many other regions in the
same period, as we will see in Chapter 3.
In Marxist theory, the concept of class is part of a larger and more
consequential notion, that of class struggle. For all class-stratified
societies, said Marx and Engels, class struggle is the motor of progress.
Most present-day Marxists consider cultural evolution to be very much
more complex than this, but they continue to emphasize the idea, and
process, of class struggle. Again we must notice that there is nothing
inherently Eurocentric about this concept unless one argues that genuine
class struggle, or some phase or form of it, occurs only in Europe. But many
Marxists argue precisely that way. According to Maurice Godelier, for
example, the West displays "the purest forms of class struggle" and "alone
has created the conditions for transcending . . . class organization." 171
Probably the most influential recent formulation of this sort of argument
is Robert Brenner's theory about the rise of capitalism. 172 Brenner tries to
demonstrate that the rise of capitalism prior to 1492 was a result of class
struggle, but class struggle only in Europe. Then he uses this argument as
evidence against what he calls "Third- Worldism," the belief that
non-Europe has been of great importance historically and is so
(politically) in the present. This conclusion has strongly influenced not
only Marxist but also conservative thought in history, geography,
• sociology, and economic-development theory. Certainly the Brenner
theory deserves our attention in this book. And it is not at all a
complicated theory.
According to Brenner, class struggle between serfs and lords, influ-
enced by depopulation, led to the decline of feudalism in northwestern
Europe. (Brenner does not mention non-Europe and scarcely mentions
southern Europe.) In most parts of northwestern Europe, the peasants won
this class struggle and became in essence petty landowners, now satisfied
with their bucolic existence and unwilling to innovate. Only in England
did the lords maintain their grip on the land; peasants thus remained
tenants. The peasantry then became differentiated, producing a class of
landless laborers and a rising class of larger tenant farmers, wealthy enough
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
to rent substantial holdings and forced (because they had to pay rent) to
commercialize, innovate technologically, and thus become capitalists.
(Brenner thinks that serfs, lords, and landowning peasants did not inno-
vate, and that towns, even English towns, had only a minor role in the rise
of capitalism.) English yeoman tenant farmers, therefore, were the foun-
ders of capitalism. Stated differently: capitalism arose because English
peasants lost the class struggle. In reality, however, peasants were not
predominantly landowners in the other countries of the region; capitalism
grew more rapidly in and near the towns than in the rural countryside; and
the technological innovativeness that Brenner attributes to fourteenth
and fifteenth century English farmers really occurred much later, too late
to fit into his theory. More importantly, commercial farming and indeed
urban protocapitalism were developing during this period in southern
Europe and (as I will argue) in other continents. Brenner's theory is simply
wrong. 173
Family
There is nothing new about the belief that the European family is in some
fundamental sense more rational and more civilized than the family types
found elsewhere. When the modernization doctrine became dominant,
this belief seems to have faded into the background; there was now a
near-consensus among social scientists that differences in family type
should be strung along the continuum from "traditional" to "modern" or,
as a variation, from "folk" to "urban." Traditional families, it was argued,
have tended to reflect strong kinship ties at a scale larger and wider than
the nuclear family; they have tended to form large, extended-family
households; and they have tended to be associated with high birthrates. In
the absence of much evidence concerning the medieval European family
and household, it was rather widely assumed that earlier European
families had conformed to the traditional model, which was seen as the
"preindustrial" family, contrasted with the'modern, post-industrial-revo-
lution nuclear family, forming a small household, with looser kin ties
beyond the household, and with fewer children. This transformation was
thought to be associated with what was called the "demographic transi-
tion," the process of change from a "traditional" demographic pattern,
with high birthrate and high deathrate, characteristic of preindustrial
conditions, to a "modern," postindustrial demographic pattern, with low
birthrate and low deathrate.
In the modernization theory of the family, the non-European world
of underdeveloped countries would go through essentially the same
transformation as it modernized. Extended family households would be
replaced by nuclear family households. This would instill modern
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
prodevelopment attitudes: people would have fewer children (thus
combating overpopulation), and they would tend, now, to think more
individualistically and thus entrepreneurially.
All of this was a bundle of assumptions. There was no evidence of a
causal link between birthrate and size of household (or strength of kin ties
beyond the nuclear family); there was merely a correlation within rich,
modern societies: both nuclear families and lower birthrates were
characteristic of these societies. (One leading demographer pointed out
that nuclear families might, in principle, be likely to have more children
per couple than extended families. 174 ) In addition, the idea that an adult
breadwinner would be more entrepreneurial, more prone to accumulate
capital, more competitive, and so on, if he (assumed to be male) was
working only for his wife and children and not for a large family including
his parents, cousins, and other relations, was a tenuous assumption. Large,
tightly knit families had proven to be powerful accumulators, for instance,
among many immigrant groups engaged in commerce. Why, indeed,
should an adult want to work harder only for spouse and children, and not
for parents, sisters, and so on? (One can in fact construct an argument to
the effect that an extended family with multiple working adults has
definite economic advantages in a developing economy. 175 ) As the
modernization doctrine itself developed, after about 1960, these ideas
began to dissipate. It became clear that various forms of social
organization can be equally modern, and that the root causes of change
and nonchange do not lie in the family structure.
Rather dramatically, in the midA960s, the notion of a peculiarly
European family pattern was reinserted into historians' common
discourse, partly as a result of an influential paper by John Hajnal. 176 As
we noted at an earlier point in this chapter, in the discussion of
demographic arguments for the "miracle," historical demography was at
that time uncovering evidence that preindustrial Europe (or part of
Europe) had a lower birthrate than one would expect of a "traditional
society." It seemed that Europeans had been marrying later in life than
would be expected in a traditional society with Malthusian controls and
therefore maximum birthrate. Instead of scrapping the Malthusian model
itself, and arguing instead that all human societies actively control their
population dynamics by using such tactics as adjusting the age of
marriage, these historians began to assert, simply, the uniqueness of
Europe. Other preindustrial societies exhibited the "traditional" pattern,
with high and uncontrolled birthrates (and therefore superrapid
population growth when mortality declined in the "transition").
Preindustrial Europe, in complete contrast, had a rational family system,
with rational population control. It was then argued, without evidence,
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
that preindustrial Europe had a higher level of living and a lower
mortality rate than non-Europe, from which it was deduced that Europe
kept its birthrate down in proper, rational, adjustment to its lower
deathrate, mainly using the mechanism of delayed marriage. Those who
put forward this argument simply failed to consider the possibility that
families in other societies have acted pretty much the same way. Evidence
to this effect was beginning to appear from a number of non-European
societies. Some societies had much lower birthrates than would be
expected from the classic model. Other societies had demonstrated major
shifts in birthrate, either upward or downward, in response to changes in
economic and other conditions. 17 7
Hajnal began his 1965 essay with this flat statement:
The marriage pattern of most of Europe as it existed for at least two
centuries up to 1940 was, as far as we can tell, unique or almost unique in
the world. There is no known example of a population of non-European
civilization which has had a similar pattern. The distinctive marks of the
"European pattern" are (1) a high age of marriage and (2) a high proportion
of people who never marry at all. 178
Hajnal's argument was in some ways very careful and in others very casual.
He noted carefully that the evidence for late marriage and (somewhat)
low marriage frequency in Europe for periods before the seventeenth
century was inconclusive, and that the "fragmentary" evidence for the
European Middle Ages suggested a "non-European pattern." 179 He
introduced absolutely no historical data for non-European regions,
casually comparing historical Europe with twentieth-century non-Europe.
The theoretical constraint is very clear: non-European patterns are
"traditional" and permanent, hence a comparison of seventeenth-century
Europe with mid-twentieth-century Asia or Africa is perfectly accepta-
ble. 180
This proposition about the unique European pattern of later
marriages and lower marriage frequencies was widely and quickly
incorporated into the broader theory of Europe's historical "miracle."
Without much supporting evidence, the proposition was firmly pushed
backward into the Middle Ages. According to Lawrence Stone, writing in
1977, "it has now been established beyond any doubt" that over most of
northwest Europe the middle and lower classes "married remarkably late,
certainly from the fifteenth century onward. . . . This custom of delayed
marriage is an extraordinary and unique feature of north-west European
civilization." 181 Here one notices particularly the word "remarkably."
This is "remarkable" only if there is something to compare it with; yet
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
non-European historical data are not given or even sought. Michael
Mann derives the pattern from the Iron Age Indo-European peasant
society. Patricia Crone speculates that it is perhaps an ancient Germanic
trait. Eric L. Jones thinks that it goes back three or four thousand years.
Alan Macfarlane thinks that it has its roots in "a particular amalgam of
Christianity and Germanic customs." 182 And so on. In a word: the
pattern is very old in Europe.
The matter of dates, or age, is certainly crucial. Western Europe was
undergoing major transformations from the seventeenth century onward,
and a delayed and lower marriage rate could well be explained by a
number of the newer facts: mobility, loss of holdings due to enclosures,
urbanization, and, later, the well-understood demographic and social
effects of the industrial revolution. Even the sixteenth century was
somewhat chaotic in western Europe. But if the marriage pattern emerged
before 1492, a date before these disruptions began, then one can speak of
a definite "European pattern," not merely a "preindustrial" or "tradi-
tional" pattern. And one can begin to build a general causal theory for the
subsequent changes — the "European miracle."
Additional propositions were added. It had long been known that
nuclear family households and neolocal residence (the married couple
establishes a household well separated from those of the parents) have
been characteristic of western Europe during recent centuries, and this is
to be expected as a feature of modernization. It fits with standard
modernization theory: the process is supposed to lead from extended
family to nuclear family. But the European miracle historians now argue
that nuclear families and neolocal residence are part of a unique
"European familial system" (Laslett). 183 And again they locate its origin
far back in history. And again they sweepingly assert that non-Europeans
lack these patterns. In fact, there is good evidence that nuclear-family
households were common in many parts of non-Europe. Taeuber,
analyzing Buck's data, found that more than 60% of peasant households
in China were nuclear in the early twentieth century. 18 ^ These are not
historical data, but the point is that China is supposed, according to
modernization theory, to be especially "traditional" as regards family and
many other things; indeed, there is common confusion between the
notion of the Chinese lineage or "sib" — made famous by Weber — and the
idea of the extended family. Larger, extended families are uncommon in
Latin America. In India, as well as in China, the notion of an extended
family is ambiguous because of the ambiguity of the notion of "neolocal
residence" (in a cramped village, house-building space can be a problem),
and the association sometimes found between neolocality and available
land upon which to begin a small holding. Further confusion is added
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
over the association between extended (and/or joint) family and
inheritance rights, power, mobility, and more. 185 Meanwhile, back in
Europe, the model of a supposedly characteristic nuclear-neolocal pattern
is subject to very serious questions for the Middle Ages. (For even earlier
times the idea of a unique pattern is speculative, and belongs with other
old and suspect ideas — discussed earlier in this chapter — about the
ancient Germanic tribes and their unique individualism, progressiveness,
and the like.) Medieval marital residence patterns may sometimes have
reflected manor rules (such as assignment of holdings) rather than
cultural residence rules in circumstances of serfdom and insecure tenancy,
and a distinction has to be made between different types of rural regions,
such as the areas with off-farm employment (like woolen areas of
southeastern England), those with "frontier" characteristics, and so on.
There is even reason to question the notion of a persistent west European
marriage pattern. 186 But even granting the generalization about western
Europe, there is no basis for considering the European pattern to have
been, historically, unique. 187
Finally, the model is embellished with some rather gaudy ornamen-
tation. It is claimed that the unique European pattern is not merely a
matter of neolocality, nuclear households, and age and frequency of
marriage. West European marriages were grounded in love. Elsewhere,
marriages were arranged. (But arranged marriages seem to have been the
rule in premodern Europe, prior to the periods of high mobility and social
disruption. The notion, regularly invoked here, that non-European
couples are strangers to one another prior to their being shoved into
marriage is colonial-era prejudice supported by a few unusual cultural
situations. Romantic love in this argument is considered an attribute of
European rationality. Non-European couples are certainly as loving as
European couples.) It is claimed, next, that the unique European family,
because it is nuclear, produces a unique European personality type. The
theory is that the small (European) household leads inevitably to
individualistic, competitive, acquisitive, yet caring behavior. Mann and
Jones, as we saw earlier, put forward the image of an ancient peasant
household, a Hansel and Gretel house deep in the forest, as the historical
source of this individualistic pattern. Macfarlane, who presents perhaps
the most extreme form of this theory (and is chided by some of his
colleagues not for his theory but for his claim that it applies mainly to the
English), argues that the early medieval English family produced a person
with the psychological and behavioral traits of (in essence) Weber's
capitalist personality, that the causal chain runs from tribal customs and
religion to family, from family to personality, and from personality to the
beginnings of capitalism (a point we return to below). This argument is
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
advanced mainly by erecting a model of what Macfarlane considers to be
"peasant society," with a peasant family and peasant mentality. Early
English rural folk don't fit this model. Therefore they were not peasants,
and did not have the traditional traits of peasantry, like a traditional
family type and traditional mentality. 188 As many have commented,
Macfarlane's notion of "peasant" is a straw man, uncharacteristic of
modern non-Europe, much less of historical non-Europe, and his view of
the medieval English farm folk as nonpeasants is historically invalid. 189
The theory of the unique European family is an important part of the
European miracle theory as it is being propagated today. It is used in two
distinct arguments. The first of these combines the family theory with
Malthusianism. The argument runs as follows: Humans in general are not
rational enough to control their sexual behavior and limit the number of
offspring to suit the prevailing conditions of food supply and the like.
Therefore, ordinary humans experience permanent, or periodic, crises, in
which overpopulation leads to famine and war and pestilence, after which
the now-reduced population begins again to overproduce offspring. The
root axiom is irrationality. People behave not intelligently, but (as Mai thus
said 200 years ago) rather like barnyard beasts. 190 The historical result of
this process is to prevent development. Any improvement in, for instance,
productive technology merely leads to population growth, to crisis, to
depopulation, and thus back to the status quo ante — a cycle of stagnation.
This is one and perhaps the crucial cause of the nondevelopment of
non-European societies in general. Europeans, by contrast, have always
(or perhaps for just a millennium or so) exhibited rational behavior in all
matters relating to population. This includes decisions about marriage
and about childbearing. The unique European late-marrying, nuclear,
neolocal, companionate family is the crucial institution in which this
rational decision-making process takes place. Thus the European family
has permitted Europeans (or west Europeans, or northwest Europeans) to
check population growth, and thereby accumulate material wealth that
would otherwise be dissipated in the feeding of excess babies. This
primordial accumulation underlies the permanent progress of Europe.
This theory, in one form or another, is advanced by many of the historians
whom we have been discussing, among them Crone, Hall, Jones, Laslett,
Macfarlane, and Mann. 191 Hall expresses one form of the theory in the
following comment (part of which we quoted earlier):
[The] European family has long been small, late marrying, nuclear and
notably sensitive to Malthusian pressure. . . . The expansion of the Euro-
pean economy did not occur laterally, as in late traditional China, because
improvements in output were not eaten up by a massive growth in
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
population. The ratio between population and acreage in Europe remained
favourable ultimately because of the relative continence of the European
family. 192
The Malthusian theory reduces humans to beasts. But even for those
scholars who accept Malthusianism, the notion that the European family
staves off the Malthusian disasters is hardly credible.
The second way in which the "unique European family" theory is
used in arguments for the European "miracle" is a matter of deducing ways
that the European family produces various sorts of uniquely progressive
attitudes and actions on the part of Europeans, attitudes and actions that
then lead toward the miracle. A very widely used form of this argument is
expressed thusly by Laslett:
[The] European familial system may have been responsible for a whole series
of features conducive to economic progress, and perhaps innovation. The
conditions laid down for marriage and procreation imposed on all
individuals . . . the necessity of saving, accumulating. . . . [The] European
familial system fostered the spirit of hoarding and parsimony. 193
The family thus generates the personality traits of an incipient capitalist,
and does so deep in the Middle Ages. This, too, is hardly credible and
hardly in accord with the realities of life (and psychology) before 1492.
Laslett, like Macfarlane and many others, makes the false assumption that
a typical medieval European family does, in fact, have choices permitting
saving, hoarding, accumulating, and so on. This argument requires that
the peasant family be a substantial landholder, or at least a tenant with
firm security, such that capital accumulation can take place and not be
bled off by master or landlord. There is much dispute about the degree of
landownership in late-medieval western Europe, but it is certain that
family behavior of the sort described by Laslett could not have been
common under serfdom and, after the decline of serfdom, could not have
been common in places where peasants did not own the land. And this
seems to have been the rule, not the exception. 19 4 It appears that this
argument is, again, a telescoping of history. The entrepreneurial yeoman
farmer of, say, the eighteenth century, is pushed back into the Middle
Ages, and an effect becomes a cause.
Many other European-family-to-European-miracle arguments are
common in present-day scholarly discourse, but space permits me to give
only one additional example, from Lawrence Stone:
There are several consequences which must have followed from the late
marriage pattern. . . . [It] is reasonable to assume that for many young men
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
this delay involved considerable sexual denial at a time of optimum male
sexual drive. ... If one follows Freudian theory, this could lead to neuroses.
. . . [It] could help to explain the high level of group aggression, which lay
behind the extraordinary expansionist violence of western nation-states at
this time. It could also have been a stimulus to capitalist economic
enterprise . . . stimulating saving in order to marry, and generating activist
social and economic dynamism. 195
Again:
The sublimation of sex among young male adults may well account for the
extraordinary military aggressiveness, the thrift, the passion for hard work,
and the entrepreneurial and intellectual enterprise of modern Western
man. 196
Europeans conquered the world because their young men were sexually
frustrated.
Space does not permit us to list and discuss all of the other common
or garden-variety explanations for the so-called European miracle. Some
additional explanations will be mentioned in various contexts at later
points in this book. But I hope that the discussion in this chapter has
sufficiently made the point that no characteristic of Europe's environ-
ment, Europe's people, or Europe's culture, at any time prior to 1492, can
be convincingly shown to have had anything to do with the fact that
Europe developed while other civilizations did not do so.
I will try, in the next two chapters, to show that the whole question
must be phrased in a different way and answered in a different way. Europe
did not rise, relative to the other civilizations, prior to 1492. When Europe
did rise, after 1492, this reflected, not some special quality of
"Europeanness," but the immense wealth which came into Europe as a
result of colonialism in the sixteenth century and thereafter.
NOTES
1. Although Eric L. Jones's 1981 book The European Miracle popularized the
phrase "the European miracle," it had been in use for a long time with the same
essential meaning: the unique rise of Europe before or during the Middle Ages. Not
every historian would describe this as a "miracle," but the term has wide acceptance,
as evidence the fact that an international symposium entitled "The European
Miracle" was held at Cambridge University in 1985.
2. Apparently my 1976 article, "Where Was Capitalism Born?" was the first
publication to reject the "miracle" theory absolutely, that is, without qualification. In
1990 Samir Amin, commenting on a later paper of mine, indicated his basic
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
agreement with this rejectionist position. (Amin, "Colonialism and the Rise of
Capitalism: A Comment," 1990; Blaut, "Colonialism and the Rise of Capitalism,"
1989; also see Blaut, "Fourteen Ninety-Two," 1992; and Amin, "On Jim Blaut's
'Fourteen Ninety-Two,'" 1992.) A few other historians have taken positions
approaching this one; their views are discussed later in this chapter.
3. Another seminal work was Cyril Black's The Dynamics of Modernization: A
Study in Comparative History (1966). Other such works in various fields will be
discussed later in this chapter.
4. Perhaps one reason was the maturation of the discipline of history itself.
Another was the influence, not entirely salutary, of positivistic scientific method on
history, which led to an attempt to specify variables and "factors," and, if possible,
quantify each of them. Another reason was the loss of faith in the nineteenth-century
idea of inevitable progress: after nearly a half century of chaos and war, progress
definitely did not appear to be something natural and inevitable; it had to be
explained and also produced. Still a third reason was the general secularization of
European thought, including history, such that human events could not be assumed
to reflect guidance of a higher power. Another reason, possibly a very important one,
was the general development of academic disciplines, and their involvement in (and
nutrition from) international and domestic policy. This implied that each discipline,
seeing the world with some degree of bias in favor of its own subject-as-factor (for
economists, the market factor; for psychologists, the motivation factor; for
sociologists, the demographic factor and the social-structural factor; for geographers,
the resource factor; etc.) tended to argue in favor of historical models that treated our
factor as crucial and those of others as secondary. Since many social scientists wrote
history in this process, this led to some special pleading.
5. 1 do not mean to imply that all of this was a dominant theory for the discipline
of history as a whole. The great majority of historical scholars worked on smaller
problems, carefully delving into events and developing limited explanations for those
events. The modernization perspective influenced some of the smaller generalizations,
for instance proffering explanations in which the factors most supportive of
modernizationism were favored — factors like population, technology, and the like.
And there were some areas of research where lack of attention to the history of
non-Europe was a critical source of error (most notably, as we will see, in studies of the
history of European technology). In addition, there were (and are) many different
points of view in the vast and diverse field of professional history, so it would be
questionable to characterize a particular historiographic period as being dominated by
a particular governing theory (or "paradigm"). I suspect that my own concern with
the body of literature relating to the "European miracle" problem probably leads me
to overemphasize the significance of the modernization view on history as a whole. It
should also be noticed that most of the prominent writers about the specific problem
of explaining the unique rise of Europe were specialist historians — economic
historians, historical sociologists, and so forth — and not historians of the standard
breed.
6. Cabral, Unity and Struggle (1979).
7. As to the present and future, Third World intellectuals tended to make two
arguments. Those who supported the idea of a capitalist form of development argued
that economic development must consist of the defense of native capital against the
corrosive diffusion into one's country of the economic and political dominance of
European countries and corporations. For socialists, influence and dominance by
international capitalism quite obviously had to be rejected. Both groups tended to
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
adopt "dependency theory" or "underdevelopment theory," which was a theory both
of history and of modern social processes and development. A relatively small
minority of Third World intellectuals, usually reflecting the thinking and interests of
the very wealthy and very right-wing sectors, welcomed the idea of economic
domination by foreign capitalist interests. Since the wealthy social sectors dominated
most Third World societies, this minority point of view often determined policy.
Also, it received much more prominence than it deserved in the journals of the First
World.
8. See James, A History of Pan- African Revolt (1938), The Black Jacobins (1938),
"The Atlantic Slave Trade and Slavery" (1970); Williams, Capitalism and Slavery
(1944). We discuss these matters in Chapter 4-
9. Amin, Accumulation on a World Scale (1974) and later works. My articles
"Geographic Models of Imperialism" (1970) and "Where Was Capitalism Born?"
(1976) laid out the skeleton of a general theory.
10. I deal with this matter in The National Question (1987b).
11. See Van Leur's 1934 essay "On Early Indonesian trade," reprinted in his
Indonesian Trade and Society (1955).
12. Duyvendak, Ma Huan Re-examined (1933); Needham and collaborators,
Science and Civilization in China, published in 6 volumes between 1965 and 1984;
Wheatley, The Golden Khersonese (1961) and The Pivot of the Four Quarters (1971);
Elvin, The Pattern of the Chinese Past (1973).
13. Amin, Unequal Development (1976), Eurocentrism (1988), "Colonialism and
the Rise of Capitalism: A Comment" (1990).
14 Bernal, Black Athena, vol. 1 (1987) and vol. 2 (1991).
15. Mention should also be made of Eric Wolf's 1982 book Europe and the Peoples
Without History which provides a useful and important survey of the history of both
European and non-European civilizations and shows how unconvincing is the theory
that non-European civilizations, historically, were stagnant and unprogressive (that
they were "peoples without history"). Wolf, however, stops short of questioning the
truly crucial Eurocentric belief that Europeans were more progressive than
non-Europeans in several ways that are crucial to the "European miracle" theory, and
so he does not directly confront that theory. (It should be noted that most mainstream
historians no longer argue that non-European civilizations are, or were, totally
unprogressive, totally "unhistorical," arguing instead about slow rates of change,
"blockages" inhibiting change, and the like — a difference of phrasing which, as we
will see, is not always a difference of argument.)
16. It is always risky to try to explain broad changes of fashion in scholarship,
especially when the changes are still underway, so this interpretation cannot be more
than a hunch, or hypothesis. Scholarly attitudes toward the Third World were very
positive in the period of anticolonial and civil rights struggles. After the late 1960s the
mood changed. Not only did more conservative views come to dominate the Western
world, but rather unexpected difficulties emerged in the Third World itself: national
conflicts, failure of development programs, and more. Western scholarship had never
really abandoned the traditional view of Europe and its relations to non-Europe,
including the diffusionist view of colonialism, and it appears that this older paradigm,
never abandoned, simply became, once again, thoroughly dominant. Certainly the
attention that had been paid previously to dependency theory and related views fell
away among mainstream scholars. Among Marxists the process was even more
dramatic, because it was less expected. In brief, Eurocentric Marxists who dismissed
the role of the Third World both historically and in the present now became virtually
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
the only Marxists within the academic world to pronounce upon issues related to the
Third World. It became quite fashionable to insist, once again, that only the working
class of the advanced capitalist countries can bring about socialism because each stage
of history commences in this part of the world (Inside) before it spreads to the rest of
the world (Outside). In the conservative camp, not only did Eurocentric views regain
their hegemony, but one began, now, to hear whispers of views not far distant from
racism: views about Third World peoples not having the potential to develop.
17. See Brenner, "The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of
Neo-Smithian Marxism" (1977), "Agrarian class structure and economic develop-
ment in pre-industrial Europe" (1985), "The Agrarian roots of European capitalism"
(1985b); Anderson, Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism (1974), Lineages of the
Absolute State (1974); Warren, Imperialism: Pioneer of Capitalism (1980).
18. I will discuss only the more important beliefs, perhaps neglecting a few of
these. And I will give just enough evidence to show that these beliefs are not
self-evidently true. Much fuller evidence is given, to dispute some of the beliefs, in
Chapters 3 and 4.
19. See Chapter 1, note 2.
20. Bowler, The Invention of Progress (1989); Harris, The Rise of Anthropological
Theory (1968); Gossett, Race: The History of an Idea in America (1963); Jackson, Race
and Racism: Essays in Social Geography (1987); Stocking, Race, Culture, and Evolution
(1968); Trigger, A History of Archeological Thought (1989).
21. See Bernal, Black Athena, vol. 1 (1987).
22. See Gossett, Race (1963).
23. Blaut, "The Theory of Cultural Racism" (1992).
24. "Hereditary neuralgia of the presumably strong tendency toward hysteria
and autohypnosis of the Indian . . ." Max Weber, The Religion of India (1967), p. 387.
This postulate is basic to Weber's analysis of Brahminism as prime cause for India's
lack of development.
25. "[The] . . . negroes long ago showed themselves unsuitable for factory work
and the operation of machines; they have not seldom sunk into a cataleptic sleep.
Here is one case in economic history where tangible racial distinctions are present"
Weber, General Economic History ( 1981 ), p. 379. Although Weber says here that this
is merely "one case" of racial influences, note that the case is crucial for Weber's
analysis both of "rationality" and of modernization; the "racial distinctions" here
separate out Africans in a fundamental way: a clear case of moderate yet crucial
racism. In the same vein, "it was found that the American Indians were entirely
unsuitable for plantation labor" (p. 299).
26. Weber, The Religion of China (1951), pp. 231-232. Weber considers these to
be "racial qualities of the Chinese" (p. 230) although cultural factors may be involved.
27. Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1958), p. 30. Weber
says here that "it would be natural to suspect that the most important reason" for the
rationality of the Occident lies in "differences of heredity," and "the importance of
biological heredity," he thinks, is "very great" (p. 30). But we do not yet know how
to measure its influence, so our attention should focus mainly on the cultural factors
(pp. 30-31). This was typical moderate racism (as I call it) for the time the work was
published (1904-1905).
28. I have not discussed the question whether biological racism remains
important today as a genuinely implicit theory, that is, one still accepted but not
consciously so. I suspect that it does. Some Eurocentric historians hold to positions
regarding individual differences between Europeans and non-Europeans that are so
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
extreme, and so bigoted, that it is difficult to avoid the conclusion that at least a few
of them may hold to an implicitly racist infratheory, perhaps unconsciously believing,
that is, that the inferiority of non-Europeans is genetically determined.
29. Among many sources on the racism fallacy, see Franz Boas' classic book,
Race, Language, and Culture (1948); also Blum, Pseudoscience and Mental Ability
(1978); Gossett, Race (1965); Haller, Outcasts from Evolution (1971); Jackson, Race
and Racism ( 1987); Magubane, The Ties that Bind: African' American Consciousness and
Africa (1987); Gill and Levidow, Anti-Racist Science Teaching (1987).
30. The idea that demographic behavior is not fully under social control, is a
primordial biological fact or factor, seems to underlie the thinking of most Eurocentric
historians (conspicuously Eric L. Jones, Michael Mann, and John Hall). The basic
proposition seems to be that population will necessarily grow beyond the rational
limits, and so overpopulation must result unless societies find nondemographic
solutions, notably by increasing food supply to feed the inexorably increasing
population. See, for instance, Michael Mann, The Sources of Social Power, vol. 1
(1986): If agricultural yields had not increased in medieval Europe, "the continent
would . . . have experienced a similar Malthusian cycle every century or so — and
would not have generated capitalism" (p. 402). This view is even encountered,
occasionally, in the radical and feminist movements. Note the following view put
forward by a Marxist-feminist: "[We] assume (given the ubiquity of the sex drive . . .)
that the total number of conceptions in a population will tend to exceed those desired
within a given incentive structure, and this unintended surplus will be greater, the
more imperfect are the means at hand. ... A given fertility pattern then is taken to
be 'rational' . . . except for a small but variable excess [of births]," Seccombe, "Marxism
and Demography," (1983), p. 31. The context is a discussion of European medieval
social evolution, but the argument is given mainly in support of Brenner's theory
about the strictly European rise of capitalism. Most radicals and feminists reject
Malthusianism and would reject Seccombe's view as Malthusian.
31. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 3. Part of the passage is a quotation.
32. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 219.
33. Hall, Powers and Liberties: The Causes and Consequences of the Rise of the West
(1985), p. 131. Italics added.
34. As F. Hassan points out, "Among human populations the practice of
population control in one form or another is universal." ("Demographic Archeology,"
1978, p. 71.)
35. Some families will of course have more conceptions than desired, and others
fewer, because birth control techniques are imperfect, but the average for the larger
group will be broadly in line with the group's values and population targets. The
techniques run the gamut from variable age of marriage and variable dowry or bride
price, to complexity of marriage rules (defining who, in a kin system, is eligible to be
one's spouse), to timing of sexual relations, to the use of antifertility and abortive
devices, to infanticide, and other practices.
36. Much of the scholarship comes from India, where colonial ideology used to
claim that poverty is a result of people having too many children. Now demographers
and other social scientists have disproven this myth. See, for instance, Mamdani, The
Myth of Population Control (1972), and Nag, "How Modernization Can Also Increase
Fertility" (1980). For Africa, see, for example, Kitching, "Proto-Industrialization and
Demographic Change" (1983); Swindell, "Domestic Production, Labor Mobility, and
Population Change in West Africa, 1900-1980" (1981); Cordell and Gregory, the
introduction to African Population and Capitalism (1987).
140 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
37. See, for instance, numerous studies showing the plasticity of birthrates,
including Nag "How Modernization Can Also Increase Fertility" (1980), Collyer,
Birth Rates in Latin America ( 1 965 ) , and Harewood, "Population Growth in Grenada"
(1966).
38. See Aston and Philpin, eds., The Brenner Debate (1985), especially the
introduction by R. Hilton.
39. Perhaps more readily, because the Malthusian explanation for poverty in
Third World countries has been a rather troublesome issue for scholars and planners
in these countries, and it has been important to show that poverty in their countries
is not somehow caused by the demographic misbehavior of ordinary people.
40. For instance Montesquieu, in The Spirit of the Laws ([1748] 1949) "People are
. . . more vigorous in cold climates" (pt. xiv.2). "There are countries where the excess
of heat enervates the body, and renders men . . . slothful and dispirited" (pt. xv.7).
4 1 . "Africa" almost always refers to "Africa south of the Sahara" in the discourse
I am criticizing, so I will use "Africa" in the same sense in the present discussion.
42. Blaut, "The Ecology of Tropical Farming Systems" (1963).
43. See, for example, Collins and Roberts, eds., Capacity for Work in the Tropics
(1988), which fails to find convincing evidence suggesting negative tropical effects.
44. The two citations (Gilfillan, "The Coldward Course of Progress," 1920, and
Lambert, "The Role of Climate in the Economic Development of Nations," 197 1 ) are
hardly indicative of modem scholarly literature.
45. India's "debilitating climate" is one reason why India fell behind Europe,
according to Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 198.
46. Among the pioneer works which have importance for peasant agriculture,
we may mention Fred Hardy's "Some Aspects of Tropical Soils" (1936) and various
of his articles in Tropical Agriculture, and the work of Robert Pendleton (especially
Pendleton, "Land Use in North-Eastern Thailand," 1943, and Prescott and
Pendleton, Laterites and Lateritic Soils, 1952), and G. Milne "A Soil Reconnaissance
Journey Through Parts of Tanganyika Territory" (1947). The first comprehensive
textbook on tropical soils embodying modern knowledge is Mohr and van Baren,
Tropical Soils (1954).
47. See Nye and Greenland, The Soil Under Shifting Cultivation (1960); Blaut,
"The Nature and Effects of Shifting Agriculture" (1962); Ahn, West African Soils
(1970).
48. See Miller, Way of Death (1988); Curtin, The Rise and Fall of the Plantation
Complex (1990). The view is echoed in many world history textbooks, for example,
Roberts, The Hutchinson History of The World (1987), pp. 54-56; McNeill, A World
History (1967), pp. 273-278.
49. See Wilken, Good Fanners: Traditional Agricultural Resource Management in
Mexico and Centra! America (1987); also Nye and Greenland, The Soil Under Shifting
Agriculture (1960); Blaut, "The Ecology of Tropical Farming Systems" (1963).
50. Denevan, The Native Population of the Americas in 1492 (1976).
51. See Cockburn and Hecht, The Fate of the Forest (1989).
52. These marginal areas often are regions in which agriculture is practiced, in
preference to some less intensive system of land use, because human communities
have been pushed off better land by historical forces, notably colonialism.
53. For a typical instance, the Oxford historian J. M. Roberts, in his popular
world history textbook, The Hutchinson History of the World (1987), makes the
following quite ignorant statement: "Probably the greatest importance of [the] spread
of iron-working [in tropical Africa] was the difference it made to agriculture. It made
possible a new penetration of the forests, new tilling of the soil (which may be
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
connected with the arrival of new food-crops from Asia ...)... This suggests once
again the important limiting factor of the African environment. Most of the
continent's history is the story of response to influences from the outside [including
iron-working and new crops)" (pp. 511-512). African farmers, like farmers in Europe
and many other regions, practiced agriculture with stone tools before iron arrived, and
continued to do so afterward whenever and wherever iron was hard to obtain. On the
age of ironworking in tropical Africa, see, for example, Wai-Andah, "West Africa
Before the Seventh Century" (1981) and Sinclair, "Archeology in Eastern Africa"
(1991).
54. See, for example, Roberts (note 53 above); also Irwin, "Sub-Saharan
Africa," in Garraty and Gay, eds. The Columbia History of the World (1981), p. 299.
55. See for instance Irvine's classical work, A Textbook of West African
Agriculture (1934); Coursey, Yams (1967).
56. According to Jones, The European Miracle (1981), "the Negroid peoples . . .
were still pushing east and south into the territories of the pygmies and the bushmen
when the Boers undertook the Great Trek north from the Cape in the 1830s," (p.
155). Also see Roberts The Hutchinson History of the World (1987), p. 178.
57. Curtin, Economic Change in Pre-Colonial Africa (1975); Curtin, The Rise and
Fall of the Plantation Complex (1990); Miller, Way of Death (1988).
58. See Wisner and Mbithi, "Drought in Eastern Kenya" (1974); Wisner, Power
and Need in Africa (1989); O'Keefe and Wisner, "African Drought: The State of the
Game" (1975).
59. The same arguments apply, with no need for qualification, in Western
Hemisphere agriculture. In relatively limited parts of the South American rain forest
the ecosystem is so fragile, as a result of local geological conditions (rocks forming
infertile kaolinitic clay soils in some areas, almost pure sands in other areas), that
cropping systems must employ shifting agriculture (or tree crops). But such areas are
the exception within the present-day distribution of rain forest environments. In
general, the great sweep of Amazonian and Guianan rain forest is a zone of
nonsedentary agriculture because of cultural-historical factors, notably depopulation
and the massive increase in cattle ranching. It is in fact cattle ranching, and not
shifting agriculture, that leads to agriculturally caused long-term environmental
degradation in the rainforest region, because (1) ranchers burn forest to the maximum
extent possible and without control, in order to expand the area of pasture, and (2)
the resulting pasture leads to steady soil degradation because coarse pasture grasses do
not maintain the soil ecosystem as does the original forest. Shifting cultivators, by
contrast, burn only under controlled conditions, burn small areas only, and carefully
encourage the regrowth of forest. If the forest disappears, their livelihood disappears.
Shifting agriculturists should not be blamed for deforestation anywhere in the humid
tropics. See Hecht and Cockburn, The Fate of the Forest (1989); Blaut, "The Nature
and Effects of Shifting Agriculture" (1963).
60. Buckle, The History of Civilization in England, 2nd ed., (1913), chap. 2. Also
see Bowler, The Invention of Progress (1989), pp. 28-29.
61. Marx, Capital, vol. 1 (1976), p. 513n.
62. Jones in fact manages to use both of the opposing theories toward the same
end. In wetter regions of Africa "living was easy." In drier areas "agriculture was not
productive." Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 154. Also see Jones, Growth
Recurring: Economic Change in World History (1988).
63. "In Africa the bountifulness and extent of the land makes for a mobile
peasantry, necessarily therefore poor material on which to build states. Something like
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
this is probably true of all slash-and-bum agriculture," John Hall, Powers and Liberties
(1985), p. 27. ("Slash-and-burn agriculture" is shifting agriculture.)
64. Laibman, "Modes of Production and Theories of Transition" (1984), p. 284.
However, Laibman's overall argument is not at all Eurocentric.
65. Buckle, History of Civilization in England, vol. 1, 2nd ed. (1913), p. 93: "[The]
great plagues by which Europe has at different periods been scourged, have, for the
most part, proceeded from the East, which is their natural birthplace, and where they
are most fatal. Indeed, of those cruel diseases now existing in Europe, scarcely one is
indigenous; and the worst of them were imported from tropical countries in and after
the first century of the Christian era."
66. The theory that the HIV virus which causes AIDS in humans is another one
of these African plagues descending upon the Western World may very well be just
the newest myth in this old diffusionist tradition. Whether or not this virus originated
in Africa, which has not been proven, the myth has already taken on ugly overtones,
as in the completely unfounded (yet classical) belief that AIDS was transmitted from
monkeys to humans because of some strange sexual practices in some obscure African
tribes. (This myth is naively reported in Shannon and Pyle, "The Origin and
Diffusion of AIDS," 1989. See the critique of this paper by Watts and Okello,
"Medical Geography and AIDS," 1990. Also see R. C. and R. J. Chirimuuta, AIDS,
Africa and racism, 2nd ed., 1989.)
67. McNeill, Plagues and Peoples (1976), p. 43.
68. See, for instance, Giblin, "Trypanosomiasis Control in African History: An
Evaded Issue?" (1990); Turshen, "Population Growth and the Deterioration of
Health: Mainland Tanzania, 1920-1960" (1987).
69. Wittfogel, Oriental Despotism (1957).
70. See Venturi "The History of the Concept of 'Oriental Despotism' in
Europe" (1963); P. Anderson, Lineages of the Absolute State (1974); B. Chandra, "Karl
Marx, His Theories of Asian Societies, and Colonial Rule" (1981).
71. Similar judgments are still commonly made by theoreticians of the European
miracle. For instance, John Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), p. 12: "Chinese society
was stuck in the same stage for over two thousand years, while Europe, in comparison,
progressed like a champion hurdler."
72. And also earlier. It is discussed for instance by Montesquieu, Bernier, Adam
Smith, and Hegel (see, for instance, "Introduction," and "The Oriental World" in
Hegel's Philosophy of History, 1956). Also see the historical reviews in Venturi, "The
History of the Concept of 'Oriental Despotism' in Europe" (1963); P. Anderson,
Lineages of the Absolute State (1974); and B. Chandra, "Karl Marx, his Theories of
Asian Societies, and Colonial Review" (1981).
73. This idea, too, had its forerunners. Possibly Marx got the idea from Karl
Ritter, his professor of geography at Berlin.
74. Marx and Engels, Selected Conespondence (1975).
75. Marx and Engels considered other factors as well, and it is fair to say that
their analysis remained speculative. I believe that Engels withdrew from the idea of
"Oriental despotism" in late life. See the discussion of this topic in P. Anderson,
Lineages of the Absolute State (1974); Blaut, "Colonialism and the Rise of Capitalism"
(1989); and B. Chandra, "Karl Marx, His Theories of Asian Societies, and Colonial
Rule" (1981).
76. See Laibman, "Modes of Production and Theories of Transition" (1984),
and Bailey and Llobera, The Asiatic Mode of Production (1981).
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
77. Weber, The Agrarian Sociology of Ancient Civilizations (1976), pp. 84, 131,
157, The Religion of China (1951), pp. 16, 21, 25, and "The Origin of Seigneurial
Proprietorship," part 1, chap. 3, esp. pp. 56-57 in General Economic History (1981).
Also see McNeill, Plagues and Peoples (1976), pp. 93, 207, 259.
78. Weber, The Agrarian Sociobgy of Ancient Civilizations (1976), pp. 157-158.
Also, on p. 84: "The basis of the economy [in Egypt] was irrigation, for this was the
crucial factor in all exploitation of land resources. Every new settlement demanded
construction of a canal . . . Now canal construction is necessarily a large-scale
operation, demanding some sort of collective social organization; it is very different
from the relatively individualistic activity of clearing virgin forest. Here then is the
fundamental economic cause for the overwhelmingly dominant position of the
monarchy in Mesopotamia [and] Egypt.
79. See, for instance, Denevan, The Aboriginal Cultural Geography of the Llanos
de Mojos of Bolivia (1966), and "Hydraulic Agriculture in the American Tropics"
(1982), on ancient drained-field or raised-field agriculture in the tropics; Golson,
"No Room at the Top: Agricultural Intensification in the New Guinea Highlands"
(1977), on ancient drainage in highland New Guinea; Doolittle, Canal Irrigation in
Prehistoric Mexico (1990), on drainage and early agriculture in Mexico; Harrison and
Turner Pre-Hispanic Maya Agriculture (1978), on early drainage in the Maya
lowlands.
80. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), pp. 8-9.
81. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), pp. 12-13, 27-28, 36, 42-3, 53, 59, 99,
102, 137.
82. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), p. 11. Also see pp. 41, 123, 132.
83. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986). Also see his essay, "European
Development: Approaching a Historical Explanation" (1988).
84. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), p. 94.
85. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), p. 179.
86. The fact that Mann attributes the ancient European takeoff mainly to
chariot warfare and iron-plow rainfall-farming, yet concedes that both innovations
were initiated by Middle Easterners themselves, suggests to me that Mann's
fundamental causal reasoning centers on the notion of European rationality:
regardless of who invented these things, the Europeans put the things to work. That
this Weberian notion is indeed basic for Mann will be demonstrated later in this
chapter.
87. Bray, Agriculture, vol. 6, part 2, of Needham and collaborators, Science and
Civilization in China (1984).
88. Blaut, "Two Views of Diffusion" (1977).
89. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), pp. 247, 406, 408, 412, 504-510,
520, 530, 539-540.
90. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), p. 509.
91. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), p. 99.
92. Hall, Powers andLiberties (1985), p. 110.
93. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 10.
94. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 47.
95. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 8. Jones makes the common error of
assuming that productivity per worker is low in irrigated agriculture in comparison
with unirrigated agriculture. This is not the case. Even with draft animals, medieval
peasant production per worker was not high. And draft animals are used in irrigated
farming, abundantly so in some Asian wet-rice farming systems.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
96. Mann, "European Development" (1988), p. 10, The Sources of Social Power
(1986), p. 406; Jones, The European Miracle (1981), pp. 90, 227; Crone, Pre-lndustrial
Societies (1989), p. 150; McNeill, Plagues and Peoples (1976), p. 295.
97. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986, chap. 5). Mann in fact builds a
theory of ancient warfare upon the basis of this sort of calculation, here also ignoring
the fact that armies then as now provision themselves and their animals on the route
of march.
98. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), chap. 2 and elsewhere. Hall, Powers and
Liberties (1985), p. 132, makes the same claim, citing Jones.
99. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), p. Ill; Jones The European Miracle (1981),
pp. 90, 105, 107, 226-227; Mann, "European Development: Approaching a Historical
Explanation" (1988), p. 10; Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), p. 406.
100. Occasionally "the criminal mind" was seen to reflect another dimension of
contrast.
101. Levy-Bruhl, How Natives Think (1966).
102. See, for instance, Boas, The Mind of Primitive Man (1938); Radin, Primitive
Man as Philosopher (1927); M. Mead, Growing Up in New Guinea (1930).
103. Stocking, Victorian Anthropology (1987), p. 59; Bowler, The Invention of
Progress (1989), p. 66; Whitman "From Philology to Anthropology in Mid-
Nineteenth-Century Germany" (1984); Bernal, Black Athena, vol. 1 (1987); Said,
Orientalism (1978). A recent expression of this theory came in a Soviet debate about
"Oriental despotism" (Lelekov, "Round-Table: State and Law in the Ancient
Orient," 1978). L. Lelekov, a historian, claimed that words meaning "freedom" and
"right" were basic in the original Indo-European language or languages but not in
Near Eastern languages, and asserted that this must have affected "social thinking" (p.
190). This contention was refuted by the philologist V. Ivanov (p. 193).
104. See Dalai, "The Racism of Jung" (1988). In Jung's work, see in particular
PsychologicalTypes (1971) (for instance: "[If] we go right back to primitive psychology,
we find absolutely no trace of the concept of the individual," p. 10); Memories,
Dreams, Reflections (1963), and "The Dreamlike World of India," in Civilisation in
Transition (1927). See also the 1954 work by Jung's disciple Erich Neumann, The
Origins and History of Consciousness (for instance: "The evolution of consciousness as
a form of creative evolution is the peculiar achievement of Western man . . . The
creative character of consciousness is a central feature of the cultural canon of the
West ... In stationary cultures, or in primitive societies where the original features of
human culture are still preserved, the earliest stages of man's psychology
predominate," pp. xviii-xix).
105. Piaget, Psychology and Epistemology (1971), p. 61.
106. See, for example, Werner and Kaplan, Symbol Formation (1964).
107. See the first 16 volumes (through 1985) of The Journal of Cross-Cultural
Psychology for a great many examples of this phenomenon. For this period something
like one-tenth of all the empirical articles in this U. S. journal were studies by white
Southern Africans purporting to show the cognitive inferiority of black Africans.
108. Rogers, The Diffusion of Innovations (1962); Rogers and Shoemaker,
Communication of Innovations (1971), pp. 187-191; McClelland, The Achieving Society
(1961); Hagen, On the Theory of Social Change (1962) and "A Framework for
Analyzing Economic and Political Change," in Brookings Institution, ed., Develop-
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
ment of the Emerging Countries: An Agenda for Research (1962), pp. 1-39. 1 have cited
only the initial statements: much literature emerged from these works.
109. S. Marglin, "Losing Touch: The Cultural Conditions of Worker
Accommodation and Resistance," in F. and S. Marglin, eds., Dominating knowledge:
Development, Culture, and Resistance (1990).
110. Sack, Conceptions of Space in Social Thought (1980). Geographers
prominent in the diffusion paradigm discussed here are L. Brown (The Diffusion of
Innovations, 1981) and P. Gould (Spatial Diffusion, 1969). On peasant traditionalism
in relation to natural hazards, see G. White, ed., Natural Hazards (1974), as an
example of the abundant literature. I criticize these and other arguments about
non- Western nonrationality in Blaut, "Two Views of Diffusion" (1977), "Diffusion-
ism: A Unitarian Critique" (1987a), and "Natural Mapping" (1991).
111. In the field of education in the United States the dominant standardized
college entrance tests (SAT and ACT) are skewed by culture-specific and sex-specific
internal (as well as situational) characteristics, such that women do more poorly than
men although they actually perform at higher levels in terms of university grades,
while the ACT and SAT test scores of Latinos (African- Americans have not yet been
studied in this way), which are very low, have no correlation whatever with their
performance in college. Thus the tests effectively minimize female and minority
college attendance. Why the tests are almost universally used, even so, is a fascinating
question. The same biases are so prominent in IQ testing that such tests have been
barred as diagnostic instruments in California schools. The "primitive mind" and
"primitive languages" biases sometimes combine, as in U.S. debates about the
so-called "English-only" issue and about the question whether non-European
literature deserves to be included in the college curriculum along with European
literature. In Boston not long ago, 30% of Hispanic children aged six to eight were not
attending elementary school because their inability to speak English had been judged
to be evidence of mental retardation, and Boston claimed not to have sufficient
resources to educate these children in "special schools." Testing in general in U. S.
education remains very racist.
112. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1980), and earlier works by
Dewey (for instance The Quest for Certainty, 1929), Whitehead (for instance, Modes
of Thought, 1938), and G. H. Mead (for instance, Philosophy of the Act, 1938).
113. This is a general assessment. Some anthropologists continue to maintain
either the "primitive mind" doctrine or the closely related "traditional mind"
doctrine. An example of the latter is George Foster's well-known and influential book
Traditional Cultures (1962), of the former, Hallpike's The Foundations of Primitive
Thought (1979). For a critique, see Schweder, "Cultural Psychology: What Is It?"
(1990).
114. On the question of Weber's use of "rationality," its basal status in his
theorizing, and yet its uncertain definition and provenance, see, for instance: Cohen's
introduction to the 1981 ed. of Weber's General Economic History (1981), pp.
xxv-xxvii; Lowith, Max Weber and Karl Marx (1982), pp. 40-42, 53-54, n. 49;
Freund, The Sociology of Max Weber (1968), pp. 140-149. In Weber, see General
Economic History ( 1 98 1 ) , chaps. 29, 30, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism
(1958), pp. 13-31, 59-60, 79, 118-120, 191, n. 19, 265, n. 31, The Religion of China
(1951), chap. 8, The Religion of India (1967), p. 387, and other works x .
115. Weber, General Economic History (1981), p. 161. Also see pp. 339,
355-368. Weber makes a large number of comments about the irrationality of Asians.
146 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
116. Weber, Economy and Society, vol. 2 (1968), pp. 1212-1374.
117. Numbers in parentheses are page numbers in The European Miracle.
118. The ecologists' term "commensalism" refers to a form of tight interspecific
cooperation between animal species, but hardly ever is it applied to humans.
119. Typical of Jones's method is to find some objectionable feature of very early '
Asian society, compare it with some pleasing feature of modern, post-industrial-
revolution European society, and then treat both features as though they were
permanent characteristics of the respective societies, giving a picture of awful
primitiveness to Asians and marvelous modernity to Europeans thereby.
120. "Frankish feudalism, in many ways proto-typical of later feudalism, was . . .
a mixture of the very, very old, deep-rooted drift of 'European' peasant society and of
the brand new the opportunistic, the 'un-European,' " Mann, "European Develop-
ment" (1988), p. 16.
121. Mann, "European Development" (1988), p. 17. Also see his The Sources of
Social Power (1986), for instance pp. 190, 195, 213, 377, 404, 412, 510. ("At the end
of all these processes stood one organic, medium-sized, wet-soil island state, perfectly
situated for take-off: Great Britain," p. 510.)
122. Mann, "European Development" (1988), pp. 8-9, 11-12, 15-18 and The
Sources of Social Power (1986) , pp. 377-378, 397-398, 402-408, 412, 500-510. Also,
on Europe's rationality and its historical significance, see McNeill, Plagues and Peoples
(1976), pp. 41, 97, 106-107, 236, 238, 249, 256, 259, 264.
123. See P. Anderson, Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism (1974), part3; Finley,
The Use and Abuse of History (1975), chap. 6; Aston and Philpin, The Brenner Debate
(1985), pp. 32-33, 42-51, 59, 63n, 214-215, 234-236, 306-316.
124. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 38); also McNeill,
Plagues and Peoples (1976), p. 234.
125. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 54.
126. Kosambi, Ancient India (1969), p. 89; R. S. Sharma, Light on Early Indian
Society and Economy (1966), p. 57.
127. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 44.
128. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 56; McNeill,
Plagues and Peoples (1976), p. 237.
129. See C. T. Smith, An Historical Geography of Western Europe (1967), p. 203;
Darby, The Domesday Geography of Eastern England (1952).
130. Orwin and Orwin, The Open Fields (1967), chap. 3; C. T. Smith, An
Historical Geography of Western Europe (1967), chap. 4.
131. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 57.
132. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 67.
133. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 68.
134. Bray, Science and Civilization in China, vol. 6, part 2, Agriculture (1984), pp.
304-328.
135. White, Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), p. 76.
136. White, Machina Ex Deo (1968). See in particular the essay — quite a famous
one — called "The Historical Roots of Our Ecological Crisis" (chap. 5).
137. White, "The Historical Roots of Our Ecological Crisis." In White, Machina
Ex Deo (1967), p. 85.
138. White, Machina Ex Deo (1967), p. 90.
139. Needham et al., Science and Civilization in China (1954-1984).
140. Some historians today simply ignore this evidence and repeat the old
notions about China's lack of technological prowess. See, for example, Roberts, The
Hutchinson History of the World ( 1 987 ), pp. 493-495 ,502.
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
141. The terms "Middle Ages" and "medieval" are conventionally used for most
or all parts of the Eastern Hemisphere.
142. Needham et al., Science and Civilization in China, vol. 4, part 2 ( 1965), chap.
27.
143. Needham et al., Science and Civilization in China vol. 4, part 2 (1965), p.
33). Arnold Pacey places the innovation in Korea. See Pacey's Technology in World
History (1990), p. 56.
144. See, for example, Lopez, "Hard Times and Investment in Culture" (1953),
Thorndyke, "Renaissance or Prenaissance?" (1943).
145. Cipolla, Guns, Sails, Empires (1965), p. 106.
146. Cipolla, Guns, Sails, Empires (1965), pp. 108-109.
147. Jones, The European Miracle (1981), p. 124.
148. Among the modern states that do not surround such simple ecological core
areas: Spain, Italy, Germany, Poland, Greece, Sweden, Russia, etc. Prior to the 20th
century, perhaps only parts of Great Britain (southern England) and France (the Paris
Basin) came close to fitting this highly abstract model, a model that is useful for some
purposes but not for the purpose of explaining the political history of the continent.
Some of these core areas are nuclei of states; others are not. In modern Southeast Asia,
Burma, Thailand, and Cambodia fit the model as well as any European case.
149. In this connection, see Dirks, The Hollow Crown (1987).
150. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), "States and Societies: The Miracle in
Historical Perspective" (1988).
151. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), "European Development"
(1988).
152. This is not the only example of the way arguments centering on the
European state have a way of contradicting one another. The Roman state is said, on
the one hand, by Hall among others, to have been a crucial innovation, the source of
many political features characteristic of, and only of, Europe. On the other hand, the
Roman state is dismissed by others (including Mann) as just another "imperial state,"
like the despotic Oriental states; Europe supposedly innovated politically by avoiding
the imperial form of state and developing instead a kind of smaller and somehow more
democratic state.
153. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity: Caste and Feudality (India, Europe
and Japan)" (1988).
154. See, for instance, White, Machina Ex Deo (1968); Mann, The Sources of
Social Power (1986), "European Development" (1988); Hall, Powers and Liberties
(1985); Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988); K. F. Werner, "Political and
Social Structures of the West" (1988); and Hallam, "The Medieval Social Picture"
(1975).
155. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), p. 135.
156. Mann, "European Development" (1988), p. 12.
157. Hallam, "The Medieval Social Picture" (1975), p. 49.
158. K. F. Werner. "Political and Social Structures of the West" (1988), p. 172.
This German medievalist argues that the central force underlying the "miracle" was
Christianity. He refers here to the Catholic church, to the body of doctrine (Catholic
and later also Protestant), to the social and political institutions that were influenced
both by church and by doctrine, and to the faith of European people, which, in
Werner's opinion, had much to do with their innovativeness, their sense of
"restlessness," their rationality. Werner acknowledges that many causal factors were
at work in bringing about the rise of Europe, and he does not hesitate to claim a role
for the natural environment. But it is clear that his theory is primarily based on
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
religion. And beyond this, one senses that this scholar himself may see the hand of a
Christian god in the rise of Christian Europe.
Werner first of all makes a strong case to the effect that European history
maintained a continuity of institutions, and of progress, from the time of the Roman
Empire down through the Middle Ages, and that the late Empire established both
ecclesiastical and lay institutions which continued down through the Middle Ages
and gave that era its character. Chief among the institutions is the Catholic church.
Werner wishes to depict the church as having a determining influence on history from
the time of its founding. He sees the rise of Europe as a process that was guided
throughout by the Christian religion, as institution and doctrine. If Werner were
simply presenting a theory of history that accords religion a dominant role, 1 would
not be discussing his views in this book. I would agree that its role has been
underemphasized by historians, conservative no less than Marxist. The reason I deal
with Werner's views is that he makes clear his belief that it is not religion in general
but the Christian religion which played the historically efficacious role in the
European "miracle." Werner's views are distinctly Eurocentric. Perhaps the key
comment is the following:
[If] we had to choose one word that, by itself alone, were capable of expressing
an essential factor in what we understand by the "European miracle," we would
choose the philosophical term . . . "unrest" . . . "restlessness" . . . Ruhelosigkeit
. . . Whilst Asia and its wisdom and, in its train, the great religions and
philosophies, strive toward the art of . . . seeking out the centre of the soul and
of the world, and of resting in God, of having arrived, the European of the
European miracle is a man who is always ready to take off once more, once he
has arrived . . . But where must be sought the causa causans of this mentality?
The spur to anxiety is to be seen in the pangs of sin . . . in the search for pardon
and grace. The importance of the deliverance of the soul gave an hitherto
unheard-of prominence to the individual, independent of his social rank, the
individual who . . . [does not abandon himself] to destiny . . . [The] sense of
responsibility seems to me to be one of the strengths of the Europeans that are
to accomplish the "miracle" (p. 185).
Thus: Europe's religion, Christianity, instills a kind of mentality in "European man"
which explains the basic source of the "European miracle."
The objection to this is the same one we put forward to all of the notions about
Europe's supposedly unique "rationality." Whether that putative trait comes from
religion (Werner) or from the post-Neolithic European tribes (Mann) or from any
other source, the basic objection is: how can you really justify a statement that makes
Europeans brighter, better, bolder than non-Europeans, if you accept the fundamental
axiom that all human communities have the same ration of mind as all others? It is
one thing, and indeed an unexceptionable thing, to credit the human mind with
prime causality in culture change, through the innovation of social, technical, and
purely intellectual things. But it is something quite different, and quite suspect, to
credit the minds of human beings from some communities — and not others — with all
of these qualities of innovativeness, restlessness, sense of responsibility, intellectual
eagerness, respect for others, and so on, qualities usually summed up in the word
"rationality." Europeans are rational but so too are non-Europeans.
159. See, for example, Palmer, Atlas of Modem History (1957); Bjtfrklund,
H^lmhoe, R$hr, and Lie, Historical Atlas of the World (1970); and Kinder and
Hilgemann, The Anchor Atlas of World History, vol. 1 (1974).
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE
160. 1 discuss this in The National Question (1987b).
161. Padgug, "The Problem of the Theory of Slavery and Slave Society" (1976).
162. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988).
163. Baechler, in "The Origins of Modernity" (1988), p. 39, suggests that we
should "juxtapose the barbarous Europe of the Halstatt period [about 600 B.C.] . . . and
Africa on the verge of colonization in the nineteenth century [a.D.]."
164. Baechler finds a true aristocracy also in Japan but believes that Japan failed
to emulate Europe for various other reasons.
165. Baechler considers it quite unremarkable that the political chaos of the
Dark Ages gave way smoothly to strong states in Europe. "Inevitably" there will be
the "reconstitution of larger polities" (Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" 1988,
p. 50). But it is equally inevitable for India that the political chaos of 1000 years ago
will not be cured and permanently, thereafter, the "polity ... is not a reality in India"
(p. 45).
166. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988), p. 59.
167. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988), p. 53.
168. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988), p. 56.
169. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988), p. 45.
170. Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity" (1988), p. 53.
171. Godelier, Sobre el Modo de Produccidn Asidtico (1969), p. 58.
172. Brenner, "The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of
Neo-Smithian Marxism" (1977); "Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Develop-
ment in Pre-Industrial Europe" (1985, originally published 1976), and "The Agrarian
Roots of European Capitalism" (1985). After the 1976 article first appeared in the
journal, Past and Present, a series of critiques was published in that journal, and
Brenner replied in 1982 with the article, "The Agrarian Roots of European
Capitalism." A volume, The Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class Structure and Economic
Development in Pre-lndustrial Europe, containing the two Past and Present articles and
several critiques, and edited by Aston and Philpin, appeared in 1985.
173. In my opinion the popularity of this thin theory is due principally to two
things. First, put forward as a Marxist view, grounded in class struggle, it proves to be,
on inspection, a theory that is fairly conventional, if somewhat rural in bias. It seems
to follows that class-struggle theories lead to conventional conclusions. And secondly,
Brenner uses his theory ("The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of
Neo-Smithian Marxism," 1977, pp. 77-92) to attack the unpopular "Third- Worldist"
perspectives of dependency theory, underdevelopment theory, and in particular three
other neo-Marxists — Sweezy, Frank, and Wallerstein — who argue that European
colonialism had much to do with the later rise of capitalism. Brenner is a
thoroughgoing Eurocentric tunnel historian: non-Europe had no important role in
social evolution at any historical period. Unaware that colonialism involves capitalist
relations of production — see Chapter 4 below — he claims that the extra-European
world merely had commercial effects on Europe, whereas the rise of capitalism was in
no way a product of commerce: it took place in the countryside of England and
reflected class struggle, not trade. See critiques of Brenner collected in Aston and
Philpin (1985) by Hilton, Croot and Parker, Wunder, Leroy, Ladurie, Bois, Cooper,
and others. Also see Torras, "Class struggle in Catalonia" (1980) and Hoyle, "Tenure
and the land market in early modern England: Or a late contribution to the Brenner
debate." (1990).
174. Taeuber, in Freedman, Family and Kinship in Chinese Society (1970).
175. (1) If only one family member is a wageworker, loss of employment is a
disaster. If several are wageworkers, normally some will be earning an income when
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
others are laid off. (2) If we assume an ability to save a certain percentage of income,
multiple income earners will provide a larger absolute amount of savings, that is,
capital; and the absolute amount of capital can be critical in entrepreneurship. (3)
Having kin to borrow from is useful for small-scale entrepreneurship. (4) Kinfolk can
supply unpaid labor. These principles are well known in Third World communities.
176. Hajnal, "European Marriage Patterns in Perspective" (1965), pp. 101-146.
This paper is one of the most widely cited publications on the subject of demography
in the European miracle literature.
177. See note 37 above.
178. Hajnal, "European Marriage Patterns in Perspective" (1965), p. 101.
179. Hajnal, "European Marriage Patterns in Perspective" (1965), p. 134.
180. Hajnal concedes that he has only contemporary data for non-Europe, but
merely suggests that historical data would prove his point even more clearly because
modern non-European family patterns, in his view, are changing in the direction of
European patterns: are being Europeanized. And when "all the qualifications about
the data have been made, there can be no doubt that our original generalization
remains" ("European Marriage Patterns in Perspective," 1965, p. 106).
181. Stone, The Family, Sex and Marriage in England 1500-1800 (1977), p. 509.
182. Mann, The Sources of Social Power (1986), p. 408; Crone, Pre-lndustrial
Societies (1989), p. 152; Jones, The European Miracle (1981), pp. 15-16; Macfarlane,
Marriage and Love in England: Modes of Reproduction 1300-1840 (1986).
183. Laslett, "The European Family and Early Industrialization" (1989).
184- Taeuber, "The Families of Chinese Farmers" (1970), pp. 63-86.
185. See Freedman, Chinese Lineage and Society (1966), p. 49.
186. See, for example, Handler "Review of Macfarlane, A., Marriage and love in
England" (1989); Hilton, "Individualism and the English Peasantry" (1980); Kertzer,
"The Joint Family Household Revisited: Demographic Constraints and Household
Complexity in the European Past" (1989); and Berkner, "The Use and Misuse of
Census Data for the Historical Analysis of Family Structures" (1975), and "The Stem
Family and the Developmental Cycle of the Peasant Household" (1989).
187. For instance, G. Lee, "Comparative Perspectives" (1987), p. 65, points out
that "[Many] scholars contend that the majority of families in any society are and
always have been nuclear, regardless of the cultural elements favoring extended
families."
188. Macfarlane, The Origins of English Individualism (1978), chap. 1 and "The
Cradle of Capitalism" (1988), p. 344.
189. See, for example, Hilton, "Individualism and the English Peasantry"
(1980) and Handler, "Review of Mcfarlane, A., Marriage and Love in England" (1989).
190. "[It] seems likely that [primitive peoples'] patterns of behavior in . . .
respect [to fertility and mortality] bore a strong resemblance to those which can be
observed in many animals," Wrigley, Population and History (1969), p. 37. Wrigley is
writing about present-day hunting-gathering-fishing peoples. A "description of the
relationship between animal social conventions and the regulation of animal
population numbers" is "a convenient point of departure for the study of primitive
man" (p. 37).
191. Crone, Pre-lndustrial Societies (1989), p. 153; Hall, Powers andLiberties: The
Causes and Consequences of the Rise of the West (1985), pp. 130-132; Jones, The
European Miracle (1981), pp. 3, 13-15, 217-19, 226-227, 231, and elsewhere; Laslett,
"The European Family and Early Industrialization" (1989), pp. 235-240; Macfarlane,
"The Cradle of Capitalism" (1988), chap. 14; Mann, The Sources of Social Power
(1986), p. 408.
THE MYTH OF THE EUROPEAN MIRACLE 151
192. Hall, Powers and Liberties (1985), pp. 130-131.
193. Laslett, "The European Family and Early Industrialization" (1989), p. 237.
194- See Croot and Parker, "Agrarian Class Structure and the Development of
Capitalism: France and England Compared" (1985). This essay, and others in the
Aston and Philpin book, The Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class Structure and Economic
Development in Pre-lndustrial Europe (1985), discuss in detail the low level of
landownership in medieval Europe.
195. Stone, The Family, Sex and Marriage in England, 1500-1800 (1977), pp.
53-54.
196. Stone, The Family, Sex and Marriage in England, 1500-1800 (1977), p. 652.
CHAPTER 3
Before 1492
n this chapter and the following one I will argue
three broad propositions.
1. Prior to 1492, the progress toward modernization and capitalism
which was taking place in parts of Europe was also taking place in parts of
Asia and Africa. The basic process was hemispheric in scale. It was a
process of change out of a precapitalist, agrarian form of class-structured
society and toward a primitive form of capitalism. There was nothing
teleological about this process; it was not some sort of evolutionary
striving toward a foreordained goal, capitalist society. Merely, I argue,
whatever happened in Europe also happened in other parts of the Eastern
Hemisphere. I will use the word "feudalism" to describe the class-
structured agrarian societies of Africa and Asia as well as Europe (and will
give my reasons for using this word in this way). The later, emerging
formation I will call "protocapitalism." In 1492, it is likely that more than
half of each continent in the Eastern Hemisphere was basically
dominated by a feudal social formation. Protocapitalist centers were rising
in various parts of all three continents, and were interconnected in a
single web or network, stretching from western Europe to southern Africa
to eastern Asia.
2. This hemisphere-wide system began to break apart shortly after
1492, because of the wealth and power acquired by Europeans in America.
America was conquered by Europeans, not by Asians or Africans, because
of Europe's location on the globe, not because of any European superiority
in level or rate of development or "potential" for development.
3. The massive flow of wealth into Europe from colonial accumula-
tion in America and later in Asia and Africa was the one basic force that
explains the fact that Europe became transformed rapidly into a capitalist
society, and the complementary fact that Asian and African protocapital-
152
BEFORE 1492
ist centers began to decline first in relative and then in absolute impor-
tance. Development began in Europe and underdevelopment began else-
where. Many processes internal to Europe were important causes of
change, of development, in that continent, but the one basic process,
which ignited and then continuously fueled the transformation, was the
wealth from colonialism.
The first proposition is the topic of the present chapter; the second and
third are the topics of Chapter 4.
I will not and cannot demonstrate the truth of these propositions. I
will simply present a substantial amount of evidence that supports them,
and will show that the propositions fit in with other known facts in a
coherent theory — a theory that, I suggest, makes sense. That is as far
toward "demonstration of truth" as I can go, given the evidence of which
I have knowledge and the amount of detailed argumentation that can be
squeezed into this chapter. Some parts of this argument (such as the
pre- 1492 development of Africa) will theorize well beyond the available
evidence, because, in my view, the facts needed to confirm or disconfirm
these parts of the argument have not yet been obtained, have not yet been
sought with sufficient diligence by diffusionist scholarship. For the most
part, however, the theorizing will be grounded in strong empirical
evidence. In addition to this evidence, there is the weight of evidence
presented in the last chapter against various opposing theories, those that
deny the importance of non-Europe before and after 1492. This has given
us, so to speak, a level playing field for considering the issues to be
discussed below.
MEDIEVAL LANDSCAPES
Before 1492, the various civilizations of Asia, Africa, and Europe were
very different from one another in many ways, but they were very like one
another in other ways. I believe that the ways in which they were different
did not have significance for cultural evolution. 1 In Chapter 2 I outlined
various theories that claim that particular differences between Europe and
other civilizations do explain the unique rise of Europe, and I tried to show
that these theories are unconvincing. In the following discussion I will
deal with some parts of culture that clearly are crucial for cultural
evolution, and I will try to show that the patterns found in medieval
Europe were not significantly different from the patterns found in other
civilizations. I will argue that modes of production, class structures,
systems of spatial exchange, and urbanization were broadly similar across
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
many civilizations, were evolving in much the same way, and to some
extent were parts of a common hemisphere-wide process.
During the century or so preceding 1492, most of humanity lived in
class-stratified agricultural societies. The great majority of people in these
societies were peasant farmers, producing their own subsistence and
forced to deliver a significant share of their output (or labor, or cash
income) to an elite, or ruling class, a class that usually held claim to the
land and almost always held both formal and real power over the peasants.
What I have described here is a mode of production, that is, a complex of
traits including material resources such as land, material culture (tools
and the like), labor employed in production and distribution, social rules
governing access to material resources and distribution of the output, and
some related traits. For medieval Europe this mode of production is called
"feudal." It is part of a larger concept, "feudal society." One of the
important features of European feudal society was the nature of states and
political power. Another was the culture of the landlord class, with its
titles, its chivalry, and the rest. A third was the importance, in some
regions and epochs, of serfdom. But underlying (or at any rate
accompanying) these features was the general fact of feudalism as a mode
of production, a landlord-peasant, class-stratified, agricultural society in
which the landlord class was fed by surplus extracted (always with some
degree of force) from peasant producers. This mode of production, with
variations, was also a basic feature of almost all of the other class-stratified
agricultural societies of the Eastern Hemisphere. 2 I will therefore use the
term "feudal mode of production" for all such societies.
Others have used the term in this way but have encountered various
important objections. Those scholars who insist that the peculiarly
European features are, indeed, the evolutionary engines of change will
naturally reject the description of other sorts of society as "feudal." Max
Weber, for instance, thought that European feudal estates were unique
and were crucial causes (or conditions) of progress. Those Marxists who
consider serfdom to be a crucial feature in evolutionary terms would not
want to use the term "feudalism" for societies that did not have serfdom
(although many outside of Europe did). 3 Samir Amin rejects this broad
usage of the term "feudalism," on the grounds that it tends to require of us
that we use European feudalism as a model against which to measure other
similar societies in other continents. Therefore, he prefers the term
"tributary" to the term "feudal," arguing, correctly, that the various forms
of surplus extraction in this mode of production (tax and rent; cash, labor,
and product) can be assimilated to the concept of tribute paying. 4 My
view is that Eurocentric historians do not have a copyright on the term
"feudalism" and so it is not only valid but also in a sense just to use this
BEFORE 1492
term for the mode of production wherever we observe it, in any continent
and any social formation. There remain other objections. What of the
small urbanized societies found here and there across the map during this
period? We will come to this matter in a later section of the chapter.
How should we describe societies that are very aberrant from the basic
landlord-peasant model? What about class-stratified pastoral societies?
What about the class-stratified societies in which there is kinship linkage
between producing class and ruling class? These matters of definition are
important and I will try to deal with them in the context of the
discussion.
There are many unanswered questions about the origins and
evolution both of agriculture and of the feudal mode of production. Until
recently most scholars believed that agriculture, class stratification, and
many other attributes of civilization had originated in the ancient Near
and Middle East. (We discussed this in Chapter 1.) Given this set of
propositions, combined with explicit and implicit beliefs about the
cultural backwardness and unprogressiveness of Asians and Africans, it
was almost axiomatic that the agricultural landscapes of feudal Europe
must have attained a qualitatively higher level of development — or,
alternatively, must have had greater potential for rapid change — than
those of many parts, and perhaps all parts, of medieval Asia and Africa. It
seemed logical to believe that agriculture as such was still in the^process
of diffusing outward in some peripheral parts of the hemisphere during
that period. For instance, as we noted in Chapter 2, historians tended to
believe that most of southern Africa was "preagricultural" even in early
modern times. Scholars speculated, and legitimately so given the basic
model, as to the dates when agriculture in general, and each form of
domesticated plant and animal in particular, had first reached each
peripheral region in the general diffusion process.
This model began to crumble fairly recently. Very early dates for the
Agricultural (Neolithic) Revolution began to appear for parts of
Southeast Asia, dates of perhaps 9,000 years ago (the generally accepted
idea is that agriculture in the Middle East is 10-12,000 years old). Pottery
seemed to be just about that old in northeastern Asia and Japan. Soon
afterward, very early dates for agriculture emerged for India, New Guinea,
and other regions. 5 Today, although the majority view still seems to be
that agriculture first arose in the Middle East, very many scholars believe
otherwise. Many argue for independent and perhaps simultaneous origins
in the Middle East and Southeast Asia; some would add West Africa. But
it is also possible that the Agricultural Revolution occurred everywhere
more or less at once. 6 By this I mean that the complex of crops, animals,
' tools, and ideas was being developed in many societies simultaneously
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
(probably over a very long period), and each new trait tended to diffuse
rapidly to those other parts of the hemisphere in which such a trait was a
useful innovation, in an overall process that I call "criss-cross diffusion."
This process gradually built up an agricultural landscape over a vast region
of the hemisphere, extending (with unimportant gaps) across the entire
swathe of tropical and midlatitude lands possessing moderately favorably
climate and soil.?
In any event, it is now generally accepted that the diffusion of
agriculture took place fairly long ago and by the Middle Ages agriculture
had reached most of those regions in the Eastern Hemisphere in which
environmental conditions are favorable for farming. Agriculture was still
spreading at this time, but it could no longer be considered the Agricul-
tural Revolution. Farming had been pushed poleward to a point not far
short of its present latitudinal limits. In the Western Hemisphere the
northern limit of maize in 1492 was not far south of the present limit of
grain cultivation in central Canada. In both hemispheres almost all of the
crops and livestock types that are important today had already been
domesticated, although varietal improvement was still going on. As a
generalization, it can be argued that each agricultural region had by this
time selected for itself, from the long list of hemispheric domesticates, the
combination of crops and stock best suited to its environmental conditions
and cultures; most groups of related domesticated crop forms in any one
part of the hemisphere were also known in many other parts.
One very dramatic bit of evidence in this matter was the swift spread
of Western Hemisphere crops through the Eastern Hemisphere after
1492. This extremely rapid diffusion of maize, cassava, tobacco, sweet
potato, white potato, and other crops, and the rapid way in which these
domesticates became culturally important, shows how rapidly the
diffusion of domesticates would occur when the process was one of the
diffusion of previously unknown innovations: we can assume that most
Eastern Hemisphere domesticates were no longer diffusing very rapidly.
Where agriculture was spreading, it was taking place mainly in peripheral
zones such as highlands, some forested regions, and remote islands, as a
result mainly of social processes like migration, conquest, and land
shortage. 8 In the years before 1492, agriculture was practiced, from
southern Africa to northern Europe, northern Asia, southeastern Asia,
and most regions of the Pacific Ocean, including Hawaii. For the most
part, cultures we would describe as "nonagricultural" had chosen not to
practice farming; they were not, therefore, "preagricultural." 9
Probably the same holds true for the more complex forms of
agricultural technology. The knowledge of irrigation, the plow, the use of
fertilizers, complex rotations (including fallowless rotations), and other
BEFORE 1492
features of intensive agriculture had probably diffused by this time to all
those parts of the agricultural landscape where farmers found it desirable
to use them, either to increase output, to reduce labor requirements, to
meet the demand for surplus delivery, or for any cultural reason
whatever. 10 I would take the argument even a step farther. Throughout
most of this landscape the diffusion of significant innovations had gone so
far that the productivity of human labor was hardly ever limited by lack
of technical knowledge of a kind available to other farmers in some other
part of the hemisphere. 11 But this is speculation.
Agricultural societies are not always class stratified. But there is
abundant evidence that most agricultural regions across the hemisphere
displayed, in this period, a combination of agriculture and the
landlord-peasant system of stratification, thus a mode of production I
label "feudal." This point will be contested on two grounds. One of the
objections, commonly heard from (some) Marxists, argues that medieval
non-European agricultural modes of production were somehow lacking in
the potential for change that we associate with the European feudal mode.
This argument (the "Asiatic mode of production," "Oriental despotism,"
etc.) was discussed sufficiently in Chapter 2.
The second difficulty is a matter of the spatial pattern. Where, on
the map of the medieval Eastern Hemisphere, do we find class-stratified
agricultural societies, and where do we find classless agricultural societies?
The answer must be given in two parts. First, we know beyond dispute
that the class-stratified mode was dominant in nearly all agricultural
regions of Asia, with clear patterns of landlord-peasant conflict.
Arguments tend to focus on Africa. But there is little doubt that the
landlord-peasant exploitative relation was dominant in much of
northeastern Africa (for example, Ethiopia), the Sudanic zone from the
Atlantic east beyond Lake Chad, some parts of the Lake Region of East
Africa, southeastern Africa around the Zimbabwe imperial zone, and part
of coastal East Africa. It is now known, also, that many of the forest- zone
and dry-forest-zone states of West and Central Africa (Akan, Yoruba,
Congo, and so forth), displayed this mode of production or something
very like it, and research on the historical geography of this large region
has just, in essence, begun. 12 Therefore the map of the feudal mode of
production in Africa is very extensive. Second, I would argue (following
Samir Amin) that nearly all state-organized societies were class societies,
that the medieval state functioned in a tight relationship to the
exploitative process and ruling-class politics. More than half of medieval
Africa, in terms of area and population, was state-organized and therefore,
I reason, more or less class stratified. I conclude, from this very sketchy
examination of the medieval spatial patterns of agriculture, technically
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
complex agriculture, and class, that the feudal mode of production
dominated more than half of Africa, Europe, and Asia, and some parts of
Oceania, in this period.
The ruling class in feudal societies is, almost everywhere, a landlord
class, although the control of land by this class may take any of several
legal forms. Some members of this class are bedecked with titles, but the
distinction between nobility and gentry is not crucial in evolutionary
terms and both forms (as well as others) were widespread across the
hemisphere. 13 This class is, after all, self-perpetuating, and it may use
inherited titles as a signal of class membership or it may use other devices
to the same effect, or both. Indeed, membership in the nontitled gentry
may, as in China at various times, improve a family's chances of retaining
ruling-class status and wealth amid the changing winds of state politics.
Nor is the distinction critical, in this context, between higher and lower
grades of nobility, and between landlords and government officials (who
likewise derive their wealth from land). As we discussed in Chapters 1
and 2, there is no substance to the traditional view that the European
medieval landlord class somehow was closer to pure private land
ownership than were the landlord classes of other places. Marx was wrong
in accepting this traditional view, because he knew little about
non-European class structures. Weber, likewise, was wrong in drawing a
sharp distinction between the supposedly European pattern of seigneurial
tenure, with land held firmly by the landlord under some sort of
arrangement with higher-order lords and kings, and the "service tenures"
which he thought to be characteristic of most other societies.
The distinction between hereditary and service tenures is very fuzzy.
In Europe, service tenure was the typical form in strict terms (with grants
conditional upon pledges of fealty, military support, etc.), but grants
tended to become hereditary. Broadly, the same held true in other
societies. Holders of fiefs or grants on service tenure might move from fief
to fief (or hold a changing portfolio of fiefs), but the important point is
that class membership permitted one to hold a fief, and to draw one's
wealth from it (and its occupants), so long as one retained membership in
the ruling class. In a crucial sense, property is private so long as an
individual or kin group continues to hold valid control, and this was the
case in many regions, in spite of periodic upheavals and replacements. But
land can be called private in another sense, that of its value in a land
market. But this implies a basically (or nearly) capitalist situation, found
only in a few highly commercialized rural regions, European and
non-European, before 1492. ^ The Chinese gentry, the Hindu fief-
holders, even the Mughal jagirdars who had been granted fiefs on service
tenure and quickly farmed them out, or converted them into private,
BEFORE 1492
heritable property, all displayed the classic features of a feudal landlord
class. 15 The European feudal-era landlord class was not more advanced,
more ready (as it were) for capitalism and modernity, than the landlord
classes in many other regions.
The so-called European manorial system is sometimes said to have
been a distinguishing feature of feudalism, a peculiarly European giant
step toward private ownership and large-scale labor use, something largely
absent from non-European areas and critical in the evolution toward
capitalism. Large estates were widespread across the hemisphere, but the
special organizational form of demesne farming by unpaid peasant labor
was found in fewer areas. The manorial system in the narrow sense of the
term, including coordinated demesne farming with corvee labor in gangs
as well as peasant holdings, and with some manufacture along with
agricultural production on the manor, was found in several areas outside
of Europe. It was important in China and in southern India. 16 But
demesne farming was not dominant throughout Europe (it was
uncommon in the Mediterranean zone), bore no resemblance to capitalist
agriculture, and in any case had nearly died out in western Europe by the
fourteenth century. Hence the relatively stronger development of this
trait in Europe than most other regions (such as northern India) cannot
account for the transition, much later, to capitalism in one area and not
the others.
Related to this question is the old European misdefinition of Indian
villages, unfortunately accepted by Marx, as closed, corporate entities
(hence, for Marx, as survivals of primitive communal society). The
medieval Indian village did indeed have corporate characteristics; it did
have communal control of usufruct (though not, apparently, communal
ownership); and it did display the tight combination of farming and
handicrafts which Marx found to be highly significant and seemed, to
him, to explain the cohesiveness of the village, its ability to remain
unchanged in the face of external shocks from colonial capitalism, yet, by
the same token, to resist social transformation. But European villages also
retained certain corporate characteristics, perhaps even more pronounced
than those of Hindu villages, where caste communities correlated very
poorly with village settlement patterns. 17 In this matter we may be
confronting the classic error of telescoping history, perceiving the
breakup of the European village after the rise of capitalism, and assuming
therefore that these villages had been dissolving as corporate entities
many centuries earlier. Furthermore, communal land ownership was
relatively unimportant in this period for both India and Europe; the
villages normally held only delegated rights (including the right to
common land), which could be and sometimes were violated by
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
landlords. The true owners of most of the productive land, holders of
hereditary and transferrable estates, were, in both areas, the ruling class.
Finally, the combination of agriculture and handicrafts was also present in
European villages. 18 Apparently it dissolved well after 1492 with the rise
of capitalism. In sum, although Indian feudalism was in no sense identical
to the European variety (or varieties), it bore the same general
characteristics as a mode of production and the same potential for
evolution toward capitalism. This argument can probably be made also for
many regions of Asia and Africa. The medieval European village seems
not to have been very unusual among the array of village settlement and
social forms across the hemisphere.
The producing class in feudalism consists, usually, of peasants, who
farm the landlord's estate in household-scale units and provide labor,
produce, or cash as rent. Serfdom is often thought to be the characteristic
labor form of feudalism, on the European model. 19 Serfs of the basically
European sort were indeed found here and there in Africa and Asia,
although the specific history of enserfment in late-Roman Europe was
unique and its legal form was rarely encountered elsewhere. What we
find, rather, is a panorama of forms of unfree labor, that is, labor of
peasants tied somehow to the landlord's estate, through all three
continents. 20 On the other hand, some scholars (among them Brenner, a
Marxist, and Baechler, a conservative) rather idealize the European
peasant of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries in western Europe and
see in that person a freehold farmer, imbued with the entrepreneurial
spirit and so forth. 21 This is again a telescoping of history. Those peasants
were tenants, still tied to estates in manifold ways; not until later times,
well after 1492, was there a strong emergence of an important freehold,
capital-accumulating, kulak-style class, ready for rural capitalism. The
European peasant was not particularly unusual. Peasants who were forced
to give labor service, or product, or cash, as rent or tribute or tax (paid to
the landlord), who were not free to move from the landlord's domain, and
whose status was inherited by later generations, were found in many parts
of medieval Asia and Africa as well as Europe.
There was a measure of interconnectedness among the feudal
agricultural societies, enough to suggest that we should think of the
whole hemisphere-wide zone of class-based agricultural societies not as
separate social entities but as a single feudal landscape with regional
variations that sometimes included sharp boundaries and sometimes did
not. Clearly there was a great deal of criss-cross diffusion among these
regions, as evidence, for instance, the commonality of agricultural
techniques over large areas. (The claim made by some European
historians, 22 that medieval European agriculture was unique in
BEFORE 1492
technological level and thus somehow ignited progress toward capital-
ism, is invalid, as we discussed in Chapter 2. European agriculture shared
most traits with other regions and was not uniquely advanced or peculiarly
pregnant with social change.) It seems likely that the evolution of
feudalism over much of the hemispheric landscape involved a steady
deepening of the oppression on peasants, as more and more surplus was
demanded, and the response by peasants included technological
development and borrowing (diffusion), as well as migration toward
peripheral regions and toward towns. At the same time, the ruling classes,
as they exhausted the potential of their own subjects to increase surplus
delivery, tried to conquer and exploit other communities of producers,
to acquire external as well as internal fields of exploitation, and this also
led to further interconnectedness of regions. 23 Yet, at the same time, feudal
ruling class communities were united in webs of kinship, or bureaucracy,
or caste, which sometimes extended over very large areas. We know that
the neat parceling of societies into nation-states did not exist in those
times, that language regions were ill-defined and language barriers of little
significance, even that religious differences did not set up barriers to the
movement of ideas, things, and people. Thus we should think of all (or
most) feudal societies as sharing a common space, through which social
forces and pressures diffused in all directions, over great distances, easily
crossing the boundaries of states. Given this conception, it is not difficult
to understand why the general evolution of feudalism as a mode of
production was proceeding in about the same way over much of the
hemisphere.
In the late Middle Ages there were signs of profound change in many
agricultural regions of all three continents. There were indications of two
sorts: signs of decay, or even imminent collapse, in the feudal system, and
signs of change toward commercialized agriculture and toward rural
capitalism. Throughout much of the hemisphere, the mode of production
appears to have been in a state of decay, and we find increasing exactions,
peasant revolts, migrations to agricultural frontiers and towns, intense
warfare among ruling classes for access to producer populations, and more.
By the fourteenth century, feudalism had entered a stage of crisis —
although not of collapse — in Europe, but it appears that there were similar
crises in parts of Asia and probably — as we will doubtless learn from
further research — Africa. 24 In all three continents there was a movement
of peasants to the towns, perhaps at roughly comparable rates. In no large
region, European or non-European, could this have become a flood of
rural-urban migrants, since urban population was still a small percentage
of total population everywhere at the end of the fifteenth century. Still,
it was an effect of crises in the rural areas. Whether these crises were
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
indications that the mode of production was truly near collapse, and this
from internal contradictions, perhaps cannot as yet be decided, but in any
case feudalism in Europe was no closer to its final demise, prior to 1492,
than were the feudalisms of many extra-European regions.
At this point in the argument, a disclaimer and a speculation. I am
not arguing that the landlord-peasant mode of production had somehow
gone through its allotted historical span and was about to collapse, or to
transform itself into capitalism. The question whether capitalism had its
earliest growth in an urban setting or a rural setting is a very complex one
indeed; I will discuss the matter further below but I do not propose any
sort of general historical theory of causation. I will argue only that the
transition, or decay, or whatever one wants to call it, was far from
complete in 1492, and the wealth from America precipitated the rise of
capitalism and, simultaneously, the final decay of the feudal mode of
production in Europe.
I speculate as follows: Given our overall model of an extremely rapid
criss-cross diffusion of the cultural traits of agriculture (crops, stock, tools,
water-management systems, etc.), and given the parallel conception of
tight and intricate interlacing among class-organized agricultural societies
in the medieval Eastern Hemisphere, one would expect that the general
growth and evolution of the class-stratified agricultural form of society
would proceed in a relatively even manner from one region to the next, as
traits diffused, as social pressures were transmitted in space by migration,
conquest, and the like, as ruling-class alliances proliferated, and so on.
Perhaps the evolution of this feudal mode of production was everywhere
conditioned by one common social fact: the steady and unrelenting
demand of the landlord class and its allies (merchants, nobility, etc.) for
more and more wealth, a demand that translated into constant pressure
on peasants to increase production so that they could increase delivery of
surplus. I view this as a long-term secular trend that led to specific
responses in the peasant sector, including technological development,
criss-cross diffusion of technology, assarting and pioneering, peasant
revolts, rural-urban migration, participation in ruling-class military
adventures, and more. I speculate, then, that these mechanisms evened
out the social tensions that were created in many places by the increasing
ruling-class demand for delivery of surplus. This would allow us to argue
that, if the mode of production was in decay or in crisis in one part of the
hemisphere, very likely the same was the case in many other parts of the
hemisphere. In a word: the mode of production rose and then ebbed on a
hemispheric scale, and what was happening in Europe in 1492 was also
happening in Africa and Asia.
But why would we expect the feudal mode of production to decay or
BEFORE 1492
decline? This is the final point of speculation. We cannot assert simply
that feudalism is a "stage" of evolution, and must eventually give way to
the next, higher "stage" of evolution (capitalism), as some mechanistic
Marxists argue. Nor can we accept the conservative form of this argument,
which sees feudalism giving way to a higher and more "modern" form of
society (capitalism) as a result of humanity's inevitable forward progress,
social, intellectual, and moral. Nor can we invoke a Malthusian force of
inevitably heightening population pressure (a thesis which was shown to
be false in Chapter 2, on grounds mainly that human cultures always
control their demographic behavior, more or less rationally). I would
propose the following explanatory model. There are two essential facts
about this form of society: first, the fact of family-scale farming as a way of
life; second, the fact of a landlord class extracting, or trying to extract, an
ever-increasing absolute surplus from farmers. Peasant farmers respond to
this pressure in many ways, as we noted above. They certainly try to
increase their population so long as each additional human being in the
community can produce the requisite surplus, that is, contribute labor
which yields more production than is needed for consumption by the
incremental member of the community and for that individual's
contribution to surplus delivery. Certainly they try to add additional land
for cultivation, and sometimes try to move to another location, seeking
agricultural or other land. But mainly they intensify. That is, they increase
agricultural productivity by continuously experimenting with new crop
varieties, new tools, new techniques, and they are ever on the alert for
news about innovations that have been tried successfully elsewhere — in
the next village, the next valley, the next island.
The process of technological improvement has no limit, but a point
will be reached when the rate of increase in labor productivity declines,
generation by generation, century by century. Doubtless the rate was at its
highest during the period when many new crops and stock types were
being domesticated at a rapid rate, and when the main tools, and iron,
were being brought into the system. By the Middle Ages, the rate of
improvement overall would have declined to a level insufficient to permit
farmers to meet the landlords' incremental demands for surplus. If we set
aside some of the alternative responses, such as pioneering and
rural-urban migration, which must have been available in some regions
but not in others, we are left with the following situation: a general crisis
in the feudal mode of production.
Now this discussion has been grounded in one assumption: that
improvements in agricultural production are taking place through
innovations mainly on the farm itself. This is largely the case for
family-scale farming in medieval and premedieval times. Of course,
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
production is also improved by importing water and nutrients into the
farm through irrigation or drainage. And always there is some off-the-farm
sale or other exchange of products, and sale or exchange of products from
the farm for inputs like fertilizer, seed, and labor. So the individual
peasant farm, or family farm, is a relatively but not absolutely
self-contained microgeographic system. We know very well, and farmers
in those days also knew very well, that the best strategy for engineering a
dramatic increase in production from a microgeographic system like the
peasant farm is to integrate it more fully into a larger, macrogeographic
system. Mainly this involves increasing the input of water and fertility
elements, like lime and manure, and changing the pattern of crops and
stock from one which must primarily feed the farm family to one which
can involve some specialization in products that are saleable and that are
well-suited to the ecological conditions of the farm. (This would
commonly mean some specialization in one or a few food products, which
are both sold and consumed, or specialization in an industrial product,
like cotton.) When, today, we speak of the "agricultural revolution" of
recent centuries, we are describing a revolution at this macrogeographic
level: modern family farms import huge amounts of fertility; they import
(purchase) many tools, pesticides, and like elements which are produced
elsewhere; they use substantial amounts of nonfamily labor; and they
specialize in ways that (sometimes) involve ecological optimization. This
list pretty much exhausts the revolutionary changes that occurred prior to
the present century, and it suggests that internal, microgeographic
improvements — which never ceased to take place — played a secondary
role at this stage in the development of agriculture.
For these macrogeographic improvements to take place there must
be a high level of commercialization of farming, because moving things into
and out of the farm microsystem (or at any rate the village microsystem)
is mainly a process of buying and selling. It would seem to follow that a
general crisis of the feudal mode of production would have one of two
possible outcomes. One of these is a relatively smooth transition to an
economy in which there is massive off-the-farm cash demand for farm
products and supply of purchasable inputs, along with cash payment of
rent (or payment on shares to a landlord who then markets the share for
cash). This scenario takes place in a landscape in which there is a large
nonagricultural population, hence a landscape that is either urbanizing or
participating in major long-distance trade. Stated differently: the crisis
can be met if commercialization and urbanization are taking place.
Alternatively, there can be revolutionary changes of another sort: peasant
revolts, either mild (such as withholding of rent) or violent, major
cultural transformation in social, political, or religious life, or something
BEFORE 1492
else equally revolutionary. Perhaps both alternatives must occur in some
combination for the crisis to be resolved. I conclude that the rather clear
pattern in which feudal contradictions intensify, as a result of increasing
demands for surplus and decreasing ability of farm families to increase the
level of surplus, must lead to a revolutionary change of some sort. Most of
the changes that I have mentioned did, in fact, occur in Europe in the late
Middle Ages and involved the overthrow of feudalism as a political and
social system and its replacement by the modern system after the model of
England's "Glorious Revolution." But I am not arguing that this rural set
of processes explains the rise of capitalism. Certainly it contributed to the
rise of capitalism, and specifically to the processes of increasing
urbanization and increasing long-distance commodity movements which
characterized the late Middle Ages throughout the hemisphere, processes
which I label "protocapitalist," and which we discuss in the following
section of this chapter.
PROTOCAPITALISM IN ASIA, AFRICA,
AND EUROPE
I use the word "protocapitalism" not to introduce a technical term but to
avoid the problem of defining another term, "capitalism." Obviously, the
kind of economic system that we ordinarily think of as capitalist did not
exist in the Middle Ages; we are dealing with its forebear, which (as I will
argue) exhibited most of the basic traits of capitalism, but on a spatially
and socially small scale, and generally within, or on the edge of, a much
larger, dominant economic system associated with the feudal mode of
production. Protocapitalism, therefore, is incipient capitalism, or near-
capitalism, or adolescent capitalism. It is the system as it existed prior to
the two revolutionary transformations which brought modern capitalism
into existence. The first of these was the political transformation which
is usually, and conventionally, called "the bourgeois revolution" or
"bourgeois revolutions" — the creation of large polities that were
dominated, not by the feudal landlord class, but by an elite of townsmen
(burghers, bourgeoisie) and their entrepreneurial allies in the countryside.
The most famous example, and in a way the defining case, was Britain's
"Glorious Revolution" of 1688, and I will use the date 1688 as the symbol
or token for the political triumph of capitalism. The second transforma-
tion was, of course, the Industrial Revolution, which did not really begin
in a big way until the last quarter of the eighteenth century. In Chapter
4 we will examine the role played by colonialism and non-Europe in both
of these transformations.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
In all three continents we find relatively small rural regions (they
were generally hinterlands of major port cities) along with a few highly
commercialized agricultural and mining regions, which were clearly
being penetrated by capitalism — were protocapitalist — in the period just
prior to 1492. Among these were Flanders, southeastern England,
northern Italy, sugar-planting regions of Morocco, the Nile valley, the
Gold Coast, Kilwa, Sofala (and hypothetically part of Zimbabwe),
Malabar, Coromandel, Bengal, northern Java, and south-coastal China.
Land was owned by commerce-minded landlords or by urban protocapi-
talists. 25 Rents were generally paid in cash except in those areas, like
Fukien, where more money profit could be extracted by landlords if they
collected the farm produce and sold it themselves. 26 Agricultural
production was organized in various ways, ranging from peasant-scale
farming to plantations, and very significant quantities of a number of
agricultural products were grown, sold, and exported: rice, cotton, sugar,
pepper, etc. Industrial production was spreading out into the countryside
in all three continents: the early putting-out system was actually
de-urbanizing industry in northwestern Europe, as the control by guilds
became loosened; probably the same was occurring in parts of Asia and
Africa (where merchant and artisan guilds were also well developed and
strong in the Middle Ages). 27 Over a much broader area, commodity
production had fully penetrated the agricultural economy, and it is
extremely doubtful whether west European peasant agriculture was more
highly commercialized than that of many parts of China and India, as
well as some other extra-European regions. Probably we can assume that
level of urbanization is a good comparative indicator of level of
agricultural commercialization for this period, since it must represent the
main off-the-farm demand for agricultural products. By this measure,
Chinese and Indian agriculture would have been more highly
commercialized than European agriculture, because a larger percentage
of total population was urban in those regions.
Cities dotted the landscape from northern Europe to southern Africa
to eastern Asia. Some of these cities were seats of power for major feudal
societies. Others were socially and geographically marginal to these
societies, and were usually to be found along sea coasts, where they had
mainly an interstitial relationship to the larger feudal societies, moving
and trading goods among them and producing manufactured commodities
for them. Probably it would be incorrect to speak of two distinct classes of
urban place, internal and marginal (or peripheral), because many
variations and gradations existed, and also because the internal,
seat-of-power cities were in many cases also major centers for intersocietal
trade and for nonagricultural production. Nevertheless, we can distin-
BEFORE 1492
guish a special group of cities that were strongly oriented toward
manufacturing and trade, were more or less marginal to powerful feudal
states (some were within these states; some were small city-dominated
states or even city-states), and were heavily engaged in long-distance
maritime trade. Cities of this sort stretched around all of the coasts of
western Europe, the Mediterranean, East Africa, and South, Southeast,
and East Asia. In these cities the mode of production could probably be
best described as incipient capitalism, protocapitalism — certainly it was
not feudalism — with wageworkers being, apparently, the largest working-
class sector, merchants, merchant— landlords, or merchant— manufacturers
the ruling class, and economic activity a mixture of trade (movement of
commodities, banking, and so on), manufacture (both large- and
small-scale), and commercial agriculture.
Some of these mercantile-maritime cities were quite small, others
quite large, but it appears that most of them were at roughly the same level
in the development of protocapitalist institutions, classes, and technol-
ogy. This is not surprising since they were intimately connected to one
another in a tight network of trade, along which ideas, techniques, goods,
and people flowed in all directions, in constant criss-cross diffusion. 28
(For example: Malacca, when the Portuguese first arrived, was trading
with the Mediterranean, Inner Asia, East Africa, the Middle East, India,
China, and probably Japan as well as all of Southeast Asia. The chronicler
Tome Pires assures us that, at the beginning of the sixteenth century, 84
different languages are spoken in that city, and, boosting its importance
for the Portuguese, asserts that "whoever is lord of Malacca has his hand
on the throat of Venice." 29 A second example from a much earlier period:
the Tenasserim port of Kalah, in the tenth century, was trading with
China and Arabia. According to Ibn al-Faqih, the parrots of Kalah talked
in Persian, Arabic, Chinese, Indian, and Greek. 30 )
The network of mercantile-maritime centers stretched, like a string
of pearls, from the Baltic to the eastern Mediterranean, and from there
southward to Sofala (or beyond — the history of East and southern Africa
is still buried in colonial slumber) and eastward to Japan. The network
also extended inland in all three continents, but the mercantile-
maritime cities and oceanic routes were eventually of greater evolutionary
importance in the rise of capitalism than were the inland centers. This
was true for two (main) reasons.
First, foreign trade was the most peripheral of protocapitalist
activities; it was literally beyond the reach of the law. (Inland cities that
bordered on deserts would also have had this peripheral quality to some
extent.) Thus, a protocapitalist port city could move products to and from
any other oceanic port without having to pass through state-organized
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
territories, and thereby avoid paying tolls, being forced to buy and sell
goods to foreign merchants at intermediate trading centers, or perhaps
even being denied permission to enter a state. It is worth noting, in this
regard, that a substantial part of the high cost of Asian spices in European
markets before 1492 resulted from the fact that shipments coming from
India via overland routes ordinarily had to be passed from merchant to
merchant at several trading points enroute, with profit taken at each
intermediate market. The cheapness of Asian spices carried by the
Portuguese in the sixteenth century therefore reflected, to a considerable
extent, the fact that the spices could be on-loaded at an Asian port, and
then transported direct to a European port with no intermediate
transactions; perhaps this factor was more important than the generally
lower cost of sea transport over land transport (a factor that is often
overemphasized) .
Second, long-distance commodity movement by sea, involving as it
did the transport of vital staples as well as luxuries, was, among
protocapitalist activities of the late Middle Ages, perhaps the closest we
get to industrial capitalism in the urban economy of that time. It involved
not merely an exchange of commodities but the production of many
commodities including ships, and incorporated sophisticated technology,
a large work force, complex transactions, and massive capital accumula-
tion. This matter brings us back, inescapably, to the problem of defining
"protocapitalism."
There is a widespread tendency, often encountered among Marxists
but by no means confined to that school of thought, which argues the
following position. Money, cash exchange, and trade have been going on
for millennia but they do not signify capitalism or even the seeds of
capitalism. This is so because capitalism is a matter of production, not
exchange. "Real" capitalism requires the application of wage labor and the
production of commodities. Exchange is merely buying and selling; it does
not add value. For Marx, it produces wealth mainly as a result of unequal
exchange (higher prices in one market than another, and the like), not as
a result of labor input and the production of use-value.
From this model come a series of highly important theses. One is the
argument that medieval European towns were not central to the rise of
capitalism because their main activity was trade, exchange, not
production. Therefore the rise of capitalism must have occurred, not in
medieval towns but in medieval agriculture. 31 But a second thesis is more
crucial for the issues discussed here. This is the argument that starts out by
conceding that the great medieval trading cities and trading routes of Asia
were much more impressive in scale than those of Europe and the
Mediterranean, but this did not make them more significant for the rise
BEFORE 1492
of capitalism — because it was production, not exchange (trade, com-
merce), that was the crucial process. No matter how highly developed the
trading routes and cities of Asia were, Europe's feudal agricultural
production (in this argument) was closer to capitalism than either the
rural or urban production systems of non-Europe and it is this fact — the
nature of European rural society as contrasted with non-European rural
society — that is crucial in explaining why capitalism arose in Europe, not
in Asia (or Africa). The fallacy regarding rural production was discussed
previously. But equally fallacious is the idea that Asian (and African) port
cities, mercantile-maritime centers, were somehow purely or largely
concerned with exchange, with "commerce." Here there are in fact three
errors. First, production involves not merely change of form but also
change of place. It is metaphysical to argue that there is something
ontologically distinctive about the process of shaping nature into a
"thing," a commodity. When a farmer produces an agricultural "thing,"
he or she must not only grow it but also transport it from field to farmstead
and then to market, and must also transport inputs of water or fertilizer or
labor from outside the farm. Farm production, therefore, involves both
change of form and change of place. An automobile assembly line is a
process of change both of form and of place. Thus, overall, spatial
movement is part of production. It has nothing whatever to do with the
entirely distinct process by which commodities are purchased and sold.
Indeed, the farmer's crop can be subject to exchange right on the farm as
well as in an off-the-farm market. Therefore, the medieval activities
involved in moving commodities over long distances were not,
ontologically, "exchange"; they were spatial transport. They involved huge
labor forces, massive capital investment, major technologies — of naviga-
tion, ship construction, banking and insurance, and more — and signifi-
cant tonnages. They produced use-value at the destination from
commodities that had none, or less, at the point of departure. In a word,
what is called "medieval trade" was a complex process in which
production and manufacture played as great a role as did exchange.
The second error is the idea, very widely held today among
historians, that the cities, the commodity movement, and the rest of the
complex, was somehow a trivial process involving only the moving of a
few luxury items to a tiny ruling class. In fact, most of the medieval
seaborne trade was a matter of staple commodities, things like crude
textiles, iron implements, rice, wheat, lumber, ships (which often were
sailed from the place of construction to some other port where they were
sold), and the like. But beyond that, the tonnage and value of products
that would not be considered staples, things like pepper, sugar, finer
textiles, pottery, and so. forth, was, in and of itself, immensely important,
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
because the market for such products was very large: the medieval elites
were by no means insignificant.
The third error is a failure to perceive how important industrial
production was in these medieval cities and their hinterlands. Thus, I
conclude that the medieval mercantile-maritime system was very much a
nursery bed of capitalism, in Asia and Africa as well as Europe.
The protocapitalist port cities of Europe were not more highly
developed than those of Africa and Asia in the fifteenth century. This
holds true regardless of the kinds of criteria chosen as measures. European
cities, first, were not larger in absolute or relative population. In fact,
urbanization in Europe was probably less advanced than urbanization in
China, India, the Arab region, and no doubt many other non-European
areas. The urban population in early Ming China was perhaps 10% of the
total population. 32 In the Vijayanagar Empire of southern India it must
have been at least as high: the inland capital alone held about 3% of the
population — comparable centers in Europe, such as Paris, may have had
half that percentage — and the coastal port cities were both numerous and
large. 33 Second, the development of the techniques of business was fully
as advanced, fully as complex, and fully as wideflung in space among the
merchants and bankers of Asia and Africa as among those of Europe.
(Tome Pires said of Gujarati businessmen in 1515: "They are men who
understand merchandise; they are . . . properly steeped in the sound and
harmony of it" and "those of our people who want to be clerks and factors
ought to go there and learn, because the business of trade is a science." 34 )
Third, the technical and material means of production seem to have been
at about the same level of development in many mercantile-maritime
centers of all three continents, allowing for differences in the volume of
production and trade, the kinds of merchandise, and the like. Maritime
techniques were also comparable across the hemisphere: though they
differed from ocean to ocean, it cannot be said that ships of one ocean
were technologically more advanced than those of the others. 35
Manufactures in port cities and other industrial centers of Europe, Africa,
and Asia were also roughly comparable in gross scale and level of
development. 36 Fourth, the urban class composition of Asian and African
centers appears to have been similar to that of European centers: in all
regions there existed a powerful class of protocapitalists and a
wage-earning class of workers, with or without involvement also of other
classes such as feudal landlords, slaves, and so on. And finally, the old
European myth, codified by Weber — that European cities were somehow
more free than non-European cities, which were under the tight control
of the surrounding polity — is essentially an inheritance from classical
Eurocentric diffusionism, which imagined that everything important in
BEFORE 1492
early Europe was imbued with freedom while everything important in
Asia (not to mention Africa) was ground under a stultifying "Oriental
despotism" until the Europeans arrived there and brought freedom. The
so-called "free cities" of central Europe were hardly the norm and were
not central to the rise of capitalism. The partial autonomy of many
mercantile-maritime port cities of Europe, from Italy to the Baltic, was of
course a reality, and usually reflected either the dominance by the city of
a relatively small polity (often a city-state) or the gradual accommoda-
tion of feudal states to their urban sectors, allowing the latter considerable
autonomy for reasons of profit or power. But all of this held true also in
various parts of Africa and Asia. Small city-states were common around
the shores of the Indian Ocean, in the Maghreb, and in Southeast Asia;
also common were quasi-independent cities, giving loose allegiance to
larger states. This point was discussed in the previous chapter.
The preceding discussion was not a theory of the rise of capitalism.
My aim was simply to show that all of the theories that claim causal
superiority for Europe on the basis of Asia and Africa's supposed lack of
progressive urbanization or because extra-European urban processes were
not important since urban processes in general were of minor importance
compared to rural processes — European rural feudalism — are very
unconvincing.
It is not an exaggeration to describe this entire network of
mercantile-maritime cities as a single protocapitalist system. 37 The
surrounding space of class-organized agricultural societies was, as I argued
previously, made up of separate societies and polities in separate regions
but was, nonetheless, integrated enough so that persistent criss-cross
diffusion and other movements led to a degree of unity; perhaps even a
degree of intercontinental equilibrium. The unity was very much more
intense for the network of protocapitalist cities. The image I have in mind
for this is a network of strings of electric lights of various sizes and colors
illuminating a garden party. The current, so to speak, which flowed
among those port cities consisted of human beings (sailors, workers,
merchants, etc.), material things (commodities, ships, fertile seeds and
cuttings of crops, musical instruments, and much more), and ideas —
technological ideas, innovative social, economic, and religious ideas, and
so on.
All of this is well known in qualitative terms but not fully so in terms
of its intensity, its spatial extent, and, most critically, its unity. The entire
system can be viewed as a single entity, so tightly integrated that there
must have been rapid, almost instantaneous, criss-cross diffusion
throughout the system of essentially every material or immaterial culture
trait that is relevant to the economic and technical and ecological
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
progress of this form of society. I believe it is an error, built into our way
of conceptualizing cultures and cultural differences, to believe that the
very profound differences of culture among the various societies that
comprised this system would, somehow, have been reflected in a lack of
integration across cultural boundaries in matters concerning the
technical-economic-ecological dimension of culture. (Recall our discus-
sion above concerning the distinction between evolutionary and
nonevolutionary or partly non-evolutionary aspects of culture, in the
theoretical tradition of anthropologists like Steward. 38 ) In those times,
differences of language did not seem to interfere with the quest for profit
among merchants and other participants in this system. (Recall the
Greek-speaking parrots of Kalah, the 84 languages spoken in Malacca.)
Nor were differences of religion any great impediment (as has been amply
documented for Muslim-Christian-Jewish trade in the medieval Mediter-
ranean 39 ). Certainly there were limited social networks, membership in
which was a matter of religion or nationality or even kinship.
Abu-Lughod has shown that the pattern of connections and distinctions
produced a set of eight overlapping social regions — she writes of "The
Eight Circuits of the Thirteenth-Century World System" — although her
data and argument are consistent with my present thesis that all regions
were in fact subregions of one protocapitalist system. 40 State boundaries
do not seem to have played an important inhibiting role in the flows
across the system, except in certain fairly limited periods when either
political conflict or specific imperial policies and practices did, indeed,
disrupt trade through one or another political partition; the truly
nationalistic forms of capitalist enterprise become important much later;
in fact, after 1492.41
The network, or system, seems to have evolved over a period of
several centuries, mainly from the tenth to the fifteenth. Without
attributing cause, I would emphasize the fact that the period during which
this system grew most rapidly in scale and intensity was the period during
which the technology of oceangoing shipping increased explosively, in
what may be thought of as a (or the) Spatial Revolution. In the
Agricultural Revolution, we do not know whether the technical-
ecological transformation was cause, or effect, or both, in relation to
social transformation, although most scholars tend to treat agriculture as
cause and social change as effect, rightly or wrongly. In the case of the
medieval Spatial Revolution, it is most likely that the technological-
ecological aspect was more a reflection of the economic and social
processes associated with emergent protocapitalism and urban devel-
opment than a cause of the latter. Nevertheless, the medieval Spatial
Revolution was in one critical way a sequel to the Agricultural
BEFORE 1492
Revolution: it intensified spatial flows much as the earlier revolution
intensified in situ production. This is not to say that earlier boat
technology and earlier long'distance sailing out of sight of land was
insignificant: the question is one of intensity.
Perhaps, as a final speculation, we might think of the Spatial
Revolution as part of a larger process which was responding to the
maturation and decline of the feudal mode of production. Certainly it is
true that increasing commodity demand by elites was a major stimulus,
but it is also possible that the emerging crisis of feudalism — the decreasing
rate at which an absolute increase in surplus could be extracted from
peasant producers, and the resulting stresses and strains — had much to do
with the rise of the intercontinental protocapitalist system. In any case,
the dramatic long-distance voyages of discovery of the later Middle Ages,
voyages by Chinese, Indians, Polynesians, Europeans, and others, should
be conceptualized as moments in a genuine Spatial Revolution.
Much of this is speculation beyond the empirical data. But we have
important data about the parallels of development from one urban system
to another, and from one trading region to another. We also have
dramatic cases of almost instantaneous diffusion: for instance, the
appearance of the cannon in the Mediterranean region and in China
almost simultaneously; perhaps in the same decade. 42 For the argument of
this book, the one crucial generalization is the following: It is not
surprising that the processes that I have called protocapitalist were going
on across the Eastern Hemisphere in the later Middle Ages. Africa, Asia,
and Europe were about equally close to — or distant from — capitalism and
modernity in 1492. After 1492, the pace of development quickened for
Europe and slowed for Africa and Asia, because of the wealth brought to
Europe from America.
NOTES
1. Concerning my use of the term "cultural evolution," see Chapter 1, note 14.
2. The discussion in this section of the chapter mainly deals with the Eastern
Hemisphere. The Western Hemisphere will be discussed separately in Chapter 4.
3. See Dobb, Studies in the Development of Capitalism (1947).
4. Amin, Unequal Development (1976) and "Modes of Production: History and
Unequal Development" (1985).
5. Kabaker, "A Radiocarbon Chronology Relevant to the Origins of
Agriculture" (1977); Megaw, Hunters, Gatherers and First Farmers Beyond Europe
(1977); Vishnu-Mittre, "Origin and History of Agriculture in the Indian Subconti-
nent" (1978). See the review in Blaut, "Diffusionism: A Uniformitarian Critique."
(1987a).
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
6. Blaut, "Diffusionism" (1987a).
7. The assumption here is that agriculture itself was evolving because it was
useful, but there is the corollary assumption that humanity realized this not just in one
favored place but in many places and among many peoples. This should not be
surprising, given the fact that agriculture is useful nearly everywhere today. But it is
definitely contradictory to the assumptions of Eurocentric diffusionism.
8. Examples of this process include the eastward movement of the medieval
agricultural frontier in the forests of eastern Europe and the reclaiming of swampland
in Iraq. Cropland was being expanded in these and other ways in many regions. In
addition, it seems certain that some societies that had not previously practiced
agriculture were being pushed into smaller or less favorable regions and therefore were
turning to agriculture as a means of increasing food production to meet the land
shortage.
9. See R. Lee, "Art, Science, or Politics? The Crisis in Hunter-Gatherer
Studies'* (1992).
10. Water-control systems in farming, including irrigation, drainage, broad-
based terracing, raised- or drained-field construction, and natural-levee adaptations
are probably as old as agriculture itself, because ( 1 ) all farmers everywhere know the
problem of moisture control (adding moisture when there is deficit; removing
moisture when there is a surplus and a danger of root drowning); (2) all of these
procedures are initially small-scale actions taken on an individual farm (recall our
discussion in Chapter 2 of the fallacies of the "hydraulic theory"); and (3) there is
direct archaeological evidence of very ancient (9,000-year-old) drainage systems in
New Guinea (Golson, "No room at the top: Agricultural intensification in the New
Guinea Highlands," 1977), and drained- or raised-field systems in tropical America
(Denevan, "Hydraulic Agriculture in the American Tropics: Forms, Measures, and
Recent Research," 1982). Thus we can infer the primitivity of irrigation and these
other water-management systems: probably they are as old as the Neolithic, along
with drainage and raised-field systems. All this shows that intensive technology had
already diffused insofar as it was going to do so, and nonadoption reflected something
other than lack of information. As we noted in Chapter 2, irrigation systems diffuse as
a social process, associated with class society. Concerning the myth that the plow was
not used in Africa, see Hopkins, An Economic History of West Africa (1973) and
Onimode, Imperialism and Underdevelopment in Nigeria (1982). Note that plows are
used in tropical agriculture very sparingly — mainly for some operations in rice
paddies.
1 1 . In classless societies, I speculate that the bundle of choices concerning crops,
tools, field systems, labor input, and the like, led to roughly a common level of output
per person, unaffected by differences in environmental quality over a great range of
environments. In some areas very extensive systems like shifting cultivation would be
used; in others, intensive systems, like wet-rice cultivation, would be used. But the
productivity of labor in terms of product per hour input would tend to be about the
same in this model for both intensive and extensive systems. This would hold true if
two assumptions are accepted: (1) that rapid and thorough diffusion had taken place,
and (2) that population was controlled by farming peoples so as to optimize the
situation concerning output and leisure time. None of this would be true in a class
society, where the constraints on technology and labor use are influenced profoundly
by the demands and power of the ruling class.
12. See, for example, Kea, Settlements, Trade, and Polities in the Seventeenth-
BEFORE 1492
Century Gold Coast (1982); Isichei, A History of Nigeria (1983); Rodney, A History
of the Upper Guinea Coast 1545-1800 (1970); A. Smith, "The Early States of the
Central Sudan" (1971); Usman, The Transformation ofKatsina (1400-1883) (1981).
13. See Blaut, "Colonialism and the Rise of Capitalism" (1989). It is also true
that in all these societies there were parallel high-status groups, clergy, bureaucrats,
military people, and so on, but there seems not to have been any case of a large, clearly
feudal society — I exclude a few cases of small urbanized power centers in dry, pastoral
regions, and a few large cities — in which wealth and status was clearly divorced from
land ownership and from the surplus extracted from peasants.
14- Apparently such private (saleable) ownership of agricultural land was found
mainly near important urban areas, ports, mining areas, etc. See Rawski, Agricultural
Change and the Peasant Economy of South China (1972); Das Gupta, Malabar in Asian
Trade: 1740 — 1800 (1967); Nicholas, "Town and Countryside: Social and Economic
Tensions in 14th Century Flanders" (1967-1968); Kea, Settlements, Trade, andPolities
in the Seventeenth-Century Gold Coast (1982); Rodney, A History of the Upper Guinea
Coast (1970); Usman, The Transformation of Katsina (1981); Sherif, Slaves, Spices and
Ivory in Zanzibar (1987).
15. On the importance of hereditary fiefs and landed property in Asia, see, for
example, Elvin, The Pattern of the Chinese Past (1973); Sharma, Indian Feudalism, c.
300-1200 (1965); Fei Hsiao-tung, China's Gentry (1953); Fu and Li, The Sprouts of
Capitalistic Factors Within China's Feudal Society (1956); Rawski, Agricultural Change
and the Peasant Economy of South China (1972); Tung, An Outline History of China
(1979); Liceria, "Emergence of Brahmanas as Landed Intermediaries in Karnataka, c.
a.d. 1000-1300 (1974); Mahalingam, Economic Life in the Vijayanagar Empire (1951);
Hasan, "The Position of the Zamindars in the Mughal Empire (1969); Raychaudhuri,
"The Agrarian System of Mughal India" (1965); Yadava, "Secular Land Grants of the
Post-Gupta Period and Some Aspects of the Growth of the Feudal Complex in
Northern India" 1966). For Africa south of the Sahara (for which there is as yet only
fragmentary evidence), see, for example, A. Smith, "The Early States of the Central
Sudan" (1971); Mabogunji, "The Land and Peoples of West Africa" (1971); Kea,
Settlements, Trade, and Polities in the Seventeenth-Century Gold Coast (1982); Isichei, A
History of Nigeria (1983); Onimode, Imperialism and Underdevelopment in Nigeria
(1982); FRELIMO, Historic de Mozambique (1971); Rodney, A History of the Upper
Guinea Coast (1970); and Usman, The Transformation ofKatsina (1981).
16. On the manorial system of China, see Elvin, The Pattern of the Chinese Past
(1973). For India, see Gopal, "Quasi-Manorial Rights in Ancient India" (1963);
Mahalingam, Economic Life in the Vijayanagar Empire (1951); Yadava, "Secular Land
Grants of the Post-Gupta Period" (1966); Yadava, "Immobility and Subjugation of
Indian Peasantry in Early Medieval Complex" (1974). Indian historians recognize
important differences between the Indian and European forms of the manor, however.
In early Indian feudalism manorial labor had some of the characteristics of serfs, some
of wage laborers, and some of tenant farmers. Early Indian feudal estates also seem to
have been less autarkic and insulated than the stereotypic European manor.
17. Marx's view is set forth in "The British rule in India" (1979). Irfan Habib,
in part following Kosambi (both are Marxists), writes of "the creation of the traditional
Indian village, closed and self-sufficient" (my emphasis) between 200 B.C. and 650 a.d.,
in a process involving "ruralization of crafts" and somewhat planned settlement
of landless people in villages: Habib, in "The Social Distribution of Landed Property
in Pre-British India" (1965).
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
18. On the unity of agriculture and handicraft industry in medieval European
villages, see, for example, Sylvia Thrupp, "Medieval Industry 1000-1500" (1972).
19. Dobb, Studies in the Development of Capitalism (1947).
20. Serfdom was not characteristic of all parts of medieval Europe. On unfree
labor in Asia and Africa, see, for example, Yadava, "Immobility and Subjugation of
Indian Peasantry in Early Medieval Complex" (1974); Levitzion, "The Early States of
the Western Sudan to 1500" (1972); Elvin, The Pattern of the Chinese Past (1973).
21. See Brenner and critics in Aston and Philpin, The Brenner Debate: Agrarian
Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-lndustrial Europe(1988); Brenner,
"The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of Neo-Smithian Marxism."
(1977); Baechler, "The Origins of Modernity: Caste and Feudality (India, Europe and
Japan)." (1988). See comments on Brenner and Baechler in Chapter 2 above.
22. including Lynn White, Jr. in Medieval Technology and Social Change (1968);
Michael Mann, "European Development: Approaching a Historical Explanation"
(1988); Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolute State (1974).
23. Blaut, The National Question (1987b), chap. 7.
24. For India, see, for example, A. Chicherov, "On the Multiplicity of
Socio-Economic Structures in India in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century"
(1976); I. Habib, "Problems of Marxist Historical Analysis" (1969); S. Gopal,
Nobility and the Mercantile Community in India" (1972); Radhakamal Mukherjee,
The Economic History of India, 1600-1800 (1967); Ramkrishna Mukherjee, The Rise
and Fall of the East India Company (1958); Jha, Studies in the Development of Capitalism
in India (1963); Nurul Hasan, "The Silver Currency Output of the Mughal Empire
and Prices in India During the 16th and 17th Centuries" (1969); Yadava, "Immobility
and Subjugation of Indian Peasantry in Early Medieval Complex" (1974). For West
Africa, see Kea, Settlements, Trade, and Polities in the Seventeenth-Century Gold Coast
(1982). For China, see Harrison, The Communists and Chinese Peasant Rebellions
(1969); Parsons, Peasant Rebellions in the Late Ming Dynasty (1970); Fu and Li, The
Sprouts of Capitalistic Factors Within China's Feudal Society (1956).
25. Appadorai, Economic Conditions in Southern India (1936); Elvin, The Pattern
of the Chinese Past (1974); Nicholas, "Town and Countryside: Social and Economic
Tensions in 14th Century Flanders" (1967-1968), pp. 458-485; Rawski, Agricultural
Change and the Peasant Economy of South China (1972); T. Raychaudhuri, ]an
Company in Coromandel (1962).
26. Rawski, Agricultural Change and the Peasant Economy of South China (1972).
27. See Appadorai, Economic Conditions in Southern India (1936); Gernet, Daily
Life in China on the Eve of the Mongol Invasion (1962); Habib, "Problems of Marxist
Historical Analysis" (1969); Mahalingam, Economic Life in the Vijayanagar Empire
(1951); K. Nilikanta Sastri, A History of South India (1966); Tung, An Outline History
of China (1979); Kea, Settlements, Trade, and Polities in the Seventeenth-Century Gold
Coast (1982), Sherif, Slaves, Spices and Ivory in Zanzibar (1987).
28. Blaut, "Where Was Capitalism Born?" (1976).
29. Pires, The Suma Oriental (1944 edition).
30. Pires, The Suma Oriental (1944); Di Meglio, "Arab Trade with Indonesia
and the Malay Peninsula from the 8th to the 16th Century" (1970). The location of
Kalah is tentatively placed in the Mergui region: see Wheatley, The Golden Khersonese
(1961).
BEFORE 1492
31. This thesis is central to the famous debate over the role of urbanization in
the medieval rise of capitalism; in Marxist literature this view is associated with
Maurice Dobb (who in fact presented it very cautiously), and its opposition —
emphasis on the role of towns in the rise of capitalism — is associated with Paul
Sweezy. See Dobb, Studies in the Development of Capitalism (1947), Sweezy, "A
Critique" (1976). The thesis is also central to the debates over "dependency theory."
For instance, Robert Brenner argues that towns and trade were essentially irrelevant
precisely because the issue is production, not exchange, and Brenner believes
(wrongly) that towns were not really important points of production in the medieval
world. See Brenner, "The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism" (1985), pp. 38-39.
Also see Chapter 2, note 172, above.
32. Elvin, The Pattern of the Chinese Past (1973).
33. Elvin, The Pattern of the Chinese Past (1973); Mahalingam, Economic Life in
the Vijayanagar Empire (1951); Naqvi, Urban Centres in Upper India, 1556-1803
(1968); Satish Chandra, "Commerce and Industry in the Medieval Period" (1964).
34. Pires, The Suma Oriental (1944). Also see K. N. Chaudhuri, Trade and
Civilization in the Indian Ocean (1985); Chan-Cheung, "The Smuggling Trade
Between China and Southeast Asia During the Ming Dynasty (1967); Di Meglio,
"Arab Trade with Indonesia and the Malay Peninsula from the 8th to the 16th
Century" (1970); Elvin, "China as a Counterfactual" (1988); Gupta, Industrial
Structure of India During Medieval Period (1970); I. Habib, "Usury in Medieval India"
(1964); Jha, Studies in the Development of Capitalism in India (1963); Pires, The Suma
Oriental (1944); Prakash, "Organization of Industrial Production in Urban Centres in
India During the Seventeenth Century with Special Reference to Textiles" (1964);
Victor Purcell, The Chinese in Southeast Asia, 2nd ed. (1965); Jan Qaisar, "The Role
of Brokers in Medieval India" (1974); Simkin, The Traditional Trade of Asia (1968);
Toyoda, History of Pre-Meiji Commerce in Japan (1969); Udovitch, "Commercial
Techniques in Early Medieval Islamic Trade" (1974).
35. Needham and collaborators, Science and Civilization in China (1954-1984),
vol. 4, part 3; Lewis, "Maritime Skills in the Indian Ocean, 1368-1500" (1973); Lo,
"China as a Sea Power" (1955); Ma Huan, The Overall Survey of the Ocean's Shores
(1970); Purcell, The Chinese in Southeast Asia, 2nd ed. ( 1965).
36. S. Chaudhuri, "Textile Trade and Industry in Bengal Suba, 1650-1720"
(1974); Elvin, "China as a Counterfactual" (1988); Gernet, Daily Life in China on the
Eve of the Mongol Invasion (1962); Jha, Studies in the Development of Capitalism in India
(1963); Naqvi, Urban Centres in Upper India, 1556-1803 (1968); Needham and
collaborators, Science and Civilization in China (1965-1984); Jan Qaisar, "The Role of
Brokers in Medieval India" (1974); Rodinson, "Le Marchand Musulman" (1974);
Rodinson, Islam and Capitalism (1973); Bodo Wiethoff, Die C/imesiscne Seeverbotspoli'
tik und der Private Uberseehandel von 1368 bis 1567 (1963); Yang, "Government
Control of Urban Merchants in Traditional China" (1970).
37. 1 proposed this idea in Blaut, "Where Was Capitalism Born?" (1976). Janet
Abu-Lughod's important book Be/ore European Hegemony: The World System a.d.
1250-1350 (1989) is the first effort to show in precise detail how this system worked
in the fourteenth century. Also see S. Chaudhuri, "Textile Trade and Industry in
Bengal Suba" (1985); Simkin, The Traditional Trade of Asia (1968); Amin,
Accumulation on a World Scale (1974) and Unequal Development (1976).
38. Steward, Theory of Culture Change: The Methodology of Multilinear Evolution
(1955). See note 1.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
39. Braudel, The Mediterranean (1972); Goitein, A Mediterranean Society (1967);
Lane, Venice: A Maritime Republic (1973).
40. Abu-Lughod, Before European Hegemony: The World System a.d. 1250-1350
(1989), fig. 1, p. 34. One of the eight regions is the nonmaritime circuit extending
from China through Central Asia to the Black Sea.
41. Blaut, The National Question (1987b).
42. Needham and collaborators, Science and Civilization in China (1965-1984),
Vol. 5, part 7; Needham, Gunpowder as the Fourth Power, East and West (1985).
CHAPTER 4
After 1492
EXPLAINING 1492
In 1492, as have seen, capitalism was slowly emerging
in many parts of Asia, Africa, and Europe. In that
year there would have been no reason whatever to
predict that capitalism would triumph in Europe,
and would triumph only two centuries later.
By "the triumph of capitalism" I mean, in the present context, the
political revolution that transferred power from the old feudal landlord
elite to the bourgeoisie (the burghers, the capital-accumulating new
elite): the bourgeois revolution. This was really a revolutionary epoch,
not a single brief event, but I will follow convention by dating it to 1688,
the year of England's "Glorious Revolution." In that year (minor
qualifications aside) the bourgeoisie definitively took power in England.
This class already held power in Holland and in some small states of
southern Europe, while in some other parts of Europe (like France) the
bourgeoisie was vigorously "rising" in certain regions although the
conflict with feudal polities had not yet been won at the level of state
power. It should be emphasized that the capitalism that triumphed was
not industrial capitalism. How this preindustrial capitalism should be
conceptualized is a difficult question because it is something much larger
than the "simple commodity production" and "merchant capital" of
earlier times. But the Industrial Revolution did not really begin until a
century later, in the late eighteenth century, and those who conceptualize
the Industrial Revolution as simply a continuation of the bourgeois
revolution are neglecting a large and important block of history, both
inside and outside of Europe.
The explanation for the rise of capitalism to political power in
Europe in the (symbolic) year 1688 requires an understanding of (1) the
reasons Europeans, not Africans and Asians, reached and conquered
America, and thus garnered the first fruits of colonialism; (2) the reasons
the conquest was successful; (3) the direct and indirect effects of the
sixteenth-century plunder of American resources and exploitation of
179
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
American workers on the transformation of Europe; and (4) the direct
and indirect effects of seventeenth-century colonial and semicolonial
European enterprise in America, Africa, and Asia on the further
transformation of Europe and eventually the political triumph of
capitalism in the bourgeois revolution.
In the following paragraphs we will summarize each of these processes
in turn, and thus, so to speak, "explain 1492." Then we will turn to the
problem of explaining the rise of capitalism to political power in Europe —
or more properly, part of Europe — in the period 1492—1688, in the sense of
trying to sort out the significance of colonialism and the extra-European
world in this epochal transformation. Finally, we will look at the signifi-
cance of colonialism, and the role of non-Europe, in the initial stages of
the Industrial Revolution, roughly, in the period of the late eighteenth and
early nineteenth centuries, and will look at the complementary process:
the beginnings of underdevelopment in Africa and Asia.
This inquiry should lead to an explanation for the fundamental fact
that capitalism became centrated in Europe. I use the verb "centrate" to
emphasize one crucial theoretical argument of this book: the rise of a
more-or-less capitalist system had been going on in many parts of the world
prior to 1492; after 1492, new forces entered which slowed, then stopped,
its evolution outside of Europe and quickened it inside. Thus the rise of
capitalism after 1492 was as much a matter of shifting its main headquar-
ters to Europe as it was a matter of "rising" in a simple evolutionary sense.
Why America Was Conquered by Europeans
and Not by Africans or Asians
One of the core myths of Eurocentric diffusionism concerns the discovery
(so-called) of America. 1 Typically it goes something like this: Europeans,
being more progressive, venturesome, achievement-oriented, and modern
than Africans and Asians in the late Middle Ages, and with superior
technology as well as a more advanced economy, went forth to explore
and conquer the world. And so they set sail down the African coast in the
middle of the fifteenth century and out across the Atlantic to America in
1492. This myth is crucial for diffusionist ideology for two reasons: it
explains the modern expansion of Europe in terms of internal, immanent
forces, and it permits one to acknowledge that the conquest and its
aftermath (Mexican mines, West Indian plantations, North American
settler colonies, and the rest) had profound significance for European
history without at the same time requiring one to give any credit in that
process to non-Europeans.
AFTER 1492
In reality, the Europeans were doing what everyone else was doing
across the hemisphere-wide network of protocapitalist, mercantile-
maritime centers, and Europeans had no special qualities or advantages,
no peculiar venturesomeness, no peculiarly advanced maritime technol-
ogy, and so on. What they did have was opportunity: a matter of
locational advantage in the broad sense of accessibility. The point
deserves to be put very strongly. If the Western Hemisphere had been
more accessible, say, to South Indian centers than to European centers,
then very likely India would have become the home of capitalism, the site
of the bourgeois revolution, and the ruler of the world.
In the late Middle Ages long-distance oceanic voyaging was being
undertaken by mercantile— maritime communities everywhere. In the
fifteenth century Africans were sailing to Southeast Asia, Indians to
Africa, Arabs to China, Chinese to Africa, and so on. 2 Much of this
voyaging was across open ocean and much of it involved exploration.
Two non-European examples are well known: Cheng Ho's voyages to
India and Africa between 1417 and 1433, and an Indian voyage around
the Cape of Good Hope and apparently some 2,000 miles westward into
the Atlantic circa 1420. 3 In this period the radii of travel were becoming
longer, as a function of the general evolution of protocapitalism, the
expansion of trade, and the development of maritime technology.
Maritime technology differed from region to region but no one region
could be considered to have superiority in any sense implying
evolutionary advantage, and novel ideas and techniques were being
spread in all directions by rapid criss-cross diffusion. The entire
hemisphere was participating and sharing in a Spatial Revolution.
Certainly the growth of Europe's commercial economy led to the
Portuguese and Spanish voyages of discovery. But the essence of the
process was a matter of catching up with Asian and African protocapital-
ist communities by European communities, which were at the margin of
the hemisphere-wide system and were emerging from a period of
downturn relative to some other parts of the system. Iberian Christian
states were in conflict with Maghreb states and European merchant
communities were having commercial difficulties both there and in the
eastern Mediterranean. The opening of a sea route to West African gold
mining regions, along a sailing route known since antiquity, and using
maritime technology known to non-Europeans as well as Europeans, was
an obvious strategy. 4 By the late fifteenth century the radii of travel had
lengthened so that a sea route to India was found to be feasible (with
piloting help from African and Indian sailors). The leap across the
Atlantic in 1492 was certainly one of the great adventures of human
history, but it has be seen in a context of shared technological and
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
geographical knowledge, high potential for commercial success, and other
factors that place it, in a hemispheric perspective, as something that could
have been undertaken by non-Europeans just as easily as by Europeans.
Europeans had one advantage. America was vastly more accessible
from Iberian ports than from any extra-European mercantile-maritime
centers that had the capacity for long-distance sea voyages. Accessibility
was in part a matter of sailing distance. Sofala, which is presumed to have
been the southernmost major seaport in East Africa in that period (there
may have been others farther south), is roughly 3,000 miles farther away
from an American landfall than are the Canary Islands (Columbus's
jumping-off point) and 5,000 miles farther from any densely populated
coast with possibilities for trade or plunder. The distance from China to
America's northwest coast was even greater, and greater still to the rich
societies of Mexico.
To all of this we must add the sailing conditions on these various
routes. Sailing from the Indian Ocean into the Atlantic one sails against
prevailing winds. The North Pacific is somewhat stormy and winds are
not reliable. From the Canaries to the West Indies, on the other hand,
there blow the trade winds, and the return voyage is made northward into
the westerlies. Obviously an explorer does not have this information at
hand at the time of the voyage into unknown seas. The extent of the
geographical knowledge possessed by Atlantic fishing communities in the
fifteenth century remains, however, an unanswered and intriguing
question, and there is speculation that these people fished around
Newfoundland and the Grand Banks before 1492. More concretely, the
Iberian sailors going to and from the Canaries, Madeira, and the Azores
made use of the same basic wind circulation as did Columbus in crossing
the entire ocean; Columbus knew that the trade winds (or easterlies)
would assist him outbound and had good reason to believe that the
westerlies would assist the return voyage. The point here is a matter of
strong probabilities. Overall, it is vastly more probable that an Iberian
ship would effect a passage (round trip) to America than would an
African or Asian ship in the late fifteenth century, and, even if such a
voyage were made by the latter, it is vastly more probable that Columbus's
landfall in the West Indies would initiate historical consequences than
would have been the case for an African ship reaching Brazil or a Chinese
ship reaching California.
Is this environmental determinism? There is no more environmen-
talism here than there is in, say, some statement about the effect of
oilfields on societies of the Middle East. I am asserting only the
environmental conditions that support and hinder long-distance oceanic
travel. In any case, if the choice were between an environmentalistic
AFTER 1492
explanation and one that claimed superiority of one group over all others,
as Eurocentric diffusionism does, we would certainly settle for environ-
mentalism.
Before we leave this topic, two important questions remain to be
asked. First, why did not West Africans "discover" America since they
were even closer to it than the Iberians were? The answer seems to be that
mercantile, protocapitalist centers in West and Central Africa were not
oriented to commerce by sea (as were those of East Africa). The great
long-distance trade routes led across the Sudan to the Nile and the Middle
East, across the Sahara to the Maghreb and the Mediterranean, and so
forth. Sea trade existed all along the western coast, but it was not large in
scale, given that civilizations were mainly inland and trading partners lay
northward and eastward. Second, why did the trading cities of the
Maghreb fail to reach America? This region (as Ibn Khaldun noted not
long before) was in a political and commercial slump. In 1492 it was under
pressure from the Iberians and the Turks. Just at that historical conjunc-
ture, this region lacked a capacity for major long-distance oceanic expedi-
tions. Also, these cities, which traded directly with the Sudan and the gold
regions, did not have the economic incentive that Europeans had to bypass
the Saharan land routes in search of a new — that is, cheaper — source of
gold.
Why the Conquest Was Successful
America became significant in the rise of Europe, and the rise of
capitalism, soon after the first contact in 1492. Immediately a process
began, and explosively enlarged, involving the destruction of American
states and civilizations, the plunder of precious metals, the exploitation of
labor, and the occupation of American lands by Europeans. If we are to
understand the impact of all of this on Europe (and capitalism), we have
to understand how it occurred and why it happened so quickly — why, in
a word, the conquest was successful.
There is a second crucial reason we need to understand the causality
of the conquest. A nondiffusionist history starts all causal arguments with
the working assumption that Europeans had no innate superiority, in any
dimension of culture, over non-Europeans, no a priori "higher potential"
for progress. This leads first to a recognition that Europeans in 1492 had
no special advantage over Asians and Africans, ideological, social, or
material. But it demands that we make the same working hypothesis about
all human communities. Why, then, did Europeans discover America
instead of Americans discovering Europe (or Africa, or Asia)? And why,
after the first contact, did Europeans conquer the American civilizations
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
instead of being defeated and driven from America's shores? The working
assumption of cultural uniformitarianism — or, if you prefer, the psychic
unity of humankind — here confronts the diffusionist tendency to dismiss
the peoples of America as primitive and irrelevant. 5
There were several immediate reasons why American civilizations
succumbed, but one of these is of paramount importance and probably
constitutes a sufficient cause in and of itself. This is the massive depopula-
tion caused by the pandemics of Eastern Hemisphere diseases that were
introduced to America by Europeans. 6 A second factor was the considera-
ble advantage Europeans held in military technology, but this advantage
has to be kept in perspective. The technological gap was not so great that
it could by itself bring military victory — after the initial battles — against
American armies that were vastly larger and would sooner or later have
adopted the enemy's technology. America is a vast territory, and in 1492
it had a very large population, numbering at least 50 million people and
conceivably as many as 200 million, a goodly proportion of these people
living in state-organized societies with significant military capability.?
Military technology tends, historically, to diffuse from one camp to the
opposing camp in a relatively short time. Moreover, the superiority of the
Spaniards' primitive guns was not really very great when compared with
the Americans' bows and arrows. I think it is, therefore, certain that the
tide would have turned against the Europeans had the matter been merely
one of military capability. There would have been no conquest, or the
conquest would have embraced only a limited territory, and certainly
would not have swept south as far as the great civilizations of the central
Andes. The point is that history went in a different direction because of
the incredibly severe and incredibly rapid impact of introduced diseases.
Resistance collapsed because the Americans were dying in epidemics even
before the battles were joined. 8 Probably 90% of the population of central
Mexico was wiped out during the sixteenth century; the majority of these
deaths occurred early enough to assist the political conquest. Parallel
processes took place in other parts of the hemisphere, especially where
there were major concentrations of population, these in most cases being
areas of state organization and high civilization. Perhaps three-quarters of
the entire population of America was wiped out during that century. 9
Millions died in battle with the Spaniards and Portuguese and in forced-
labor centers such as the mines of Mexico and Peru, but much greater
numbers died in epidemics, and this was the reason that resistance to the
conquest was rapidly overcome in most areas.
Both the susceptibility of American populations to Eastern Hemi-
sphere diseases and the lower level of military technology among Western
Hemisphere peoples can be explained in fairly straightforward cultural-
AFTER 1492
evolutionary terms, although evidence bearing on the matter is partly
indirect. The Western Hemisphere was not occupied by humans until very
late in the Paleolithic period; there is dispute about the first arrivals, but
most scholars do not believe that the Americas were occupied before
30,000 b.p. The first immigrants did not possess agriculture. The earliest
migrations preceded the Agricultural Revolution in the Eastern Hemi-
sphere; in addition, the source area for the migrations, northeastern
Siberia, is generally too cold for agriculture, even for present-day agricul-
ture, and we would not expect to find that these cultures were experiment-
ing with incipient agriculture 20,000 years or so ago although some
low-latitude cultures were doing so. Migrants to America were paleolithic
hunters, gatherers, fishers, and shellfishers. They came in small numbers,
apparently in a widely spaced series of relatively small population move-
ments, and spread throughout both North and South America. Only after
some millennia had passed was the stock of resources for hunting, fishing,
gathering, and shellfishing under any significant pressure from humans.
One assumes that population growth was slow but — this is of course
speculative — that population growth eventually did reach the point where
conditions were favorable to an Agricultural Revolution. 10 In the Eastern
Hemisphere the Agricultural Revolution seems to have occurred (as a
qualitative change) roughly 10,000-12,000 years ago. In the Western
Hemisphere that point may have been reached about 4,000 years later. 11
Thereafter, cultural evolution in the Western Hemisphere proceeded
along lines somewhat parallel to those of Eastern Hemisphere evolution:
the development of agricultural societies, of monumental ceremonial
centers, science, writing, cities, feudal class structures, and mercantile
trade. It seems, indeed, that the Western Hemisphere societies were
closing the gap. But in 1492, military technology in the most advanced
and powerful states was still well behind that of Eastern Hemisphere states.
Metal was just coming into use in this arena, and guns had not been
invented. Hence the superiority of Cortes's armies over Moctezuma's and
Pizarro's over the Incas'. (When Cortes arrived at Tenochtitlan the Aztecs
were already dying in great numbers from European diseases which,
apparently, had been carried by American traders from Cuba to Mexico.
Likewise, the Incas apparently were succumbing to these diseases before
Pizarro arrived. 12 )
The susceptibility of American populations to Eastern Hemisphere
diseases, and the consequent devastation of American settlements, col-
lapse of states, and defeat and subjugation by the Europeans, is explained
within the same general model. Small populations entered America and
probably bore with them only a small subset of the diseases that existed in
the Eastern Hemisphere at the time of their departure. They came, in
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
addition, from a rather isolated, thinly populated part of the hemisphere,
and a part which, having a cold climate, would have lacked some diseases
characteristic of warm regions. Perhaps more important is the history of
the diseases themselves. Many diseases originated or became epidemiol-
ogically significant during or after the Agricultural Revolution, and have
ecological connections to agriculture, to urbanization, to zoological and
botanical changes in the ecosystems strongly modified by human land use,
and so on. In the Eastern Hemisphere humanity entered these ecological
situations after the initial migrations to the Western Hemisphere, hence
these migrants to America would not have carried these diseases with
them. Later migrants may have done so (although this is again unlikely
because they came from a cold and isolated part of Asia, and came in small
numbers). But we can assume that the sparse settlement, the hunting-
gathering-fishing-shellfishing way of life, and the absence of agricultural
settlements and urbanization in the Americas during many millennia,
would have caused a disappearance of some of the Eastern Hemisphere
diseases that had been carried across to the Americas by migrants. After a
time the American populations would have lost their physiological
immunities to diseases no longer present in these populations, and they
would of course lack immunities to diseases never before encountered. It is
known, in this regard, that utter devastation was produced in the Americas
from diseases to which Eastern Hemisphere populations had such high
levels of immunity that they experienced these diseases as minor maladies
only.
Hence there is no need to take seriously any longer the various myths
that explain the defeat of the Americans in terms of imputed irrationality
or superstitiousness or any of the other classical, often racist, myths about
American civilizations in 1492. (The most widely known of these myths
is the idea that Mexicans imagined that Cortes and his troops were gods,
and fell down before them in awe instead of fighting. This did not
happen.) The relatively minor difference in technology between the two
communities, and the impact of Eastern Hemisphere diseases upon West-
ern Hemisphere communities, can be explained in terms of the settlement
history of the Western Hemisphere and its consequences. The Americans
were not conquered: they were infected.
Europe in 1492
In 1492, European society was rather sluggishly moving out of feudalism
and toward capitalism. Nothing in the landscape would suggest that a
revolutionary transformation was imminent, or even that the social and
economic changes taking place were very rapid. The growth of the
AFTER 1492
English woolen trade in the fifteenth century was not (as it is often
depicted) a sign of revolutionary economic change: it was complemented
by a decline in competing woolen industries in southern Europe. 13 Rural
growth in this century reflected mainly population recovery (in some
areas) after the great plagues of the preceding century, and the
commercialization of agriculture that was then taking place had been
doing so for some time. 14 Towns were growing, but only slowly, and the
urban population was still only a small fraction of total population
(except in Italy and the Low Countries); and the urban population of
Europe was smaller than it was in many non-European areas. 15 There were
strong signs even of economic contraction instead of growth. 16 The
Italian Renaissance, in economic terms, did not raise the Italian centers
above the level of many non-European centers, including those in nearby
Islamic countries (for instance, Cairo), and the Renaissance was not at all
a technological revolution. 17 All of this needs to be said by way of setting
the stage. Before 1492 there was slow growth in Europe, perhaps even a
downturn. Certainly — and this is accepted by the majority of European
historians — no truly revolutionary transformation was underway in 1492.
Within a few decades after 1492 the rate of growth and change
speeded up dramatically, and Europe clearly entered a period of rapid
metamorphosis. There is no dispute about this fact, which is seen in the
known statistics relating to prices, urban growth, and much more beside. 18
What is disputable is the causal connection between these explosive
sixteenth-century changes and the beginnings of economic exploitation
in America (and, significantly but secondarily, in Africa and Asia). There
is agreement that the effect was profound. But did it truly generate a
qualitative transformation in Europe's economy? Or did it suddenly
quicken a process already well underway? Or did it merely modify this
process slightly with effects such as inflation? This question cannot be
answered unless we break out of the European historical tunnel and look
at, what was going on in America, Asia, and Africa between 1492 and
1688, the symbolic date for Europe's bourgeois revolution.
COLONIALISM AND THE RISE
OF EUROPE, 1492-1688
Colonialism and Capitalism in the Sixteenth Century
Enterprise in the Americas was from the start a matter of capital
accumulation: of profit. No matter if some elements of medieval law
were incorporated in legal and land-granting systems in (for
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Europeans) the New World, and if the Iberian governments took a
substantial, though usually overestimated, portion of the profits. The
goal of all European individuals and groups involved in the enterprise,
clergy apart, was to make money, for oneself or one's country (usually
the former).
The leading group, almost everywhere, was the European
protocapitalist class, not only merchants but also industrialists and
profit-oriented landlords — not only Iberian but also Italian, Flemish,
Dutch, German, English, and so on. This class community took its
profit from American enterprise and invested part of it in Europe,
buying land and developing commercial agriculture, developing
industries (like shipbuilding, sugar refining, and so on) that were
associated with the growing colonial enterprise, developing profitable
businesses in spheres of activity which served the growing European
economy (for instance, the burgeoning Atlantic fisheries), building
urban structures, and the like. Part of the profit was plowed back into
additional colonial risk enterprise, in America and in the new trading
enterprises in southern Asia, Africa, and the Levant. One of the
deceptively subtle aspects of the process was the immense increase in
purchases of all sorts by European merchants in all markets, inside and
outside of Europe, growing out of the fact that these merchants now
had incredible amounts of precious metals or metal-based money at
their command and could offer previously unheard-of prices. Perhaps
half the gold and silver brought back from America in the sixteenth
century was contraband, hence available directly for this kind of
enterprise, but the remainder, after passing through the great customs
houses, quickly entered circulation as the Iberian governments paid
out gold and silver for goods and services. 19
Colonial enterprise in the sixteenth century produced capital in
a number of ways. One was gold and silver mining. A second was
plantation agriculture, principally in Brazil. A third was the trade with
Asia in spices, cloth, and the like. A fourth and by no means minor
element was the profit returned to European investors from a variety of
productive and commercial enterprises in the Americas, including
profit on production for local use in Mexico, Peru, and elsewhere;
profit on sale of goods imported from Europe; profit on a variety of
secondary exports from America (leather, dyestuffs, etc.); profit on
land sales in America; profit returned to Europe by families and
corporations holding land grants in Mexico and other areas. A fifth
was slaving. A sixth, piracy. Notice that all of this is normal capital
accumulation; none of it is the mysterious thing called "primitive
accumulation." 20 (Value from wage labor, not to mention forced
AFTER 1492
labor, was involved, and much of it was value from production, not
simply from trade.) Accumulation from these sources was massive. It
was massive enough so that the process cannot be dismissed as a minor
adjunct of protocapitalist accumulation in Europe itself, and it was
massive enough, I believe, to fuel a major transformation in Europe,
the rise to power of the bourgeoisie and the immense efflorescence of
preindustrial capitalism, in ways that we will discuss.
Precious Metals
We notice first the export of gold and silver from the Americas and its
insertion within the circuits of an Eastern Hemispheric market economy
in which gold and silver already provide the common measure of value,
directly or indirectly, in almost all markets. The flow of precious metals
began immediately after the European discovery of America, and by 1640
at least 180 tons of gold and 17,000 tons of silver are known to have
reached Europe. 21 (The real figures must be at least double these amounts,
since records were poor for some areas and periods and since contraband
was immensely important. 22 ) Additional quantities of gold came from
colonial activities in Africa. In the period 1561 to 1580 about 85% of the
entire world's production of silver came from the Americas. The simple
quantity of gold and silver in circulation in the Eastern Hemisphere
economy as a whole was profoundly affected: hemispheric silver stock
may have been tripled and gold stock increased by 20% during the course
of the sixteenth century as a result of bullion brought from America. 23
The fact that much of the pre-existing stock must have been frozen in uses
not permitting direct or indirect conversion to money suggests to me that
American bullion may have as much as doubled the gold- and silver-based
money supply of the Eastern Hemisphere as a whole. (In Europe, the
circulation of metal coins increased eight- or ten-fold in the course of the
century. 24 ) This process must be seen in perspective: it is money flowing
constantly and in massive amounts into Europe, through Europe, and
from Europe to Asia and Africa, constantly replenished at the entry
points (Seville, Antwerp, Genoa, etc.) with more American supplies, and
constantly permitting those who hold it to offer better prices for all
goods — as well as labor and land — in all markets, than anyone else had
ever been able to offer in prior times.
The importance of these flows of gold and silver is routinely
underestimated by scholars, mainly for three reasons (apart from implicit
diffusionism, the simple tendency to undervalue causal events in
non-Europe). First, the process is seen somehow as purely primitive
accumulation. But the metals were mined by workers and transported by
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
workers; the enterprise overall involved risk capital and all of the other
familiar traits of the sorts of protocapitalist productive enterprises which
were characteristic of that time (that it was partly state-controlled does
not alter this argument, nor does the fact that some of the labor was
unfree); and very major economic and social systems were built around
the mines themselves in Mexico, Peru, and other parts of America.
Second, the argument that precious metal flows significantly
affected the European economy is dismissed by some scholars as
"monetarism" (roughly, the theory that changes in money alone are very
significant for changes in the economy overall). The error in this charge
is a failure to see the sixteenth-century economy in its own, appropriate,
geographical and social context, and to impute to the economy of that
time the liquidity of exchange and the relative lack of spatial friction that
characterizes the capitalist economy of our own time. Two facts here are
basic. First of all, the possession of precious metal was highly localized in
space. European merchants, as a community, obtained it and set it in
motion outward, toward rural Europe and toward markets outside of
Europe. Second of all, the supply of precious metal was essentially
continuous, and therefore the advantage held by European protocapital-
ists in terms of prices they could offer for commodities, labor, and land was
persistently higher than the prices which competitors anywhere could
offer. So the protocapitalist community very steadily undermined the
competition in all markets across the Eastern Hemisphere, within Europe
and without, eventually gaining control of most international seaborne
trade in most of the mercantile— maritime centers from Sofala to Calicut
to Malacca. 25 The penetration of these markets, the acquisition of trading
bases, and the control of a few small but important producing areas (like
some islands of the Moluccas), was not a matter of European rationality
or venturesomeness, but rather reflected the availability to Europeans of
American gold and silver, trans-shipped through Lisbon, Antwerp,
Acapulco (in the "Manila galleons"), and so on.
A third sort of doubt about the importance of American gold and
silver is associated with the critique of Earl Hamilton's classic theory that
the precious metal supply produced an imbalance between factors of
production in the European economy, produced thereby a windfall of
profits, and thus in effect destabilized the economy and moved it toward
capitalism. 26 Hamilton was one of the few economic historians to
perceive that American gold and silver was a crucial, central cause of
change in Europe, although he was (partly) wrong about the mechanisms
that brought about this change. The metals did not transform the
economy in any direct sense. Rather, they enriched the protocapitalist
class and thereby gave them the power to immensely accelerate the
AFTER 1492
transformation that was already underway — not only in Europe — toward
capitalism as a political and social system, and to prevent non-European
capitalists from sharing in the process. American bullion hastened the rise
of capitalism and was crucial in the process by which it became centrated
in Europe.
Plantations
The impact of the slave plantation system on Europe's economy was felt
mainly in the seventeenth century and thereafter. But part of the general
undervaluing of the significance of early colonialism — of the world
outside of Europe — is a tendency not to notice that the plantation system
was of considerable importance even in the sixteenth century. Moreover,
the early history of the Atlantic sugar plantation economy gives a
revealing picture of the way in which the protocapitalist colonial
economy was eroding the feudal economy. Sugar planting was not a new
enterprise; sugar (contrary to myth) was not a rare commodity, and sugar
planting (also contrary to myth) was not an insignificant economic
curiosity at the fringe of capitalist development. Commercial and feudal
cane sugar production was found throughout the Mediterranean in the
fifteenth century. 27 Although little is known about the way planting was
organized, it is known that commercial sugar production was important in
India 2,000 years ago (apparently it was a Mauryan state industry), and in
the Middle Ages commercial sugar planting under various feudal and
probably protocapitalist systems of organization was found in East Africa,
part of West Africa, Morocco, Egypt, Cyprus, the Levant, various parts of
Mediterranean Europe, and other regions. 28 If cane sugar was not an
important commodity in northern Europe this was because of its price, as
against that of sweeteners like honey. Europeans first moved the
commercial plantation system out into the newly settled Atlantic islands
from Madeira to Sao Tome" and then vastly expanded production in the
Americas. But throughout the sixteenth century the new plantations
merely supplanted the older Mediterranean sugar-producing regions; total
production for the Europe-Mediterranean market did not rise until
later. 29 This was capitalist production displacing feudal and semifeudal
plantation production, using the twin advantages of colonialism: empty
land and cheap labor. No other industry was as significant as the
plantation system for the rise of capitalism before the nineteenth century.
In 1600 Brazil exported about 30,000 tons of sugar with a gross sale
value of £2,000,000. This is about double the total annual value of all
exports from England to all of the world in that period. 30 It will be recalled
that British exports in that period, principally of wool, are sometimes
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
considered paradigmatic for the "awakening," indeed the "rise," of early-
modern Europe. Also in 1600, per capita earnings from sugar in Brazil, for
all except Indians, was about equal to per capita income in Britain later in
that century. 31 The rate of accumulation in the Brazilian plantation
industry was so high at the end of the sixteenth century that it was able to
generate enough capital to finance a doubling of its capacity every two
years. 32 Early in the seventeenth century the Dutch protocapitalist com-
munity (which was heavily involved in the Brazilian sugar enterprise,
mainly in the shipping and sales dimensions) calculated that profit rates in
the industry were 56% per year, totalling nearly £1,000,000 per year. The
rate of profit was higher still a bit earlier, at the close of the sixteenth
century, when production costs, including the cost of purchasing slaves,
amounted to only one-fifth of income from sugar sales. These statistics
should be seen against the background of an industry that was not
responding to some novel demand for some novel product in an already-
rising Europe, but was merely (in essence) undercutting the precapitalist
Mediterranean producers of Spain, Italy, Morocco, Egypt, and elsewhere,
in the supply of a highly important commercial product.
Sugar is of course the centerpiece of the plantation system down to
the late eighteenth century. But other kinds of colonial production,
mainly but not only agricultural, and fully as close to capitalism as was
the Brazil plantation system, were of some significance even before the
end of the sixteenth century. There was, for instance, some direct
production of spices in the Moluccas and some European involvement
with Indian merchant capitalists in the organization pepper production
in South India. Dyes, tobacco, and other commercially valuable products
were flowing from America to Europe. A very large agricultural economy
existed in parts of America to supply food, fiber, leather, and other
necessities to the mining settlements and other settlements. Immediately
after 1492 (or before?) west European fishermen and whalers developed
an immense industry in Newfoundland and elsewhere on the North
American coast.
To all of this must be added the profits from other sorts of colonial
and semicolonial activities in the Eastern Hemisphere. 33 The slave trade
was highly profitable even in the sixteenth century. European merchant
capitalists of all nations profited greatly from the Lisbon trade with Asia
and East Africa in textiles and particularly spices (the Asian spices carried
by the Portuguese and sold mainly through Antwerp did not replace the
traditional Mediterranean flow but rather added to it, hence providing a
novel and important source of accumulation). There was, in addition,
considerable profit from the within-Asia trade resulting from the
domination of long-distance oceanic trade in East Africa, India, and
AFTER 1492
Southeast Asia by Portugal (with participation also by Spain and later
Holland). Broadly speaking, however, accumulation deriving from
Western Hemisphere colonial activities far outweighed that from Eastern
Hemisphere activities, colonial and semicolonial, in the sixteenth
century. Overall, both the quantitative significance, in that century, of
production and trade in colonial and semicolonial areas and the immense
profitability of the enterprise, that is, the rapid capital accumulation
which it fostered directly and (in Europe) indirectly, add up to a
significant vector force, easily able to change the process of economic
transformation in Europe from sluggish evolution to rapid revolution.
Effects
There seem to be two particularly good ways to assess the real significance
for the rise of capitalism of sixteenth-century colonial production in
America, and some other areas, along with trading, piracy, and the like,
in Asia and Africa. One way is to trace the direct and indirect effects of
colonialism on European society, looking for movements of goods and
capital, tracing labor flows into industries and regions stimulated or
created by colonial enterprise, and looking at the way urbanization
nourished in those cities that were engaged in colonial (and more
generally extra-European) enterprise or closely connected to it, and the
like. This processes overall would then be examined in relation to the
totality of changes taking place in Europe in that century, to determine
whether, in Europe itself, changes clearly resulting from the direct and
indirect impact of extra-European activities were the prime movers for
economic and social change. This task still remains undone. The second
way is to attempt to arrive at a global calculation of the amount of labor
(free and unfree) that was employed in European enterprises in America,
Africa, and Asia, along with the amount of labor in Europe itself which
was employed in activities derived from extra-European enterprise, and
then to look at these quantities in relation to the total labor market in
Europe for economic activities that can be thought of as connected to the
rise of capitalism. This task has not been done either; indeed, as far as I
know little research has been done on sixteenth-century labor forces and
labor markets in American settlements or indeed in Europe. So the
proposition which I am arguing here, concerning the significance of
sixteenth-century colonialism (and related extra-European activities) for
the rise of capitalism in Europe, perhaps cannot be tested as yet.
Still, there are suggestive indications. Some of these have been
mentioned already: matters of assessing the quantities and values of
colonial exports to Europe. We can also speculate about labor. One
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
approach is through population. The population of Spain and Portugal in
the mid-sixteenth century may have been around nine million. 3 ^
Estimates of sixteenth-century populations for America vary widely and
there is much controversy about population levels and rates of decline, 35
but for the present, highly speculative, and essentially methodological,
argument, I will ignore the controversies and play with global estimates.
The population of Mexico at midcentury may have been around six
million, a population that was undergoing continuous decline from its
preconquest level of perhaps 30 million down to one-tenth of that figure
(or perhaps less) in 1600. 36 Populations in the Andean regions involved
in mineral and textile production for the Spaniards may (I am
speculating) have totalled five million in the late sixteenth century.
Perhaps we can add an additional two million for the population of other
parts of Ibero- America that were within regions of European control and
presumably involved, more or less, in the European-dominated economy.
Let us, then, use a ball-park estimate of 13 million for the American
population that was potentially yielding surplus value to Europeans in the
mid-to-late sixteenth century. The population seems larger than that of
Iberia. Granted, the comparison should be made with a larger part of
Europe, certainly including the Low Countries, which were intimately
involved in the exploitation of America (and Asia) at this period, along
with parts of Italy and other countries. Assume then a figure of 20 million
for Europe as against 13 million for America.
I see no reason to argue that the European populations were more
intimately involved in the rise of capitalism than the American
populations — that is, the 13 million people who we assume were in
European-dominated regions. It is likely that the proportion of the
American population that was engaged in labor for Europeans, as wage
work, as forced labor including slave labor, and as the labor of farmers
delivering goods as tribute or rent in kind, was no lower than the
proportion of Iberian people engaged in labor for commercialized sectors
of the Spanish and Portuguese economy. Moreover, the level of
exploitation for Indian labor must have been much higher than that for
Iberian labor because portions of the Indian labor force were worked
literally to death in this period — depopulation was due in part to forced
labor — and so the capital generated by each American worker must have
been higher than that generated by a European worker. (We need to
remind ourselves again that we are dealing with a preindustrial, basically
medieval economy in Europe. It cannot be argued, for instance, that
technology or fixed capital in production was more advanced in the
utilization of European than in that of American labor, so exploitation
was in the last analysis a function of human effort.)
AFTER 1492
We must next take into account the fact that the capital
accumulated from the labor of Americans went directly to the economic
sectors in Europe that were building capitalism, whereas most workers and
peasants in Europe were still connected to essentially medieval sectors of
the economy. Then we must add the labor of Africans and Asians. And
finally, we must take into account the European workers, in Europe and
elsewhere, whose labor must be considered part of the extra-European
economy. By this admittedly speculative reasoning, free and unfree
workers in the colonial and semicolonial economy of the late sixteenth
century were providing as much or more surplus value and accumulated
capital for European protocapitalism, the rising bourgeoisie, as were the
workers of Europe itself.
Little is known about the American work force in the sixteenth
century, but, again, some speculations are possible. Las Casas asserted that
three million or more Indians had been enslaved by the Spaniards in the
northern part of Spanish America during the first half of the sixteenth
century, and this figure, once dismissed, is now taken seriously. 37 It is
known that more than 400,000 were enslaved in Nicaragua alone. 38 It is
realized also that Indian slave labor was extremely important in the
European economy of America in that period, in Brazilian sugar planting,
Mesoamerican and Antillean mining, and elsewhere. Let us speculate
that 100,000 Indians were working as slaves for Spaniards in a given year
in the mid-sixteenth century. Perhaps 20,000 Indians were working at
free and forced labor in the mines of Mexico and the Andes in the latter
part of the century, 39 and it is safe to assume that five times that number
were involved in the mining economy overall. Potosf, the great Andean
silver-mining city, had a population of 120,000 in the 1570s (larger than
Paris, Rome, Madrid, Seville). A much greater but unknown number of
Indians were workers on haciendas and other European enterprises, or
provided periodic forced labor, or provided tribute and rent in kind. (The
Cortes encomienda in Mexico included 50,000 Indians. 40 ) There may
have been 100,000 African slaves in America and on the island of Sao
Tome in the closing years of the century. 41 There may have been 300,000
Europeans, Mulattos, and Mestizos in the Americas in 1570,42 of whom
conceivably as many as 250,000 were workers.
Perhaps it would not be unreasonable to estimate that one million
people were working in the European economy of the Western
Hemisphere in the closing years of the sixteenth century, perhaps half of
them engaged in productive labor in distinctly capitalist enterprises. Can
this have been more than the European protocapitalist work force of the
time? All of this is somewhat speculative, but it points toward the
conclusion that American labor was a truly massive part of the total labor
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
of this we must add three additional quantities: labor involved in the slave
trade within continental Africa; 43 labor in other extra-European regions
(Sao Tome, Ternate, Calicut, and so on) that was incorporated into the
European economy or produced goods for trade to Europeans; and labor of
Europeans, inside and outside of Europe, which was part of the
extra-European economy — sailors, soldiers, stevedores, teamsters, clerks,
foremen, and the rest.
By the end of the sixteenth century the rise of Europe had well
begun. As capital flowed into Europe, and as other effects of colonial
enterprise also flowed into the European system or region, secondary
causation appeared, including agricultural expansion and transformation,
primitive manufacturing, urbanization, and expansion of rural settlements
and the commercial economy. These latter have been looked at carefully
but in a mainly tunnel-historical framework; as a result, the rise of Europe
in the sixteenth century has appeared to be a process taking place wholly
within the European spatial system, and caused wholly (or mainly) by
autochthonous forces. As we have seen, this is an inaccurate picture and
an incomplete one. Urbanization was taking place, but mainly in areas
connected to the extra-European economy. Inflation was also (with some
qualifications) most severe in these areas. 44 Among the sectors of the
European economy that were growing in the sixteenth century, some, like
piracy and shipbuilding, were tied directly to the extra-European
economy, while others, like wheat production and North Atlantic
fishing, were stimulated directly and indirectly by that economy. 45
I would generalize as follows. The initiating condition, at the
beginning of the sixteenth century, is a west and central European
economy that is undergoing slow but definite change toward capitalism —
as are many regions of Asia and Africa at that same time. Novel forces
intrude into the European system, as impinging boundary processes,
because of the conquest of America and the other extra-European events,
intruding processes which consist mainly of capital and material products
(and of course the labor embedded in these things). These then intersect
with the ongoing evolving economic, technological, demographic, and
other changes. Many new changes appear, as a result not of direct stimulus
from the extra-European world but from the changes already underway,
which themselves are mainly results of those extra-European boundary
processes. The internal European changes of course feed forward to
produce intensification of the processes going on in America, Asia, etc.,
and these, in turn, produce still more changes within Europe.
We can see a geographical pattern in all of this. There is a tendency
for major economic changes to occur first near the mercantile-maritime
centers that participate in the extra- European processes. Obviously, not
AFTER 1492
centers that participate in the extra-European processes. Obviously, not
all of the centers that existed in 1492 were equal participants in that
process, with some of the Iberian, Italian, and Flemish port cities taking
the lead. But the network was sufficiently tight so that Hanseatic and
English ports were early participants, as were inland cities with special
economic characteristics, like Augsburg and Paris. From these many
centers, the process spread into the interior of Europe, first into areas that
supplied basic staple goods like wheat — the growth at that time of the
Baltic wheat trade and manorial production of wheat in parts of central
and east Europe is well known — and then elsewhere. At any given time
we see a broad and irregular spatial pattern (of the type which geographers
call "distance decay") of descending levels of urbanization and
commercial production as we move across the landscape toward interior
Europe.
Other processes were underway as well, and so the pattern that I have
mapped out here is much too simple. Population growth in some areas
reflected sixteenth-century economic changes associated with extra-
European events but in other areas it signified recovery from the
fourteenth- and fifteenth-century population declines. Other changes,
such as peasant revolts, reflected the general crisis of the late feudal
economy, but the sixteenth-century rise of prices and (at least in some
areas) rents was a contributing force in the unrest. As to the Reformation,
I would argue in the Tawneyan tradition that it was broadly an effect, not
an independent cause, of the economic changes that were taking place in
Europe in the sixteenth century. 46 But which changes? The internal
crumbling of feudalism? The forces impinging from the extra-European
world? Both? Probably the spatial diffusion of the Reformation in the
sixteenth century reflected mainly intra-European forces, 47 but by the
time of the seventeenth-century bourgeois revolutions, the areas most
deeply involved in extra-European activities tended to be centers also of
Protestantism. In short: the spatial patterns of change in sixteenth-
century Europe reflect to some extent the integration of Europe with
America, and secondarily Africa and Asia, but the pattern is still
somewhat unclear.
Overall, the processes of transformation and modernization in
sixteenth-century Europe were terribly complex, varying in time and
place throughout most of that continent. But the generalization is
nonetheless fairly straightforward. The extra-European component, after
1492, led to an immense stimulation of changes in Europe, those that
produced on the one hand an increase in the rate of European economic
change and growth, and on the other hand the beginnings of a centration
of capitalism in Europe (a process discussed further below). By the end of
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
the sixteenth century these extra-European forces had laid the foundation
for the political and social triumph of (preindustrial) capitalism, or rather
for the fact that the Glorious Revolution occurred in 1688, instead of
much later, and in England, instead of Egypt or Zimbabwe or India or
China (or all of these at once).
Colonialism and Capitalism in the
Seventeenth Century
By the middle of the seventeenth century, changes were taking place in
Europe at a rapid rate and on a massive scale, and the problem of sort-
ing out the internal and external causes and effects for this period is a
very complex matter. In this same period there occurred a massive
expansion, in location and intensity, of formal and informal colon-
ialism in the Americas and around the coasts of Africa and Asia, and for
these extra-European processes the problem of complexity is compounded
by a lack of quantitative data regarding volume of production, numbers
in the labor forces, capital accumulation, and other information that
would help us to judge the role of colonialism (as a broad concept) in
the changes that were taking place within Europe. These matters are far
too complex to permit us to discuss them satisfactorily here. I will limit
myself to a rather sketchy intervention or (if you prefer to call it that)
a model.
By the beginning of the seventeenth century, the Netherlands and
England had emerged as the centers (or center) of capitalist development
in Europe. 48 Although Spain continued to feed huge quantities of silver
and some gold into Europe in the first half of this century, and Portuguese
plantations in Brazil and trading activities in Asia continued to be
important fountains of accumulation, the main expansion of colonial
enterprise after 1600 was Dutch and English. The crucial component was
the West Indian plantation system, which expanded explosively after
about 1640. (Fifty thousand slaves were imported into Barbados alone in
the following 50 years. Probably two million slaves were imported into
America in the course of the seventeenth century.) 49 If we place the Dutch
and British sugar colonies in the same economic space as the metropolitan
countries themselves, it seems likely that the sugar plantation economy
was the single largest productive sector in this expanded European
economy (or "Atlantic economy," as it is often called) aside from family
farming, and by far the largest single generator of value. (Brazilian
plantations, producing partly for Dutch capital, were still, in the mid-
seventeenth century, more massive than the West Indian.) But British and
Dutch enterprise in the Eastern Hemisphere was also expanding very
AFTER 1492
rapidly; the East India companies were formed around 1600, and by 1650
the Dutch and British together controlled most of the intercontinental
trade — unequal trade, and in a sense semicolonial trade — with Asia, as
well as the slave trade in Africa. Meanwhile, Spanish enterprise was
yielding substantial accumulation in America (whether or not there was a
"seventeenth-century depression"). And we must not ignore the great
variety of additional extra-European sources of accumulation: a now
massive fishing industry in the northwestern Atlantic, resource extraction
and the beginnings of European settlement in North America, the slave
trade, piracy, Russian enterprise in Siberia, and much more.
The key question is this: How central was the role played by colonial
and semicolonial enterprise in the seventeenth-century rise of Europe and
of capitalism within Europe? The model I would build involves two
elements. The first is a continuation and enlargement of the sixteenth-
century processes, which, as I argued, involved a sluggishly growing
European economy quickened into rapid development by extra-European
forces after 1492. By the middle of the next century the European
bourgeoisie had strengthened their class position and (in the key
locations) had enticed much of the feudal aristocracy into joining
bourgeois enterprise, 50 and had well begun the process of destroying
protocapitalist enterprise outside of Europe, as a result of the inflowing
capital from America (and secondarily in that period, Africa and Asia).
Now, apart from stocks of precious metal, it is improbable that
capital accumulated from extra-European enterprise in 1500-1650
amounted to a sizeable share of total invested capital in Europe, even in
the more advanced regions of Europe, even in the economic sectors in
which capital was more or less fluid. What it did do was provide a critical
increment: everywhere it allowed the merchant-entrepreneurial commu-
nity to offer higher prices for products, labor, and land; everywhere it put
investment capital in the hands of classes and communities other than
the traditional elite, the group less likely to accumulate beyond its social
needs and less likely to reinvest profits in new ventures. Colonial capital,
in a word, was new capital. Without it, the sluggish late-medieval
economy of pre- 1492 days would have continued its slow progress out of
feudalism and toward capitalism (or something like capitalism), but there
would have been no Seventeenth-Century Bourgeois Revolution.
Perhaps the essence of capitalism, at a level of aggregation above the
worker-capitalist class relation, is the reinvestment of profits to enlarge
productive capacity. Capitalist enterprise can be technologically primi-
tive or advanced but always, to survive, it must accumulate capital. It is
never in equilibrium. This point leads us to focus on the conditions that
permitted continued growth, exponential growth, in the sixteenth and
200 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
seventeenth centuries. This growth did not involve technological change
in any important way: production increases were mainly matters of
drawing more workers and more productive materials into traditional
productive processes to yield more output. Given the fact that capital for
expansion was available because of the extra-European enterprises and
other, related developments, the key problem in the seventeenth century
must have been markets, or demand. The capitalist had access to capital,
had access to labor — at the levels of production then prevailing a truly
massive proletarianization was not necessary — and had access to raw
materials (some European, some colonial). The growth of a capitalist
enterprise in that period was perhaps constrained most seriously by the
need to open up new markets: to sell more of the product so that more
could be produced, more capital generated, and so on.
Some of these markets were in Europe itself, reflecting at first the
ability of capitalist enterprise to sell traditional products (like sugar) at
lower costs than prevailed under the feudal economy, but gradually the
urbanization and commercialization of the continent brought in feedback
loops so that the newer way of life, generated by the rise of capitalism,
itself generated more internal markets for capitalism. But probably the
main growth of markets for protocapitalist enterprise in the seventeenth
century, and thus the main stimulus for the rise of capitalism, was outside
the system. This is well known in the case of trade with eastern Europe.
It is known in the case of markets in America, Africa, and Asia, but the
quantitative significance of these extra-European markets has not been
fully evaluated. In the case of the English bourgeoisie, the main markets
for capitalist enterprise, including agricultural and nonagricultural
products from England and re-exported products from abroad, were in
America, Africa, and Asia, along with nontraditional markets in the
Baltic. For the Dutch, extra-European commerce was even more
important. Italian communities continued to depend considerably on the
eastern Mediterranean.
In the seventeenth century, then, the crucial role of the extra-
European world, added on to and perhaps more significant than its
sixteenth-century role as provider of bullion and some other products, was
to permit an expansion of demand — including forced demand, as on the
slave plantations — for capitalist products, a demand sufficiently great so
that productive capacity and output of capitalist enterprises could
continue to grow at an incredibly fast rate. This growth in output was one
of the two essential seventeenth-century forces involved in the rise of
capitalism. The second force was, simply, the political triumph itself, the
bourgeois revolution. This provided the bourgeoisie with the legal and
AFTER 1492
political power to rip apart the fabric of the society in its quest for
accumulation. Forced proletarianization thereby became possible, as did
government support for almost any strategy that the new accumulating
elite had in mind. And an Industrial Revolution, a transformation of the
methods of production so that output could increase at an even greater
rate, became (one might say) inevitable.
THE CENTRATION OF CAPITALISM
The phrase "the rise of capitalism" generally evokes an image of factories,
steam engines, masses of wage workers, cities grimy with coal dust:
industrial capitalism. Our discussion thus far has not dealt with the rise of
industrial capitalism — the Industrial Revolution — but with the precur-
sors to that momentous event. But let me, for a moment, review some of
these precursors.
Before 1492, most of the preconditions that would be critical for the
eventual rise of industrial capitalism were present not merely in parts of
Europe but also in parts of Asia and Africa. After 1492, in the sixteenth
and seventeenth centuries, Europe acquired three additional precondi-
tions. One was the very considerable accumulation of wealth from the
mines and plantations of America and from trade in Asia and Africa. The
second, closely related to the first, was the huge enlargement of markets
outside of western Europe for products either produced in western Europe
or imported and then reexported; that is, a very great and almost
constantly growing demand. Third, and most important of all, the social
sectors involved with capitalism took political power on a wide scale in
western Europe, something that had not happened elsewhere except on
very small terrains. This, the bourgeois revolution, allowed the emerging
capitalist class-community to mobilize state power toward its further rise,
such that the entire society contributed to the underwriting of colonial
adventures and to the preparation of infrastructure such as cities and
roads, while the state's police and military power could now be mobilized
to force people off the land and into wage work, and to conscript people
and resources for advantageous wars abroad. All three of these precursors,
as I have argued, appeared because of — or would not have appeared had
it not been for — colonialism.
Historians engage in fierce debates about the causes of the Industrial
Revolution. Most of the candidate causes, or "factors," are theories within
the "European miracle" category which we discussed and tried to refute in
Chapter 2. Propositions about, for instance, general medieval moderniza-
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
tion of the European economy and polity, medieval technological
revolutions, "rationality" in medieval and later times, and the like, are
built into the most common explanations for the later emergence of an
Industrial Revolution. We showed, I hope, that all of these processes were
at work outside of Europe as well as inside, so that they cannot be enlisted
as causes of an event that happened only in Europe.
This is a problem where the sequence and dating of events is
extremely important. The concept of the Industrial Revolution is usually
bound up with two more specific transformations: the development of
steam power and generally novel technology in industrial production, and
the development of wage labor in industrial production. But the timing is
wrong. The technological part of the Industrial Revolution became
important very late in the process, too late to explain the revolution itself.
It is certainly true that technological advances were taking place in
European manufacturing during the period from 1492 to, say, 1750, but
very little of this technology was unique to Europe, as we have seen, and,
most crucially, the technological advances that eventually became
important in increasing manufacturing production and increasing labor
efficiency in that production occurred much later: in the last decades of
the eighteenth century and, much more profusely, in the nineteenth
century. In agriculture, the main technological advances were matters of
increasing areal productivity in an environment of declining agricultural
labor, but all of the essential technological changes that were involved in
this process were traditional and were known outside of Europe. (A few
scholars give great weight to newer crops like turnips, but such matters
were of very minor importance — setting aside the much earlier
introduction of the potato — compared to such things as the increased use
of capital and purchased input nutrients. The fact that farmers in western
Europe learned how to increase their production while decreasing labor
inputs is not at all novel in the history and geography of agriculture. Thus
the agricultural revolution of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
can be considered an effect, not a cause, in the industrializing and
urbanizing process.) So the technological side of the Industrial Revolu-
tion was not primary cause except as it may have been primary cause for
a hemisphere-wide and very slow transformation, as we discussed
previously. It appeared too late.
A somewhat similar argument can be given in response to the thesis
that the development, by capitalism, of mass wage labor in manufacturing
production was primary cause of the Industrial Revolution. This argument
is most commonly put forth by those Marxist economists who hold to a
strict construction of one of the arguments in Marx's Capital. It is
indisputable that you cannot have fully mature industrial capitalism
AFTER 1492
without basing it in a wage-labor setting that is also a (relatively) free
labor market, one in which workers can go from employer to employer.
But these conditions did not exist prior to the late eighteenth century.
Wage labor was predominant, but little of it was employed in
manufacturing, and hardly ever did a worker confront a really free labor
market, with real choices as to place of employment. These were features
of industrial capitalism as it emerged after the Industrial Revolution really
got rolling.
All such theories about the causes of the Industrial Revolution are
diffusionist in the sense, and to the degree, that they see the process as an
internal evolution within European history and society. As we noted in
Chapter 2, an antidiffusionist, anti-Eurocentric body of historical theory
has been developing over the past 50-odd years, a body of theory
developed mainly, but not solely, by scholars from the extra-European
world. In no other arena of historical discussion has this emerging critical
school had as great an impact as it has had on the debates about the
origins of the Industrial Revolution.
The thesis that industrial development in Europe depended in many
ways on colonial processes was widely accepted in the eighteenth and
early nineteenth centuries. 51 Later, perhaps because of the growth of
diffusionist ideology with its guiding proposition that Europe is the
autonomous source of progress, this thesis fell into disfavor among
European historians. 52 It was forcefully advanced by a number of colonial
scholars in the 1930s and 1940s. Perhaps understandably it was Indian
scholars who emphasized the fact that a highly developed Indian cotton
textile industry not only provided some of the new technology for
Britain's industry, particularly in dyeing, but also had to be forcibly
suppressed by Britain — in a process which some Indian scholars call "the
de-industrialization of India" — in order to allow the British industry to
develop in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. 53 (The cotton
textile industry was the leading sector in the early Industrial Revolution.)
Also in the 1930s, West Indian scholars, notably C. L. R. James and Eric
Williams, began to advance the thesis that slave-based industry and the
slave trade were crucial causal forces in British and French industrializa-
tion. This general argument evolved into a broad theory which is now
widely argued both by Caribbean scholars — it is sometimes called "the
Caribbean school of history," rather too narrowly — and by others, many
of whom are African-American and African scholars. This theory is of
great importance, and I will try to summarize it briefly, ignoring a number
of secondary disagreements among some of its proponents.
The most basic and general argument, advanced first by C. L. R.
James and Eric Williams, was the proposition that the West Indian
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
slave-based plantation system in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries was a highly advanced form of industrial system, implicitly the
most advanced form in existence at that time. They, and later writers in
the same scholarly tradition, showed that the plantation system involved
very heavy capitalization, complex business organization, very advanced
industrial technology (in milling, rum manufacture, transport, and so on),
a large labor force in the sugar factory as well as in the fields, a
considerable force of free workers and supervisors as well as slaves, and,
most important of all, immense profits — profits not only from the
plantation and its production but also from the slave trade and many
ancillary components of what Williams called "the triangular trade." 54
(Said James in his classic history of the Haitian revolution, The Black
Jacobins, "the slave-trade and slavery were the economic basis of the
French revolution . . . Nearly all the industries which developed in France
during the eighteenth century had their origin in goods or commodities
destined either for the coast of Guinea or for the Americas." 55 ) I would
extend this argument to a slightly more general proposition: Within the
overall economic space which the Europeans controlled in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, they found it possible to advance
the capitalist industrial production system — large-scale, organized, sem-
imechanized — to its highest level, for that era, mainly in the plantation
system, using slave labor, until the evolution of industrial production as
an overall system had evolved sufficiently so that profits could be made
even when the labor force was paid a living wage, a wage permitting
subsistence and reproduction of the working class, and the system could
then be centrated, imported into Europe itself. 56 Stated differently, the
earliest phase of the Industrial Revolution was so crude, undeveloped, and
indeed barbaric that free labor could not be used, if the output was to be
profitable. Therefore, the capture and forced labor of slaves was necessary
for production, or, alternatively, colonial rule elsewhere (as in India) was
needed to force the delivery of commodities at very low prices.
Both James and Williams argued that the profits from this complex
were crucial in providing much, perhaps most, of the capital required in
the early phase of the Industrial Revolution. Williams's book, Capitalism
and Slavery, provided the classic statement of and argument for this thesis.
He showed in great detail how the profits from the slave trade, the slave
plantation, and the ancillary economic sectors flowed into England and
then into the forms of investment that fueled the Industrial Revolution
and its infrastructure (canals, ports, and the like). Most of the mainstream
(European) community of scholars has rejected this theoretical position.
The general view is that the industrial revolution was an almost entirely
intra-European phenomenon, and such matters as the slave trade, the
AFTER 1492
slave plantation, and the profits from all of this had to be merely a detail
or footnote. 57 Periodically, efforts have been made to refute the theory,
but the only part of the theory which has really been subjected to
empirical critique is the most limited and in a way least crucial part.
Engerman and some others tried to show that, if various assumptions of
neoclassical economics are made about the eighteenth-century British
economy, and if traditionally low calculations are used as regards the
number of slaves brought to America, then it would appear that the slave
trade was not really very profitable. But in fact the slave trade itself was
only a part of the overall complex that Williams and others were looking
at; in fact, the plantation as in industrial system was much closer to the
center of their attention because it was here that labor was put to use in
generating mass commodities. Inikori and others have shown that the
numbers of slave transported to the Americas has been underestimated.
Finally, the neoclassical assumptions (among them the argument that
there were "normal" profits in an eighteenth-century industry, as though
the Industrial Revolution and factor and product markets had already
matured) are widely questioned.
Another stream of criticism has come from some Marxists, among
them Brenner and Laclau, who share the Eurocentric-diffusionist views of
the conventional historical school just discussed. 58 Their positions tend
to be grounded in two arguments, one of which is dogmatic and the other
fallacious. First, they claim that unfree labor cannot, by definition, be
considered part of capitalism. This has been answered by C. L. R. James
who showed that the error is that of trying to judge a seventeenth- and
eighteenth-century labor system by the standards of the mid-nineteenth
century, the era of mature competitive capitalism as described by Marx.
Even more effective has been the demonstration by Immanuel Waller-
stein that capitalism uses a range of alternative labor systems under
alternative production conditions, and forced labor is one of these
alternative systems. 59 Second, the Marxist critics claim that processes that
occurred outside of Europe and involved then the import of commodities
and capital into Europe, must be denominated "exchange" rather than
"production," and so cannot be considered crucial for industrial
development or capitalism. This thesis is simply false: production on a
slave plantation is just as much production as is production in a
Birmingham needle factory.
Scholars such as Bailey, Beckles, Darity, Mintz, Sheridan, Solow,
Robinson, and Rodney, and (on a world-scale canvas) Amin, Waller-
stein, and Frank, have, in recent years, given strong backing to the critical
theory I have outlined here. 60 Conventional historians sometimes label it
"the Williams thesis." My point is that this "thesis" is something much
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
larger: it is the current state of the body of theory that pays adequate
attention to the role played by colonialism in the Industrial Revolution.
One other point of contention concerns the significance of demand.
All parties, concede that the decisions to increase productive capacity,
decisions which, in aggregate, led to the Industrial Revolution, were made
on the basis of judgments that additional commodities, if produced, could
be sold. The conventional historians generally treat the increase in
demand as a somehow natural product of the modernization of Europe. 61
The critical historians insist, rather, that colonialism was itself required in
order to increase the level of demand such that industrialists would make
efforts to increase capacity, efforts which, when the revolution got truly
underway, involved the use of powerful new productive technology. The
critical historians have indeed shown that an immense amount of demand
was generated by the slave trade, by the plantations (demand for food,
clothing, machinery, ships, and so on), and by the overall expansion of
the trading sphere in which European commodities moved in the
eighteenth century and thereafter. I would generalize the case as follows:
there would not have been an Industrial Revolution had it not been for
the immense demand that Europeans were able to generate in the
colonies, and it was this fact that, more than anything else, pushed the
Industrial Revolution forward.
Capitalism arose as a world-scale process: as a world system.
Capitalism became centrated in Europe because colonialism gave
Europeans the power both to develop their own society and to prevent
development from occurring elsewhere. It is this dynamic of development
and underdevelopment which mainly explains the modern world.
In this chapter and the two preceding ones I have tried to show, with
empirical evidence, that there was no "European miracle." Africa, Asia,
and Europe shared equally in the rise of capitalism prior to 1492. After
that date, Europe took the lead. This happened, as I have tried to
demonstrate in this chapter, because of Europe's location near America
and because of the immense wealth obtained by Europeans in America
and later in Asia and Africa — not because Europeans were brighter or
bolder or better than non-Europeans, or more modern, more advanced,
more progressive, more rational. These are myths of Eurocentric
diffusionism and are best forgotten.
NOTES
1. Europeans did not "discover" America: the hemisphere was settled many
millennia earlier by people who migrated in from Siberia and the Arctic. So I prefer
not to conceptualize the European arrival as a "discovery." Likewise, the idea that the
AFTER 1492
Western Hemisphere is a "New World" is false since it was hardly new to those who
lived there and greeted Columbus on his arrival in 1492. It is, however, very difficult
to avoid using the phrase "New World" in certain contexts, and I will occasionally
have to do so.
2. See K. N. Chaudhuri, Trade and Civilization in the Indian Ocean (1985);
Simkin, The TraditionalTrade of Asia (1968); Sherif, Slaves, Spices and Ivory in Zanzibar
(1987). It is highly likely that West Africans sailed across to the Americas before
1492. (See DeVisse and Labib, "Africa in Intercontinental Relations," 1984.)
However, because there seem not to have been major mercantile-maritime port cities
in West Africa — unlike East Africa — it is not likely that transatlantic voyages before
1492 had significant impact on Africa or on America. This is probable for several
reasons. First, in the absence of such major port cities and large-volume long-distance
sea commerce, it is likely that ships along the coast were rather small. They would
easily have been capable of a westward voyage to America, given the strong and steady
trade winds blowing westward, but a return voyage would have to have been made far
to the north or the south, in the zone of the westerlies — roughly as far north as the
latitude of southern Europe or as far south as the latitude of Namibia. Therefore the
round trip would have been a very formidable undertaking. On the other hand, we
may indeed learn from future scholarship that West African sailors, Moroccan sailors,
and West European sailors all were fishing and whaling quite regularly off the coast of
America (perhaps on the Grand Banks) before 1492; if strong evidence for this
emerges, then we would consider it likely that West Africans were familiar with the
round-trip voyage and with some parts of the American coast. But we do not have
such evidence at present, and we have to consider it more likely that any West
African ships that reached America were blown off course, in which case a return
voyage would have been very difficult. It would have to have been made without prior
knowledge of the long, circuitous route (unless American sailors knew the route and
gave navigational information to the African sailors — but we do not have convincing
evidence at present that Americans crossed the Atlantic before 1492). Secondly, the
portion of the American coast that is closest to Africa, roughly the Brazilian coast
south of the mouth of the Amazon, seems not to have had major population
concentrations and abundant gold and silver artifacts inviting trade or plunder.
(Granted, if West Africans reached the West Indies, they would have found such
artifacts in abundance, as did Columbus.) And thirdly, the complex of historical
conditions that would turn a single voyage into the beginning of a massive conquest
seem unlikely to have been present in coastal West Africa. Large-scale trade, a class
of merchant-capitalists, banking and other institutions of capitalism, and the like,
were found in interior West African urban centers, but not, it seems, in the urban
centers along the coast: these were not important as mercantile-maritime centers. For
the interior cities, major long-distance trade went northward and eastward overland,
and it is unlikely that attempts would have been made to develop large-scale oceanic
travel from a coastal harbor.
Some scholars maintain the truth of two propositions about West African
transatlantic voyaging that I cannot accept. The first of these asserts that Africans
exerted an important influence on American cultures before 1492. The second asserts
that West Africans crossed the Atlantic in much the same way as did Columbus, but
they had different values than the Europeans, and did not choose to murder, plunder,
enslave, and enrich themselves at the expense of Americans as did the Europeans; and
therefore they did not attempt conquest. Most of the evidence offered in support of
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
important precolumbian diffusion from Africa to America is taken from the old
arguments of European scholars of the "extreme diffusionism" school we discussed in
Chapter 1 . The extreme diffusionists claimed that ancient Egyptians or Phoenicians
crossed the Atlantic, and, in essence, brought civilization to the Americans. Some
modern scholars modify this mainly by insisting that because Egypt was a clearly
African civilization — this I am certain is true — it was an African people, not a
putatively European people, who brought civilization to the Americas. A second
source of evidence is the apparently African facial features of the great Olmec head
sculptures of southern Mexico. But some precolumbian Americans must have had
these features, too: they are not rare among modern Latin American Indians. But the
most serious objection to this theory is the following: The Olmec civilization is the
oldest known civilization in the Americas. If Olmec civilization came from Africa,
and was not developed indigenously by people of America, then we would have to say
that Americans simply did not have the ability to civilize themselves; civilization had
to be something brought in from elsewhere, by diffusion. This is viewed as a deep
insult by Latin Americans, who maintain, I am sure correctly, that Western
Hemisphere peoples developed civilization on their own. Perhaps they acquired a few
domesticates from sailors arriving from across the Atlantic or the Pacific. But the real
cultural development was a matter of independent invention, not diffusion. Again we
notice that the form of argument comes from classical diffusionism: some human
communities are inventive and others merely imitative. Based only on the thin and
questionable evidence that has been presented thus far that Africans brought major
cultural advances to America, this thesis is not persuasive.
Somewhat more troublesome to me is the argument that when Africans crossed
the Atlantic before or at the same time as Columbus did, they did not have the savage
values of the Europeans, and so did not try to conquer, loot, and enslave. To accept
this, one would have to believe that there is something absolutely fundamental in
European culture, something very old, and very deeply embedded, that makes
Europeans different from other humans. This admits a good part of the Eurocentric
claim that Europeans are unique among humans; it merely inverts the argument and
claims that their uniqueness lies not in progressiveness but in aggressiveness,
predatoriness, and cupidity. I am much more comfortable with an argument that
begins with the idea of a common basal human mentality ("psychic unity"). It then
explains the bloodthirstiness of the European conquistadors as an effect of the kind of
civilization they represented: its development of an oppressive class structure in
feudalism, and its further development of protocapitalism, a system in which wealth
is obtained at all cost and in any way possible. Bloodthirsty protocapitalist
communities, ready and anxious to conquer, loot, and enslave wherever this brought
a profit, were found in many parts of the Eastern Hemisphere, in all three continents.
My argument in this book is that the key factor favoring European moves of conquest
in the Americas, and not favoring West African moves of this sort, was the existence
of major mercantile-maritime centers in coastal Europe, protocapitalist centers of the
sort found in the interior of Africa but with the added features associated with
long-distance oceanic trade. Sofala and Kilwa in East Africa had these features but
Sofala and Kilwa were — as we note in this chapter — very much farther from the
American looting grounds than were the Iberian ports and the Canary outports. (I
have not cited specific scholars who hold these views that I criticize because a full and
fair review of their theories is not possible in the space of a single long footnote.
Obviously, I do not agree with the theory of Ivan Van Sertima, as presented in his
important work They Came Before Columbus [1976], concerning the precolumbian
AFTER 1492
diffusion of major civilizing traits from Africa to America, although he is very
probably correct in his view that Africans did come to America before Columbus did.)
3. Filesi, China and Africa in the Middle Ages (1972); Ma Huan, The Overall
Survey of the Ocean's Shores (1970); Panikkar, Asia and Western Influence (1959).
4. I have not learned of documented evidence that North Africans or West
Africans regularly sailed up and down the coast past Cape Bojador. (See DeVisse and
Labib, "Africa in Intercontinental Relations," 1984.) Apparently medieval sailing
techniques — European and non-European — had difficulty with the passage prior to
the time when Portuguese voyages began in the fifteenth century. However, there was
no question of "discovery." The sea route was known in antiquity. Important land
routes paralleled the entire length of the coast, from Fez south to Takrur (near modern
Dakar) and beyond (see Niane, "Mali and the Second Mandingo Expansion," 1984,
and Levitzion, "The Early States of the Western Sudan to 1500," 1971), and there
were medieval-era settlements in the Canaries and along the coast itself. Basically, it
was much cheaper to travel overland, and probably faster. What the Portuguese
"discovered" was a method of outflanking the competing merchant interests of North
and West Africa, by applying sailing technology known to Europeans and East
Africans but not known (or at any rate used, or at any rate known to have been used)
by West Africans in that period. It should be noted also that the Portuguese
navigational strategy in passing Bojador was basically the same strategy used for
voyages to the Atlantic islands, and probably known to Moroccan sailors as well as
Europeans.
5. Blaut, "Diffusionism: A Uniformitarian Critique" (1987).
6. For general reviews, see Crosby, The Columbian Exchange (1972) and
McNeill, Plagues and Peoples (1976). See Borah and Cooke, "La Demografta Hist6rica
de America Latina: Necesidades y Perspectivas" (1972); Whitmore, "A Simulation of
Sixteenth-Century Population Collapse in the Basin of Mexico" (1991); Alchon,
Native Society and Disease in Colonial Ecuador (1991); Lovell, " 'Heavy Shadows and
Black Night': Disease and Depopulation in Colonical America" (1992).
7. See Denevan, The Native Population of the Americas in 1492 (1976), for a
review of the disputes concerning the American population at the time of the
conquest.
8. Crosby, The Columbian Exchange (1972); Alchon, Native Society and Disease
in Colonial Ecuador (1991).
9. For a discussion of the various calculations, see Denevan, The Native
Population of the Americas in 1492 (1976); Denevan, "The Pristine Myth: The
Landscape of the Americas in 1492" (1992); Lovell, " 'Heavy Shadows and Black
Night' " (1992); and Whitmore, "A Simulation of Sixteenth-Century Population
Collapse in the Basin of Mexico" (1991).
10. The assumption here is that population continued to grow so long as food
resources for hunting, gathering, fishing, and shellfishing were abundant. At a certain
purely hypothetical time, it is likely that people who had certainly already
experimented with crop cultivation, found that a better supply of food (and fiber, etc.)
would be obtained through agriculture, and so began the transformation. Note that
this argument is in no way Malthusian.
11. See Fiedel, Prehistory of the Americas (1987).
12. See Crosby, The Columbian Exchange (1972), Lovell, " ' Heavy Shadows and
Black Night,' " and Alchon, Native Society and Disease in Colonial Ecuador (1991).
13. Miskimin, The Economy of Early Renaissance Europe, 1300-1460 (1969).
210 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
14. Abel, Agricultural Fluctuations in Europe from the Thirteenth to the Twentieth
Centuries (1980).
15. de Vries, European Urbanization, 1500-1800 (1984).
16. Hodgett, A Social and Economic History of Medieval Europe (1972) ("[The]
200 years after c.1320 may be said to be a period of down-turn in the [European]
economy as a whole," p. 212); Lopez and Miskimin, "The Economic Depression of the
Renaissance," (1961-1962); C. T. Smith, An Historical Geography of Western Europe
Before 1800 (1969).
17. Lopez, "Hard Times and Investment in Culture" (1953); Thorndyke,
"Renaissance or Prenaissance?" (1943).
18. Braudel, "Prices in Europe from 1450 to 1750" (1967); de Vries, European
Urbanization (1984). On the rapid impact of these changes on Asia, see, for example,
Atwell, "International Bullion Flows and the Chinese Economy circa 1530-1650"
(1982); Aziza Hasan, "The Silver Currency Output of the Mughal Empire and Prices
in India during the 16th and 17th centuries" (1969).
19. Cespedes, Latin America: The Early Years ((1974); McAlister, Spain and
Portugal in the New World, 1492-1700 (1984).
20. In classical political economy, and in some of modern Marxist economics,
the idea of "primitive accumulation" serves as a kind of catchall for ways of
accumulating capital that did not involve — in essence — capitalist enterprise. Pirate
treasures and the like were "primitive accumulation," and, in general, the kind of
wealth brought from the American colonies in the sixteenth century was considered
primitive accumulation. (According to Marx, "The treasures captured outside Europe
by undisguised looting, enslavement and murder flowed back to the mother-country
and were turned into capital there": Marx, Capital, 1976, vol. 1, p. 918). But "primitive
accumulation" cannot really be defined with any precision. I will argue here that the
wealth accumulated in the Americas was primitive only in the sense that it was part
of a preindustrial-capitalist economy. In other respects, notably in the involvement of
labor and value produced by labor, it was regular accumulation. The distinction is very
fundamental, as we will see, because, if what transpired in the colonies was not "real"
or "ordinary" accumulation, scholars can claim that the colonial economy was
backward and "feudal," rather than a primitive sort of capitalism.
21. E. J. Hamilton, American Treasure and the Price Revolution in Spain,
1501-1650 (1934); Brading and Cross, "Colonial Silver Mining: Mexico and Peru"
(1972); H. and P. Chaunu, Seville et I'Atlantique (1504-1650), vol. 6, pt. 1 (1956);
Cross, "American Bullion Production and Export 1550-1750" (1983).
22. See note 19 above.
23. Vicens Vives, An Economic History of Spain (1969).
24. Vilar, A History of Gold andMoney, 1450-1920 (1976).
25. There remained, nonetheless, a very large trade carried on by non-European
merchants in the China Seas and the Indian Ocean.
26. E. ]. Hamilton, "American Treasure and the Rise of Capitalism" (1929), and
American Treasure and the Price Revolution in Spain (1934). Also see the important
book by Walter Prescott Webb, The Great Frontier (1951), which builds in part on
Hamilton's theory to argue for the great importance of the Americas in the rise of
Europe during this period and later.
27. Galloway, The Sugar Cane Industry: An Historical Geography from its Origins
to 1914 (1989); Deerr, The History of Sugar (1949-1950).
28. See, for example, Galloway, The Sugar Cane Industry (1989); Deerr, The
History of Sugar (1949-1950); Watson, Agricultural Innovation in the Early Islamic
World: The Diffusion of Crops and Farming Techniques, 700-1 100 (1983); N. S. Gupta,
AFTER 1492
Industrial Structure of India During the Medieval Period (1970); Niane, ed., UNESCO
General History of Africa, Vol. 4. (1984); Bray, Science and Civilization in China, Vol.
6, Part 2, Agriculture (1984).
29. Deerr, The History of Sugar (1949-1950).
30. Simonsen, Historia Econdmica do Brasil, 1500-1820 (1944); Furtado, The
Economic Growth of Brazil (1963); Minchinton, The Growth of English Overseas Trade
(1969). Also see the more general, but extremely important, works of I. Wallerstein,
A. G. Frank, and S. Amin, particularly Wallerstein's The Modern World System, 3 vols.
(1974-1988), Frank's Capitalism and underdevelopment in Latin America (1968) and his
World Accumulation, 1492-1789 (1978), and Amin's Accumulation on a World Scale
(1974) as well as his Unequal Development (1976).
31. Edel, "The Brazilian Sugar Cycle of the 17th Century and the Rise of West
Indian Competition'^ 1969).
32. Furtado, Economic Growth of Brazil (1963).
33. See K. N. Chaudhuri, Trade and civilization in the Indian Ocean (1985); Satish
Chandra, The Indian Ocean: Explorations in History, Commerce and Politics (1987);
Magalhaes-Godinho, L'Economie de L'Empire Portugais aux XV et XVI Siecles (1969).
34. de Vries, European Urbanization (1984).
35. William Denevan, "Introduction," in Denevan, ed., The Native Population
of the Americas in 1492 (1976), and "The Pristine Myth: The Landscape of the
Americas in 1492" (1992; Lovell, " 'Heavy Shadows and Black Night' " (1992).
36. See Borah and Cook, "La demograffa hist<5rica de America Latina:
necesidades y perspectivas" (1972); Whitmore, "A Simulation of Sixteenth-Century
Population Collapse in the Basin of Mexico" (1991).
37. Semo, Historia del Capitalismo en Mexico: Los Origenes, 1521-1763 (1982).
38. Radell, "The Indian Slave Trade and Population of Nicaragua During the
Sixteenth Century" (1976).
39. Bakewell, "Mining in Colonial Spanish America" (1984).
40. Semo, Historia del Capitalismo (1982).
41. For various calculations, see Curtin, The Atlantic Slave Trade (1969);
Furtado, Economic Growth of Brazil (1963); Deerr, History of Sugar (1949-1950);
Florescano, "The Formation and Economic Structure of the Hacienda in New Spain";
Inikori, The African Slave Trade from the Fifteenth to the Nineteenth Century (1979), esp.
pp. 57 and 248; McAlister, Spain and Portugal in the New World (1984).
42. McAlister, Spain and Portugal in the New World (1984).
43. In the present discussion I am giving far too little attention to Africa and
particularly to the effects of the slave trade in Africa. See Chapter 2.
44. Fisher, "The Price Revolution: A Monetary Interpretation" (1989).
45. Dunn, Sugar and Slaves: The Rise of the Planter Class in the English West Indies,
1624-1713 (1972), pp., 10-11.
46. Tawney, Religion and the Rise of Capitalism (1952 edition).
47. Hannemann, The Diffusion of the Reformation in Southwestern Germany,
1518-1534 (1915).
48. There is debate as to why the center shifted from Iberia to the lower
Rhine-southern England region. Perhaps the same forces which had made this
northern region a mercantile-maritime center in the Middle Ages permitted it to gain
control of the overseas enterprise: namely, large population, abundant nearby fertile
land and forest resources, access to many markets (the Rhine, the Baltic, etc.).
Vis-a-vis Italy, it held most of these same advantages plus that of location on the
Atlantic and possession of the requirements for rapid growth of oceanic shipping and
fishing fleets.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
49. See Deerr, The History of Sugar (1949-1950); Curtin, The Atlantic Slave
Trade (1969); and Inikori, The African Slave Trade from the Fifteenth to the Nineteenth
Century (1979). The question whether slave labor is or is not proletarian — a serious
issue in discussions of the slave plantation system (see Mintz, Sweetness and Power:
The Place of Sugar in Modern History, 1985) — will be taken up later in this chapter. In
any event there is no disagreement about the contribution of slave (and other forced)
labor to capital accumulation, hence to surplus value generation, using "surplus value"
in a sense appropriate to modes of production different from industrial capitalism.
50. However, a good share of the old landowning elite joined in the new
enterprise. It is not correct to assume that the new protocapitalist elite was in simple
opposition to the old elite. There is much confusion on this matter, some of it
occasioned by literal acceptance of Marx's idea that merchants are somehow not the
class that evolves into the early capitalist, entrepreneurial, accumulating class. On the
role of medieval merchants in protocapitalism, see Thrupp, The Merchant Class of
Medieval London (1300-1500) (1948); Carus-Wilson, Medieval Merchant Venturers
(1967).
51. See R. W. Bailey, "Africa, the Slave Trade, and the Rise of Industrial
Capitalism in Europe and the United States: A Historiographic Review" (1986); W.
Darity, Jr., "British Industry and the West Indies Plantations" (1990).
52. There were, of course, exceptions. Brooks Adams, in his 1895 work The Law
of Civilization and Decay, argued (pp. 259-260) that the British victory at Plassey in
1757, which immediately gave Britain access to cheap Indian cotton (and other
Indian "plunder") set into motion the explosive industrialization of Britain's cotton
textile industry, leading directly and immediately to the major inventions of that
industry: the spinning jenny in 1764, the mule in 1776, and Watt's steam engine in
1768.
53. See Palme Dutt, The Problem of India (1943); Alavi et al., Capitalism and
Colonial Production (1982).
54. C. L. R. James, The Black Jacobins: Toussaint L'Ouverture and the San
Domingo Revolution (1938) and A History of Negro Revolt (1938); Eric Williams,
Capitalism and Slavery (1944). Also see the later work by James, "The Atlantic Slave
Trade and Slavery: Some Interpretations of their Significance in the Development of
the United States and the Western World" (1970); and the later work by Williams,
British Historians and the West Indies (1966). Important recent contributions include:
R. W. Bailey, "The Slave(ry) Trade and the Development of Capitalism in the
United States: The Textile Industry of New England" (1990); W. Darity, "British
Industry and the West Indian Plantations" (1990); J. Inikori, "Slavery and the
Revolution in Cotton Textile Production in England " (1989). Also see note 60
below.
55. The Black Jacobins (1938), pp. 47-48.
56. I have argued elsewhere (Blaut, The National Question, 1987b, chap. 7) that
the level of oppression and exploitation associated with slave labor as it was used in
the plantations could not have been applied to members of the European cultural
community itself. (This was indeed tried, but quickly abandoned in favor of slave
labor.) Generally, cultural rules and practices limit the level of exploitation of
producers within a society — a matter of maintaining social peace in a society — but no
such rules apply to external or foreign workers.
57. See the excellent review by C. Robinson, "Capitalism, Slavery and
Bourgeois Historiography" (1987). Also excellent is Bailey, "The Slave(ry) Trade and
the Development of Capitalism in the United States" (1990).
AFTER 1492
58. See Brenner's "The Origins of Capitalist Development: A Critique of
Neo-Smithian Marxism" (1977); E. Laclau, Politics and Ideology in Marxist Theory
(1977).
59. Wallerstein, The Modern World System (1974-1988).
60. See Bailey, "The Slave(ry) Trade and the Development of Capitalism in the
United States" (1990), Darity, "British Industry and the West Indian Plantations"
(1990), Mintz, Sweetness and Power: The Place of Sugar in Modern History (1985), and
Robinson, "Capitalism, Slavery and Bourgeois Historiography" (1987); also, see
Beckles, "The Williams Effect': Eric Williams' Capitalism and Slavery and the Growth
of West Indian Political Economy" (1987); Sheridan, Sugar and Slavery (1973), and
his "Eric Williams and Capitalism and Slavery: A Biographical and Historiographical
Essay" (1987); Solow, "Capitalism and Slavery in the Exceedingly Long Run" (1987);
Inikori, "Slavery and the Development of Industrial Capitalism" (1989); Rodney,
How Europe Underdevebped Africa (1972).
61. Some Marxists treat it this way, too: "[What] distinguished the English
industrial development of the early modern period was its continuous character, its
ability to sustain itself and to provide its own self-perpetuating dynamic. Here . . . the
key was to be found in the capitalist structure of [English] agriculture" (Brenner,
"Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe,"
1985, p. 53).
CHAPTER 5
Conclusion
This book has two basic themes or arguments.
First, in Chapter 1, I try to explain what
Eurocentric diffusionism is as a body of ideas,
and to show how this theory — or supertheory,
or world model — came to dominate European scholarly thought a century
ago and why it still does so to a considerable extent today. And second, in
Chapters 2 through 4, 1 carefully examine the single most important part
of diffusionism, the theory of Europe's historical superiority or priority,
the theory of "the European miracle," and I try to refute it.
Diffusionism needs to be analyzed much more thoroughly than I
have been able to do in this book. Many diffusionist theories and
programs that, today, exert an important and unfortunate influence on
many fields of thought and action have not been discussed here. In other
writings I have explored the influence of diffusionism on theory and
practice concerning the national question, or nationalism, 1 and on theory
and practice concerning the development of peasant agriculture. 2 Other
writers have, of course, examined many aspects of diffusionism and
problems caused by diffusionism. 3 But, overall, the critique of diffusionism
has barely begun.
The critique will have to range across many fields of scholarship and
practice. Here — just to make this point clear — are four examples.
1 . Philosophical dualism, the body of epistemological and ontologi-
cal doctrine developed in European thought from Descartes to Kant and
the neo-Kantians, appears to be, in part, a projection of the dualism of
Inside and Outside. Reason is Inside. Mere matter, mere sensuousness, is
Outside — the non-European world and the irrational mentation of its
inhabitants.
2. The so-called Big Bang Theory, the theory that everything began
at one space-time point and this point was here, seems to be diffusionism
214
CONCLUSION
on the largest canvas of all. Big Bang cosmogony appears to be fortified
less by empirical evidence than by a hunch that the whole idea is
"reasonable" — the essential judgment (as we noticed in Chapter 1) by
which culture projects its prejudices into science. 4
3. The theory that AIDS diffused out of Africa is very reminiscent of
a historical chain of theories, each explaining some plague as a
counterdiffusion from non-Europe to Europe. (We discussed aspects of
this question in Chapters 1 and 2.) A recent book entitled AIDS, Africa
and Racism gives important evidence that the AIDS-out-of-Africa
doctrine may, indeed, be simply a new incarnation of this diffusionist
view of human disease. 5 If this is the case, the matter of causality of
HIV-retroviruS'Caused disease may have to be rethought. The forms found
outside of Africa may be more relevant for explanation and cure than
those inside Africa.
4- Many theories about economic history since the beginning of the
Industrial Revolution, and about economic development today, seem to
be steeped in diffusionism. The Industrial Revolution has not diffused
outward from Europe to non-Europe. Not only does it have origins in
non-Europe as well as Europe (we discussed this matter in Chapter 4), but
the notion that industrialization has been spreading to the non-European
world is largely a false (conformal) idea. The diffusion of maquiladora'Style
assembly-plant activities in the Third World is not genuine industrializa-
tion but rather a kind of world-scale putting-out system: Outside provides
cheap labor, Inside provides most of the raw materials and most of the
consumption, and garners nearly all of the profit as well as the permanent
infrastructure. The industrialization of Japan began long ago and was not
an effect of diffusion. 6 The industrialization of Korea and one or two East
Asian ministates in recent decades has not been imitated elsewhere.? The
diffusion of industrialization, therefore, is not a simple and natural
diffusion process, but a political agenda. And an agenda for scholarly
inquiry.
This book, therefore, has no real conclusion. The book itself is an
introduction: an introduction to the study, to the diagnosis and
treatment, of a serious malady of the mind.
NOTES
1. Blaut, The National Question (1987b); Blaut and Figueroa, Aspectos de la
cuestion nacional en Puerto Rico (1988).
2. Blaut, "Two Views of Diffusion" (1977) and "Diffusionism: A Uniformicarian
Critique" (1987a).
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
3. Reference has been made to this work in Chapters 2, 3, and 4-
4. See Talkington, "But the Editor Looks at the Universe from a Different
Frame of Reference" (1986); Frankel, "Marxism and Physics: A New Look" (1991).
5. Chirimuuta and Chirimuuta, AIDS, Africa and Racism (1989). A naively
diffusionist view of AIDS is given in Shannon and Pyle, "The Origin and Diffusion
of AIDS" (1989); see the critique of this view in Watts, Okello, and Watts, "Medical
Geography and AIDS" (1990).
6. Japan became industrialized precisely because of a lack of diffusion. It was the
only major non-European country that managed to avoid European domination, and
this resulted from its inaccessibility. It was, among major societies, the farthest and
most inaccessible from the standpoint of Europeans, and by the time European power
had subdued China, in the nineteenth century, Japan had been able to begin its
military modernization; hence the victory over Russia, the beginnings of colonial
expansion, and the onset of an industrial revolution around 1900.
7. At the other end of the scale, giant countries like India and Brazil have a great
deal of industry but in proportion to their size — and on a per capita measurement —
they are no more industrialized than are smaller Third world countries. See Amin,
Delinking: Toward a Poly centric World (1990).
Bibliography
Abel, W. (1980). Agricultural fluctuations in Europe from the thirteenth to the twentieth
centuries. London: Methuen.
Abu-Lughod, J. (1987-1988). The shape of the world system in the thirteenth
century. Studies in Comparative International Development 22(4):3-25.
. (1989). Before European hegemony: The world system a.d. 1250-1350. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Adams, B. (1895). The law of civilization and decay. New York: Macmillan.
Adams, W., Van Gerven, D., and Levy, R. (1978). The retreat from migrationism.
Annual Review of Anthropology 7:483-532.
Ahn, P. (1970). West African soib. London: Oxford University Press.
Ajayi, J., and Crowder, M., eds. (1972). History of West Africa. Vol. 1. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Alavi, H. (1982). India: The transition to colonial capitalism. In H. Alavi, et al., eds.,
Capitalism and colonial production. London: Croom Helm.
, Burns, P., Knight, G., Mayer, P., and McEachern, D., eds. (1982). Capitalism
and colonial production. London: Croom Helm.
Alchon, S. (1991). Native society and disease in colonial Ecuador. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Amin, S. (1973). Neo-cohnialism in West Africa. New York: Monthly Review Press.
. (1974). Accumulation on a world scale. New York: Monthly Review Press.
. (1976). Unequal development. New York: Monthly Review Press.
. (1985). Modes of production: History and unequal development. Science and
Society 49:194-207.
. (1988). Eurocentrism. New York: Monthly Review Press.
. (1990). Colonialism and the rise of capitalism: A comment. Science and
Society 54:67-72.
. (1990). Delinking: Toward a polycentric world. London: Zed Books.
. (1992). On Jim Blaut's "Fourteen ninety-two." Political Geography 11:394-
396.
Anderson, J. (1882). New manual of general history. New York: Clark and Maynard.
Anderson, P. (1974). Passages from antiquity to feudalism. London: New Left Books.
. (1974). Lineages of the absolute state. London: New Left Books.
Appadorai, A. (1936). Economic conditions in southern India (1000-1500 a.d.). 2 vols.
Madras: University of Madras Press.
Asad, T, ed. (1975). Anthropology and the colonial encounter. London: Ithaca Press.
Aston, T, andPhilpin, C, eds. (1985). The Brenner debate: Agrarian class structure and
217
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
economic development in pre-irtdustrial Europe. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
Atwell, W. (1982). International bullion flows and the Chinese economy circa
1530-1650. Past and Present 95:68-91.
Baechler, J. (1988). The origins of modernity: Caste and feudality (India, Europe and
Japan). In J. Baechler, J. A. Hall, and M. Mann, eds. Europe and the rise of
capitalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
, Hall, J. A., and Mann, M., eds. (1988). Europe and the rise of capitalism.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Bailey, A., and Llobera, J., eds. (1981). The Asiatic mode of production: Science and
politics. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Bailey, R. (1986). Africa, the slave trade, and the rise of industrial capitalism in
Europe and the United States: A historiographic review. American History: A
Bibliographic Review 2:1-91.
. (1990). The slave(ry) trade and the development of capitalism in the
United States: The textile industry of New England. Social Science History
14(3):373-414.
Bakewell, Peter. (1984). Mining in colonial Spanish America. In L. Bethell, ed., The
Cambridge history of Latin America: Colonial Latin America, Vol. 2. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Baran, P., and Sweezy, P. (1966). Monopoly capital. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Barnes, H. E., ed. (1925). Ploetz' manual of universal history. New York: Blue Ribbon
Books.
Beckles, H. (1987). "The Williams effect": Eric Williams' Capitalism and slavery and
the growth of West Indian political economy. In B. Solow, and S. Engerman,
eds., British capitalism and Caribbean slavery: The legacy of Eric Williams.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Berkner, L. (1975). The use and misuse of census data for the historical analysis of
family structures. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 5:721-738.
. (1989). The stem family and the developmental cycle of the peasant
household, American Historical Review 77:398-428.
Bernal, M. (1987). Black Athena: The Afroasiatic roots of classical civilization, Vol. J.,
The fabrication of ancient Greece. London: Free Association Books.
. ( 1991 ). Black Athena: The Afroasiatic roots of classical civilization, Vol. 2, The
archeological and documentary evidence. London: Free Association Books.
Bhatia, B. (1967). Famines in India. Bombay: Asia Publishing House.
Bji/rklund, O., H$mhoe, H, R^hr, A., and Lie, B. (1970). Historical atlas of the world.
New York: Barnes and Noble.
Black, C. (1966). The dynamics of modernization: A study in comparative history. New
York: Harper and Row.
Blaikie, P. (1978). The theory of the spatial diffusion of innovations: a spacious
cul-de-sac. Progress in Human Geography 2:268-295.
Blaut, J. (1962). The nature and effects of shifting agriculture. In Symposium on the
impact of man on humid-tropics vegetation. Canberra: UNESCO and Australian
Government Printer.
. (1963). The ecology of tropical farming systems. Revista Geogrdfica
28:47-67.
. (1970). Geographic models of imperialism. Antipode 2(1):65— 85.
. (1973). The theory of development. Antipode 5(2):22-26.
. (1976). Where was capitalism born? Antipode 8(2):1-1 1.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
. (1977). Two views of diffusion. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 67:343-349.
. (1979). Some principles of ethnogeography. In S. Gale, and G. Olsson, eds.,
Philosophy in geography. Dordrecht: Reidel.
. (1982). Nationalism as an autonomous force. Science and Society 46:1-23.
. (1984). Modesty and the movement. In T. Saarinen, et al, eds., Environ-
mental perception and behavior: An inventory and prospect. Chicago: University
of Chicago Department of Geography, Research Paper No. 209.
. (1987a). Diffusionism: A uniformitarian critique. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 77:30—47.
. ( 1987b). The national question: Decolonizing the theory of nationalism. London:
Zed Books.
. (1989). Colonialism and the rise of capitalism. Science and Society
53:260-296.
. (1989). Review of J. Baechler.J. Hall, and M. Mann, eds., Europe and the rise
of capitalism. Progress in Human Geography 13(3):441— 448.
. (1991). Natural mapping. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers
16(n.s.):55-74.
. (1991). Review of P. Curtin, The plantation complex. Journal of Historical
Geography 17:472-474.
. (1992a). The theory of cultural racism. Antipode 24(4):289-299.
. (1992b). Fourteen ninety-two. Political Geography 1 1 (3):355— 385.
, and Figueroa, L. (1988). Aspectos de la cuestidn nacional en Puerto Rico. San
Juan: Editorial Claridad.
, Frank, A. G., Amin, S., Dodgshon, R., Palan, R., and Taylor. P. (1992).
Fourteen ninety-two: The debate on colonialism, Eurocentrism, and history.
Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press.
, and Rfos-Bustamante, A. (1984). Commentary on Nostrand's "Hispanos"
and their "Homeland." Annals of the Association of American Geographers
74:157-164.
Blum, J. (1978). Pseudoscience and mental ability. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Boas, F. (1938). The mind of primitive man. New York: Macmillan.
. (1948). Race, language and culture. New York: Macmillan.
Bois G. (1985). Against the neo-Malthusian orthodoxy. In Aston, T, and Philpin,
C, eds., The Brenner debate: Agrarian class structure and economic development
in pre-industrial Europe. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Borah, W., and Cook, S. E. (1972). La demograffa historica de America Latina:
necesidades y perspectivas. In J. Bezant et al., eds., La historia econdmica en
America Latina. Mexico, D.F.: Sep-Setentas.
Bowler, P. (1989). The invention of progress. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Brading, D. A., and Cross, H. C. (1972). Colonial silver mining: Mexico and Peru.
Hispanic- American Historical Review 52:545-79.
Brantlinger, P. (1988). Rule of darkness: British literature and imperialism, 1830-1914-
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Braudel, F. (1967). Prices in Europe from 1450 to 1750. In E. Rich, and C. Wilson,
eds. The Cambridge economic history of Europe, Vol. 4: The economy of expanding
Europe in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
. (1972). The Mediterranean. New York: Harper and Row.
220 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Bray, Francesca. (1984). Science and civilization in China, Vol. 6, part 2, Agriculture.
(Joseph Needham, principal author and editor.) Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Brenner, R. (1977). The origins of capitalist development: A critique of
neo-Smithian Marxism. New Left Review 104:25-93.
. (1985). Agrarian class structure and economic development in pre-
industrial Europe. In T. Aston and C. Philpin, eds., The Brenner debate:
Agrarian class structure and economic development in preAndustrial Europe.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. (Originally in Past and
Present No. 70, 1976).
. (1985). The Agrarian roots of European capitalism. In T. Aston, and C.
Philpin, eds., The Brenner debate: Agrarian class structure and economic
development in pre-industrial Europe. Cambridge, England: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press. (Originally in Past and Present, no. 97, 1982).
. (1986). The social basis of economic development. In J. Roemer, ed., "
Analytical Marxism. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Browett, J. (1980). Development, the diffusionist paradigm and geography. Progress in
Human Geography 4:56-79.
Brown, L. (1981). Innovation diffusion: A new perspective. London: Methuen.
Buckle, H. T. (1913). History of civilization in England. 4 vols., 2d ed., rev. New York:
Hearst's International Library.
Bury, J. B. (1932). The idea of progress. New York: Macmillan.
Cabral, A. (1979). Unity and struggle: Speeches and writings of Amilcar Cabral. New
York: Monthly Review Press.
Carter, G. (1968). Man and the land: A cultural geography. New York: Holt, Rinehart,
and Winston.
Cams-Wilson, E. M. (1967). Medieval merchant venturers. 2d ed. London: Methuen.
Cesaire, A. (1972). Discourse on colonialism. New York: Monthly Review Press.
C6spedes, G. (1974). Latin America: The early years. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Chambers, M., et al. (1987). The Western experience. 2 vols., 4th ed. New York: Alfred
A. Knopf.
Chan-Cheung, J. (1967). The smuggling trade between China and Southeast Asia
during the Ming Dynasty. In E Drake, ed., Symposium on historical,
archeological, and linguistic studies on southern China. Hong Kong: Hong Kong
University Press.
Chandra, B. (1981). Karl Marx, his theories of Asian societies, and colonial rule.
Review 5(l):13-94.
Chandra, S. (1964). Commerce and industry in the medieval period. In B. Ganguli,
ed., Readings in Indian economic history. Bombay.
, ed. (1987). The Indian Ocean: Explorations in history, commerce and politics.
New Delhi: Sage.
Chaudhuri, K. N. (1978). The trading world of Asia and the English East India Company,
1660-1760. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
. (1985). Trade and civilization in the Indian Ocean. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Chaudhuri, S. (1974). Textile trade and industry in Bengal Suba, 1650-1720. Indian
Historical Review 1:262-278.
Chaunu, H., and Chaunu, P. (1956). Seville et I'Atlantique (1504-1650). Part 1. Paris:
SEVPEN.
Chicherov, A. (1976). On the multiplicity of socio-economic structures in India in
BIBLIOGRAPHY
the 17th and 18th century. In G. Abramov, ed., New Indian studies by Soviet
scholars. Moscow: USSR Academy of Sciences.
Childe, V. G. (1951). Social evolution. New York: Henry Schuman.
Chirimuuta, R. C, and Chirimuuta, R. J. (1989). AIDS, Africa and Racism, 2d ed.
London: Free Association Books.
Chisholm, M. (1982). Modern world development. Totowa, N.J.: Barnes and Noble.
Choudhary, A. (1974). Early medieval village in north-eastern India (a.d. 600-1200).
Calcutta: Punthi Pustak.
Cipolla, C. (1965). Guns, sails, and empires: Technological innovation and the early phase
of European expansion, 1400-1700. New York: Pantheon.
Cockburn, A., and Hecht, S. (1989). The fate of the forest. London: Verso.
Cohen, I. (1981). Introduction to Weber, M., Genera! economic history. New
Brunswick, NJ: Transactions.
Cohen, M. (1977). The food crisis in prehistory. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Collier, W. F. (1868). Outlines of general history. London: T. Nelson and Sons.
Collins, K., and Roberts, D., eds. (1988), Capacity for work in the tropics. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Collyer, O. (1965). Birth rates in Latin America. Berkeley: Institute of International
Studies, University of California at Berkeley.
Conklin, H. (1969). Lexicographical treatment of folk taxonomies. In Tyler, ed.,
Cognitive anthropology. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Cooper, J. (1985). In search of agrarian capitalism. In T. Aston, and C. Philpin, eds.,
The Brenner debate: Agrarian class structure and economic development in
pre-industrial Europe. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Corbridge, S. (1986). Capitalist world development. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and
Littlefield.
Cordell, D., and Gregory, J. (1987). Introduction to D. Cordell and J. Gregory, eds.,
African population and capitalism: Historical perspectives. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Coursey, D. (1967). Yams. London: Longmans, Green.
Crone, P. (1989). Pre-industrial societies. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Croot, P., and Parker, D. (1985). Agrarian class structure and the development of
capitalism: France and England compared. In T. Aston, and C. Philpin, eds.,
The Brenner debate: Agrarian class structure and economic development in
pre-industrial Europe. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Crosby, A. W. (1972). The Columbian exchange: Biological and cultural consequences of
1492. Westport, CO: Greenwood Press.
Cross, H. (1983). South American bullion production and export 1550-1750. In J.
Richards, ed., Precious metals and the late medieval and early modern worlds.
Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press.
Curtin, P. (1969). The Atlantic slave trade. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
. (1975). Economic change in pre-colonial Africa: Senegambia in the era of the slave
trade. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
. (1990). The rise and fall of the plantation complex. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Dalai, F. (1988). The racism of Jung. Race and Class 29(3):l-22.
Darby, H. (1952). The Domesday geography of eastern England. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Darity, W, Jr. (1990). British industry and the West Indies plantations. Social Science
History 14( 1): 1 1 7-148.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Das Gupta, A. (1967). Malabar in Asian trade: 1740-1800. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press,
de Vries, J. (1984). European urbanization, 1500-1800. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Deerr, Noel. (1949-1950). The history of sugar. 2 vols. London: Chapman and Hall.
Denevan, W. (1966), The aboriginal cultural geography of the llanos de Mojos of Bolivia.
Iberoamericana, no. 48. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California
Press.
. (1976). Introduction to W. Denevan, ed., The native population of the
Americas in 1492, 1-12. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
. (1982). Hydraulic agriculture in the American tropics: Forms, measures, and
recent research. In K. Flannery, ed., Maya subsistence: Studies in memory of
Dennis E. Puleston. New York: Academic Press.
. (1992). The pristine myth: The landscape of the Americas in 1492. Annals
of die Association of American Geographers 82: 369-385.
, ed. (1976). The native population of die Americas in 1492. Madison: University
of Wisconsin Press.
DeVisse J., and Labib, S. (1984). Africa in intercontinental relations. In D. Niane,
ed., UNESCO general history of Africa, Vol. 4. Paris: UNESCO.
Dew, T. (1853). A digest of the laws, customs, manners, and institutions of the ancient and
modem nations. New York: Appleton.
Dewey, J. (1916). The logic of judgments of practice. In Essays in experimental logic.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
. (1929). The quest for certainty. New York: G. P. Putnam.
Di Meglio, R. (1970). Arab trade with Indonesia and the Malay Peninsula from the
8th to the 16th century. In D. S. Richards, ed., Islam and the trade of Asia.
Oxford: Cassirer.
Dirks, N. (1987). The hollow crown: Ethnohistory of an Indian kingdom. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Dobb, Maurice. (1947). Studies in the development of capitalism. New York:
International Publishers.
Doolittle, W. (1990). Canal irrigation in prehistoric Mexico: The sequence of technological
change. Austin: University of Texas Press.
DuBois, W. E. B. (1965). The world and Africa: An inquiry into the part which Africa has
played in world history. New York: International Publishers.
Dunn, R. S. (1972). Sugar and slaves: The rise of the planter class in the English West
Indies, 1624-1713. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Duruy, V, and Grosvenor, E. (1901). A general history of the world. New York: Crowell.
Dutt, R. P. (1943). The problem of India. New York: International Publishers.
Duyvendak, J. (1933). Ma Hwan re-examined. Verhandlungen der Koninklijke Akademie
van Wetenschappen te Amsterdam, afdeeling letterkunde, nieuwe reeks. Part
33 (3): 1-74.
Edel, M. (1969). The Brazilian sugar cycle of the 1 7th century and the rise of West
Indian competition. Caribbean Studies 9(1):24^45.
Edmonson, M. (1961). Neolithic diffusion rates. Current Anthropology 2(2):71— 86.
Eliot Smith, G. (1928). In the beginning: The origin of civilization. New York: Morrow.
. (1933). The diffusion of culture. London: Watts.
Elvin, M. (1973). The pattern of the Chinese past. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
. (1988). China as a counterfactual. In J. Baechler, J. A. Hall, and M. Mann,
eds., Europe and the rise of capitalism, 101-112. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Engels, F. (1970). The origin of the family, private property, and the state. In Marx and
Engels: Selected works, Vol. 3. Moscow: Progress.
. (1974). What have the working classes to do with Poland? In D. Fernbach,
ed., Karl Marx: Political writings, Vol. 3. New York: Vintage.
. (1975). Letter to K. Marx, June 6, 1853. In Marx and Engels: Selected
correspondence. Moscow: Progress.
Fei Hsiao-tung. (1953). China's gentry. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Redel, S. (1987). Prehistory of the Americas. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
Filesi, T. (1972). China and Africa in the Middle Ages. London: Frank Cass.
Finley, M. (1975). The use and abuse of history. New York: Viking Press.
Fisher, D. (1989). The price revolution: A monetary interpretation. Journal of
Economic History 49:883-902.
Fisher, G. (1885). Outlines of universal history. New York: Ivison, Blakeman, Taylor.
. (1896), A brief history of the nations and their progress in history. New York:
American Book Co.
Fleck, L. (1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Florescano, E. (1984). The formation and economic structure of the hacienda in New
Spain. In L. Bethell, ed., The Cambridge history of Latin America: Colonial Latin
America, Vol. 2. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Foster, G. (1962). Traditional cultures: And the impact of technological change. New York:
Harper and Row.
Frake, C. (1969). The ethnographic study of cognitive systems. In S. Tyler, ed.,
Cognitive anthropology. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Frank, A. G. (1968). Capitalism and underdevelopment in Latin America. New York:
Monthly Review Press.
. (1969). Sociology of development and underdevelopment of sociology. In
his Latin America: Underdevelopment or revolution. New York: Monthly Review
Press.
. (1978). World accumulation, 1492-1789. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Frankel, H. (1991). Marxism and physics: A new look. Science and Society 55:336-347.
Freedman, M. (1966). Chinese lineage and society. London: University of London Press.
Freeman, E. (1874). General sketch of history. New York: Holt.
Freire, P. (1972). Pedagogy of the oppressed. New York: Herder and Herder.
FRELIMO (Frente de Libertacao de Mozambique. (1971). Historia de Mogambique.
Porto, Portugal: Afrontamento.
Freund, J. (1969). The sociology of Max Weber. New York: Vintage.
Fu Chu-fu and Li Ching-neng. (1956). The sprouts of capitalistic factors within China's
feudal society. Program in East Asian Studies, Western Washington State
University, Occasional Paper no. 7.
Furtado, C. (1963). The economic growth of Brazil. Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press.
Fyfe, C, and McMaster, D., eds. (1981). African historical demography. Edinburgh,
Scotland: Centre of African Studies.
Galeano, E. (1972). The open veins of Latin America. New York: Monthly Review
Press.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Galloway, J. H. (1977). The Mediterranean sugar industry. Geographical Review
67:177-192.
. (1989). The sugar cane industry: An historical geography from its origins to 1914.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Garraty, J., and Gay, P., eds. (1981). The Columbia history of the world. New York:
Dorset Press.
Gernet, J. (1962). Daily life in China on the eve of the Mongol invasion, 1250-1276.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Giblin, J. (1990). Trypanosomiasis control in African history: An evaded issue?
]oumal of African History 31:59-80.
Gilfillan, S. (1920). The coldward course of progress. Political Science Quarterly
35:393-410.
Gill, D. and Levidow, L., eds. (1987). Anti-racist science teaching. London: Free
Association Books.
Gilman, A. (1874). First steps in general history. Cambridge, MA: Riverside Press.
Godelier, M. (1969). Sobre el modo de production asidtico. Barcelona, Spain: Ediciones
Martinez Roca.
Goitein, S. (1967). A Mediterranean society. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of
California Press.
Golson, J. (1977). No room at the top: Agricultural intensification in the New
Guinea Highlands. In J. Allen et al., eds., Sunda and Sahul: Prehistoric studies
in Southeast Asia, Melanesia and Australia. London: Academic Press.
Goodrich, S. G. (1843). Peter Parley's common school history. Philadelphia: E. H.
Butler.
Gopal, L. (1963). Quasi-manorial rights in ancient India. Journal of the Economic and
Social History of the Orient 6:296-308.
Gopal, S. (1972). Nobility and the mercantile community in India. Journal of Indian
History 50:793-802;
Gorman, C. (1977). A priori models and Thai prehistory: A reconsideration of the
beginnings of agriculture in Southeast Asia. In C. A. Reed, ed., Origins of
agriculture. The Hague: Mouton.
Gossett, T. ( 1963). Race: The history of an idea in America. Dallas: Southern Methodist
University Press.
Gould, P. (1969). Spatial diffusion. Commission on College Geography, Association of
American Geographers, Resource Paper no. 4, Washington, DC: Association
of American Geographers.
Graebner, F. (1911). Methode der ethnologic Heidelberg, Germany.
Gupta, N. S. (1970). Industrial structure of India during the medieval period. Delhi:
Chand.
Habib, I. (1963). The agrarian system of Mughal India. London: Asia Publishing House.
. (1964). Usury in medieval India. Comparative Studies in Society and History
6:392-419.
. (1965). The social distribution of landed property in pre-British India.
Enquiry 2(2,n.s.):21-75.
. (1969). Problems of Marxist historical analysis. Enquiry 3(2,n.s.):52-67.
Hagen, E. (1962). The theory of social change: How economic growth begins. Homewood,
IL: Dorsey Press.
. (1962). A framework for analyzing economic and political change. In
Brookings Institution, ed., Development of the emerging countries: Anagendafor
research, 1-39. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 225
Hagerstrand, T. (1967). Innovation diffusion as a spatial process. Translated by A. Pred.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hajnal, J. (1965). European marriage patterns in perspective. In D. Glass and D.
Eversley, eds., Population in history: Essays in historical demography. Chicago:
Aldine.
Hall, J. (1985). Powers and liberties: The causes and consequences of the rise of the West.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
. (1988). States and societies: The miracle in historical perspective. In J.
Baechler, J. A. Hall, and M. Mann, eds., Europe and the rise of capitalism.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Hallam, H. (1975). The medieval social picture. In E. Kamenka and R. Neale, eds.,
Feudalism, capitalism and beyond. London: Edward Arnold.
Haller, J. (1971). Outcasts from evolution: Scientific attitudes of racial inferiority,
1859-1900). Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Hamilton, E. J. (1929). American treasure and the rise of capitalism. Economica
9:338-357.
. (1934). American treasure and the price revolution in Spain, 1501-1650.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hamilton, G. S. (1985). Why no capitalism in China? Negative questions in
historical, comparative research. Journal of Developing Societies 1:187-211.
Handler, R. (1989). Review of Macfarlane, A., Marriage and love in England. American
Anthropologist 91:107 '8-1079.
Hannemann, M. (1975). The diffusion of the Reformation in Southwestern Germany,
1518-1534. Department of Geography, University of Chicago, Research
Paper no. 167.
Hansis, R. (1976). Ethnogeography and science: Viticulture in Argentina. Ph.D. diss.,
Pennsylvania State University.
Hardy, E (1936). Some aspects of tropical soils. Transactions of the Third International
Congress of Soil Science 2:150-163.
Harewood, J. (1966). Population growth in Grenada. Social and Economic Studies
15:61-84.
Harris, M. (1968). The rise of anthropological theory. New York: Crowell.
Harrison, P. (1969). The communists and Chinese peasant rebellions. New York:
Atheneum.
, and Turner, B. L., eds. (1978). Pre-Hispanic Maya agriculture. Albuquerque:
University of New Mexico Press.
Hasan, A. (1969). The silver currency output of the Mughal Empire and prices in
India during the 16th and 17th centuries. Indian Economic and Social History
Review 6:85-116.
Haskel, D. (1848). Chronology and universal history. New York: J. H. Colton.
Hassan, F. (1978). Demographic archeology. In M. B. Schaffer, ed., Advances in
archeological method and theory, Vol. 1. New York: Columbia University Press.
Hegel, G. (1956). The philosophy of history. New York: Dover Publications.
Hilton, R. (1980). Individualism and the English peasantry. New Left Review, no. 120,
pp. 109-111.
. (1985). Introduction. In T. Aston, and C. Philpin, eds., The Brenner debate:
Agrarian class structure and economic development in preAndusttial Europe.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
, ed. (1976). The transition from feudalism to capitalism. London: New Left
Books.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Ho Ping-ti. ( 1977). The indigenous origins of Chinese agriculture. In C. A. Reed, ed.,
Origins of agriculture. The Hague: Mouton.
Hodgett, A. J. (1972). A social and economic history of medieval Europe. London:
Methuen.
Hopkins, A. (1973). An economic history of West Africa. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Howard, A. (1975). Pre-colonial centers and regional systems in Africa. Pan- African
Journal 8(3):247-270.
Huddleston, L. (1967). Origins of the American Indians: European concepts, 1492-1 729.
Austin: University of Texas Press.
Hoyle, R. (1990). Tenure and the land market in early modern England: Or a late
contribution to the Brenner debate. Economic History Review 43:1-20.
Hudson, B. (1977). The new geography and the new imperialism: 1870-1918.
Antipode9(l):12-19.
Hulme, P. (1992). Colonial encounters: Europe and the Native Caribbean 1492-1797.
London: Routledge.
Huntington, E. (1924). Principles of human geography. 3d ed. New York: John Wiley.
Inikori, J. (1987). Slavery and the development of industrial capitalism. In B. Solow
and S. Engerman, eds. (1987). British capitalism and Caribbean slavery: The
legacy of Eric Williams. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
. (1989). Slavery and the revolution in cotton textile production in England.
Social Science History 13(4):343-379.
, ed. (1979). The African slave trade from the fifteenth to the nineteenth century.
Paris: UNESCO.
Irvine, F. (1934). A textbook of West African agriculture: Soils and crops. London: Oxford
University Press.
Irwin, G. (1982). Sub-Saharan Africa. In J. Garraty, and P. Gay, eds., Columbia history
of the world. New York: Columbia University Press.
Isichei, E. (1982). A history of Nigeria. London: Longmans.
Ivanov, V. (1985). Round-table: State and law in the ancient Orient. (Discussion.)
Social Sciences (USSR Academy of Sciences) 16(3):177-201.
Jackson, P., ed. (1987). Race and racism: Essays in social geography. London: Allen and
Unwin.
James, C. L. R. (1938a). The Blackjacobins: ToussaintL'Ouverture and the San Domingo
revolution. London: Seeker and Warburg.
. (1938b). A history of Negro revolt. London: Fact. Rev. ed. (1969), A history
of Pan-African revolt. Washington, DC: Drum and Spear Press.
. (1970). The Atlantic slave trade and slavery: Some interpretations of their
significance in the development of the United States and the Western World.
In J. A. Williams and C. F. Harris, eds, Amistad I, 119-164. New York:
Vintage.
Jett, S. C. (1991). Further information on the geography of the blowgun and its
implications for transoceanic contacts. Annals of the Association of American
Geographers 81:89-102.
Jha, S. C. (1963). Studies in the development of capitalism in India. Calcutta:
Mukhopadhyay.
Johnson, K. (1977). Do as the land bids: A study of Otomi resource use on the eve of
irrigation. Ph.D. diss., Clark University.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Joly, N. (1897). Man before metals. New York: Appleton.
Jones, E. L. ( 1981 ). The European miracle. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press.
. (1988). Growth recurring: Economic change in world history. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Jung, C. (1963). Memories, dreams, reflections. New York: Random House.
. (1964). The dreamlike world of India. In his Civilization in transition
{Collected works, vol. 10). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
. (1971). Psychological types (Collected works, vol. 6). Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Kabaker, A. (1977). A radiocarbon chronology relevant to the origins of agriculture.
In C. A. Reed, ed., Origins of agriculture. The Hague: Mouton.
Kagan, D., Ozment, S., and Turner, E (1987). The Western heritage, 2 vols., 3rd ed.
New York: Macmillan.
Kea, R. (1982). Settlements, trade, and polities in the seventeenth-century Gold Coast.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Keightley, T. (1849). Outlines of history. Rev. ed. London: Longmans.
Kerridge, E. (1968). The agricultural revolution. New York: A. M. Kelley.
Kertzer, D. (1989). The joint family household revisited: Demographic constraints
and household complexity in the European past. Journal of Family History
14:1-16.
Kinder, H., and Hilgemann, W. (1974). The Anchor atlas of world history, Vol. 1. New
York: Anchor Books.
Kitching, G. (1983). Proto- industrialization and demographic change. Journal of
African History 24:221-240.
Kniffen, F. (1965). Folk housing: Key to diffusion. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers 55:549-577.
Koepping, K.-P. (1983). Adolf Bastion and the psychic unity of mankind. St. Lucia,
Australia: University of Queensland Press.
Kosambi, D. D. (1969). Ancient India. New York: Meridian Books.
Kroeber, A. (1937). Diffusionism. In Encyclopedia of the social sciences, 5:139-142.
New York: Macmillan.
Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Laclau, E. (1977). Politics and ideology in Marxist theory. London: New Left Books.
Laibman, D. (1984). Modes of production and theories of transition. Science and
Society 48(3):257-294.
Lambert, D. (1971). The role of climate in the economic development of the tropics.
Land Economics 47:339-344.
Lane, F. (1973). Venice: A maritime republic. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press.
Laslett, P. (1988). The European family and early industrialization. In J. Baechler, J.
A. Hall, and M. Mann, eds., Europe and the rise of capitalism. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Lattimore, O. (1980). The periphery as locus of innovation. In J. Gottmann, ed.,
Centre and periphery: Spatial variation and politics. Beverly Hills. CA: Sage
Publications.
Lee, G. (1987). Comparative perspectives. In M. B. Sussman and S. K. Steinmetz,
eds., Handbook of marriage and the family. New York: Plenum.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Lee, R. (1992). Art, science, or politics? The crisis in hunter-gatherer studies.
American Anthropologist 94:31-54.
Lelekov, L. (1985). Round-table: State and law in the ancient Orient. (Discussion.)
Social Sciences (USSR Academy of Sciences) 16(3):177— 201.
Lentnek, B. (1969). Economic transition from traditional to commercial agriculture.
Annals of the Association of American Geographers 59:65-84.
Lerner, R., Meacham, S., and Burns, E. (1988). Western civilizations: Their history and
their culture. 11th ed. New York: Norton.
Le Roy Ladurie, E. (1985). A reply to Robert Brenner. In T. Aston and C. Philpin,
eds., The Brenner debate: Agrarian class structure and economic development in
pre-industrial Europe. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Levitzion, N. (1972). The early states of the Western Sudan to 1500. In J. Ajayi and
M. Crowder, eds., History of West Africa, Vol. 1. New York: Columbia
University Press.
LeVy-Bruhl, L. (1966). How natives think. New York: Washington Square Press.
Lewis, A. (1973). Maritime skills in the Indian Ocean, 1368-1500. Journal of the
Economic and Social History of the Orient 16:238-264.
Lewis, W. A., ed. (1970). Tropical development, 1880-1913. Evanston, IL: Northwest-
ern University Press.
Liceria, M. A. C. (1974). Emergence of Brahmanas as landed intermediaries in
Karnataka, c. a.d. 1000-1300. Indian Historical Review 1(1):28— 35.
Lloyd, G. (1990). Demystifying mentalities. Cambridge, England: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Lo Jung-pang. (1955). China as a sea power. Far Eastern Quarterly 14:489-503.
Lopez, R. (1953). Hard times and investment in culture. In R. Lopez, ed., The
Renaissance: A symposium. New York: Metropolitan Museum of Art.
, and Miskimin, H. (1961-1962). The economic depression of the
Renaissance. Economic History Review 14:408-426.
Lord, J. (1869). Ancient states and empires: For colleges and schools. New York: Charles
Scribner.
Lovell, W. G. (1992). "Heavy shadows and black night": Disease and depopulation in
Colonial Spanish America. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
82:426-443.2
Lowie, R. (1937). The history of ethnological theory. New York: Rinehart.
Lowith, K. (1982). Max Weber and Karl Marx. London: Allen and Unwin.
Ma Huan. (1970). The overall survey of the ocean's shores. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Mabogunji, A. (1972). The land and peoples of West Africa. In J. Ajayi and M.
Crowder, eds., History of West Africa, Vol. 1. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Macauley, T. (1850-1861). The history ofEnglandfrom the accession of James the Second.
5 vols. London: Longman.
Macfarlane, A. (1978). The origins of English individualism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
. (1986). Marriage and love in England: Modes of reproduction 1300-1840.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
. (1988) The cradle of capitalism. In J. Baechler, J. A. Hall, and M. Mann,
eds., Europe and the rise of capitalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Magalhaes-Godinho, V. (1969). L'economie de I'empire portugais aux XV et XVI siecles.
Paris: SEVPEN.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Magubane, B. (1987). The ties that bind: African-American consciousness and Africa.
Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press.
Mahalingam, T. (1951). Economic life in the Vijayanagar Empire. Madras: University of
Madras Press.
Malinowski, B. (1927). The life of culture. In G. Eliot Smith, ed., Culture: The
diffusion controversy. New York: Norton.
Mamdani, M. (1972). The myth of population control. New York: Monthly Review
Press.
Mandelbaum, M. (1971). History, man and reason: A study in nineteenth-century
thought. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Mann, M. (1986). The sources of social power: Vol. 1. A history of power from the
beginning to A.D. 1 760. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
. (1988). European development: Approaching a historical explanation. In J.
Baechler, J. A. Hall, and M. Mann, eds., Europe and the rise of capitalism.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Mannheim, K. 1936. Ideology and Utopia. New York: Harcourt, Brace.
Marglin, S. (1990). Losing touch: The cultural conditions of worker accommodation
and resistance. In F. Marglin and S. Marglin, eds., Dominating knowledge:
Development, culture, and resistance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Markham, S. (1944), Climate and die energy of nations. London: Oxford University
Press.
Marx, K. (1976). Capital. New York: Vintage.
. (1979). The British rule in India. In Marx and Engels: Collected Works,
12:125-33. Moscow: Progress.
, and Engels, F. (1975). Selected correspondence. 3d ed. Moscow: Progress.
, and Engels, F. (1976). The German ideology. Moscow: Progress.
McAlister, L. (1984). Spain and Portugal in the New World, 1492-1700. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press
McClelland, D. (1961). The achieving society. Princeton, NJ: Van Nostrand.
McKay, D. (1943). Colonialism in the French geographical movement. Geographical
Rev/ew 33:214-232.
McNeill, W. (1967). A world history. New York: Oxford University Press.
. (1976). Plagues and peoples. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books.
Mead, G. H. (1936). Movements of thought in the nineteenth century. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
. (1938). The philosophy of the act. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Mead, M. (1930). Growing up in New Guinea. New York: Blue Ribbon Books.
Megaw, J., ed. (1977). Hunters, gatherers and first farmers beyond Europe: An
archeological survey. Leicester, England: Leicester University Press.
Merriman, T. (1875). The trail of history. 3d ed. Boston: Merriman and Stewart.
Miller, J. (1982). The significance of drought, disease, and famine in the agriculturally
marginal zones of West-Central Africa. Journal of African History 23:17-61.
. (1988). Way of death. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Milne, G. (1947). A soil reconnaissance journey through parts of Tanganyika
Territory, December 1935 to February 1936. Journal of Ecology 35:192-265.
Minchinton, W. (1969). The growth of English overseas trade. London: Methuen.
Mintz, S. W. (1985). Sweetness and power: The place of sugar in modem history. New
York: Penguin Books.
Miskimin, H. (1969). The economy of early Renaissance Europe, 1300-1460.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Mohr, E., and van Baren, F. (1954). Tropical soils. Amsterdam: Royal Tropical
Institute.
Montesquieu. (1949). The spirit of the laws. New York: Hafher Press. (Originally
published in 1748.)
Mukherjee, Radhakamal. (1967). The economic history of India, 1600-1800.
Allahabad, India: Kitab Mahal.
Mukherjee, Ramkrishna. (1958). The rise and fall of the East India Company. 2d ed.
Berlin: VEB Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften.
Muller J. (1842). The history of the world to 1783. 4 vols. Boston: Webb.
Nag, M. (1980). How modernization can also increase fertility. Current Anthropology
21:571-588.
Naqvi, H. K. (1968). Urban centres in Upper India, 1556-1803. Bombay: Asia
Publishing House.
Needham, J. (1985). Gunpowder as the fourth estate east and west. Hong Kong: Hong
Kong University Press.
, and collaborators. (1954-1984). Science and civilization in China. 6 vols.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Neumann, E. (1954). The origins and history of consciousness. New York: Scribner's.
Newsom, L. (1985). Indian population patterns in colonial Spanish America. Latin
American Research Review 20(3): 41—74-
Niane, D. (1984). Mali and the second Mandingo expansion. In D. Niane, ed.,
UNESCO general history of Africa, Vol. 4. Paris: UNESCO.
, ed. (1984). UNESCO general history of Africa, Vol. 4. Paris: UNESCO.
Nicholas, D. M. (1967-68). Town and countryside: Social and economic tensions in
14th century Flanders. Comparative Studies in Society and History 10:458-485.
Nisbet, R. (1980). History of the idea of progress. New York: Basic Books.
Nurul Hasan, S. (1969). The position of the Zamindars in the Mughal Empire. In R.
Frykenberg, ed., Land control and social structure in Indian history. Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press.
Nye, P., and Greenland, D. (1960). The soil under shifting cultivation. Farnham Royal,
England: Commonwealth Agricultural Bureaux.
O'Keefe, P., and Wisner, B. (1975). African drought: The state of the game. In P.
Richards, ed., African environment: Problems and perspectives, London:
International African Institute.
Onimode, B. (1982). Imperialism and underdevelopment in Nigeria. London: Zed Books.
Orwin, C, and Orwin, C. (1967). The open fields. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Osae, T, Nwabara, S., and Odunsi, A. (1973). A short history of West Africa. New
York: Hill and Wang.
Pacey, A. (1990). Technology in world history: A thousand-year history. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Padgug, R. (1976). Problems in the theory of slavery and slave society. Science and
Society 40:3-28.
Palmer, R., ed. (1957). Atlas of world history. Chicago: Rand McNally.
Panikkar, K. M. (1959). Asia and Western influence. London: Allen and Unwin.
Parsons, J. B. (1970). Peasant rebellions of the late Ming Dynasty. Tucson: University of
Arizona Press.
Pearse, A. (1980). Seeds of plenty, seeds of want: Social and economic implications of the
green revolution. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Pendleton, R. (1943). Land use in north-eastern Thailand. Geographical Review
33:14-41.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Perry, W. (1935). The primordial ocean. London: Methuen.
Piaget, J. (1971). Psychology and epistemology. New York: Grossman Publishers.
Pinar, W. (1974). Heightened consciousness, cultural revolution, and curriculum theory.
Berkeley, CA: McCutchan.
Pires, T. (1944). The Suma Oriental. London: Hakluyt Society.
Ploetz, C, andTillinghast, W. (1883). Epitome of ancient, medieval, and modem history.
Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.
Prakash, I. (1964). Organization of industrial production in urban centres in India
during the 17th century with special reference to textiles. In B. Ganguli, ed.,
Readings in Indian economic history. Bombay, India.
Prescott, J., and Pendleton, R. (1952). Laterites and lateritic soils. Slough, England:
Commonwealth Agricultural Bureaux.
Purcell, V. (1965). The Chinese in Southeast Asia. 2d ed. London: Oxford University
Press.
Qaisar, A. J. (1974). The role of brokers in medieval India. Indian Historical Review
1:220-246.
Quackenbos, J. ( 1889) . Illustrated school history of the world. New York: American Book
Company.
Radell, D. R. (1976). The Indian slave trade and population of Nicaragua during the
sixteenth century. In W. Denevan, ed., The Native Population of the Americas
in 1492. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Radin, P. (1927). Primitive man as philosopher. New York: Appleton.
. (1965). The method and theory of ethnology. New York: Basic Books.
Ratzel, F. (1896). The history of mankind (Volkerkunde) . 2 vols. London: Macmillan.
Rawski, E. (1972). Agricultural change and the peasant economy of South China.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Raychaudhuri, T. (1962). Jan Company in Coromandel. The Hague: Nijhoff.
. (1965). The agrarian system of Mughal India. Enquiry 2(l,n.s.):92-121.
Reclus, E. (1876-1894) Nouvelle geographie universelle. Paris: Hachette.
Reed, C. A., ed. (1977). Origins of agriculture. The Hague: Mouton.
Richards, P., ed. (1975). African environment: Problems and perspectives. London:
International African Institute.
Robbins, R. (1832). The world displayed in its history and geography: Embracing a history
of the world from the Creation to the present day. New York: W. W. Reed.
Roberts, J. (1987). The Hutchinson history of the world. 2d ed. London: Hutchinson.
Robinson, C. (1987). Capitalism, slavery and bourgeois historiography. History
Workshop 23:122-141.
Rodinson, M. (1973). Islam and capitalism. New York: Pantheon.
. (1974). Le marchand musulman. In D. S. Richards, ed., Islam and the trade of
Asia. Cambridge, England: Cassirer.
Rodney, W. (1970). A history of the Upper Guinea Coast, 1545-1800. New York:
Monthly Review Press.
. (1972). How Europe underdeveloped Africa. London: Bogle-L'Ouverture
Publications, and Dar es Salaaam: Tanzania Publishing House.
Rogers, E. (1962). The diffusion of innovations . New York: Free Press.
, and Shoemaker, F. (1971). Communication of innovations. New York: Free
Press.
Rorty, R. (1980). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Rouse, I. (1961). Comments on Edmonson's Neolithic diffusion rates. Current
Anthropology 2:96.
232 THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
. (1986). Migrations in prehistory. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Roxborough, I. (1979). Theories of underdevelopment. London: Macmillan.
Sack, R. (1980). Conceptions of space in social thought. London: Macmillan.
Said, E. (1979). Orientalism. New York: Random House.
Sanderson, E. (1898). History of the world from the earliest time to the year 1898. New
York: Appleton.
Sastri, K. N. (1966). A history of South India from prehistoric times to the fall of
Vijayanagar. 3d ed. Madras: Oxford University Press.
Schmidt, W. (1939). The culture historical method of ethnology. New York: Fortuny.
Schweder, R. (1990). Cultural psychology: What is it? In J. Stigler, R. Schweder, and
G. Herdt, eds., Cultural psychology : Essays on comparative human development.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Seccombe, W. (1983). Marxism and demography. New Left Review no. 137, pp.
22-47.
Semo, E. (1982). Historia del capitalismo en Mexico: Los origenes, 1521—1763. Mexico,
D.F.: Ediciones Era.
Shannon, G., and Pyle, G. (1989). The origin and diffusion of AIDS. Annals of the
Association of American Geographers 79:1-24.
Sharma, R. S. (1965). Indian feudalism, c.300-1200. Calcutta: University of Calcutta
Press.
. (1966). Light on early Indian society and economy Bombay: Manaktalas.
Shepherd, W. (1911). Historical atlas. New York: Henry Holt.
Sheridan, R. (1974). Sugar and slavery. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University
Press.
. (1987). Eric Williams and Capitalism and slavery: A biographical and
historiographical essay. In B. Solow and S. Engerman, eds. British capitalism
and Caribbean slavery: The legacy of Eric Williams. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Sherif, A. (1987). Slaves, spices and ivory in Zanzibar. London: James Currey.
Simkin C, (1968). The traditional trade of Asia. London: Oxford University Press.
Simonsen, R. (1944). Historia econdmica do Brasil, 1500-1820, 2d ed. Sao Paulo,
Brazil: Companhia Editora Nacional.
Sinclair, P. (1991). Archeology in eastern Africa: An overview of current
chronological issues. Journal of African History 32:179-219.
Smith, A. (1972). The early states of the Central Sudan. In J. Ajayi and M. Crowder,
eds., History of West Africa, Vol. 1. New York: Columbia University Press.
Smith, C. T. (1969). An historical geography of Western Europe before 1800. London:
Longmans.
Smith, P. (1868). An ancient history: From the earliest records to the fall of the Western
Empire. 3 vols. London: Walton.
So Kwan-wai. (1975). Japanese piracy in Ming China during the 16th century. East
Lansing: Michigan State University Press.
Solow, B. ( 1987). Capitalism and slavery in the exceedingly long run. In B. Solow and
S. Engerman, eds. British capitalism and Caribbean slavery: The legacy of Eric
Williams. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
, and Engerman, S., eds. (1987). British capitalism and Caribbean slavery: The
legacy of Eric Williams. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Spencer, H. (1969). The man versus the state. Baltimore: Penguin Books.
Spradley, J., and McCurdy, D. (1975). Anthropology: A cultural perspective. New York:
Wiley.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Steele, J., and Steele, E. (1883). A brief history of ancient, medieval, and modem peoples.
New York: American Book Co.
Steward, J. (1955). Theory of culture change: The methodology of multilinear evolution.
Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Stocking, G. (1968). Race, culture, and evolution. New York: Free Press.
. (1987). Victorian anthropology. New York: Free Press.
, ed. (1984). Functionalism historicized: Essays on British social anthropology.
Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Stone, L. (1977). The family, sex and marriage in England 1500-1800. New York:
Harper and Row.
Sweezy, P. (1976). A critique. In R. Hilton, ed., The transition from feudalism to
capitalism. London: New Left Books.
Swindell K. (1981). Domestic production, labor mobility, and population change in
West Africa, 1900-1980. In C. Fyfe and D. McMaster, eds., African historical
demography. Edinburgh, Scotland: Centre of African Studies.
Swinton, W. (1874). Outlines of the world's history. New York: Ivison, Blakeman,
Taylor.
Taeuber, I. (1970). The families of Chinese farmers. In M. Freedman, ed., Family and
kinship in Chinese society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Talkington, L. (1986). But the editor looks at the universe from a different frame of
reference. Science and Nature, nos. 7-8, pp. 94-100.
Tarde, G. (1903). The laws of imitation. New York: Henry Holt.
Tawney, R. H. (1952). Religion and the rise of capitalism. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Taylor, G. (1945). Environment and nation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Temu, A., and Swai, B. (1981). Historians and Africanist history: A critique. London:
Zed Books.
Thalheimer, M. (1883). Outline of general history for the use of schools. New York:
American Book Co.
Thapar, R. (1978). Ancient Indian social history: Some interpretations. New Delhi, India:
Orient Longman.
. (1982). Ideology and the interpretation of early Indian history. Review
5:389-412.
Thorndyke, L. (1943). Renaissance or prenaissance? Journal of the History of Ideas
4:65-74.
Thrupp, S. (1948). The merchant class of medieval London (1300-1500). Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
. (1972). Medieval industry 1000-1500. In C. Cipolla, ed., The Fontana
economic history of Europe: The Middle Ages. London: Collins.
Tiedemann, C, and Van Doren, C. (1964). The diffusion of hybrid seed com in Iowa:
A spatial diffusion study. Institute for Community Development and Services,
Michigan State University, Bulletin B-44.
Titow, J. Z. (1969). English rural society, 1200-1350. London: Allen and Unwin.
Tolman, E. (1951). A Psychological model. InT. Parsons and E. Shils, eds., Towards
a general theory of action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Torras, J. (1980). Class struggle in Catalonia. Review 4:253-265.
Toulmin, S., and Goodfield, J. (1965). The discovery of time. New York: Harper and
Row.
Toyoda, T. (1969). History of pre-Meiji commerce in Japan. Tokyo: Japan Cultural
Society.
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Trigger, B. (1989). A history of archeohgical thought. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
Tung, C. (1979). Outline history of China. Hong Kong: Joint Publishing Co.
Turner, B. (1978). Marx and the end of Orientalism. London: Allen and Unwin.
Turshen, M. (1987). Population growth and the deterioration of health: Mainland
Tanzania, 1920-1960. In D. Cordell and J. Gregory, eds., African population
and capitalism: Historical perspectives. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Tyler, S., ed. (1969). Cognitive anthropology. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Tytler, A. (1844). Universal history, from the Creation to the beginning of the eighteenth
century. Rev. ed. Boston: Massey.
Udovitch, A. (19741* Commercial techniques in early medieval Islamic trade. In D.
S. Richards, ed., Islam and the trade of Asia. Cambridge, England: Cassirer.
Usman, Y. B. (1981). The transformation of Katsina (1400-1883). Zaria, Nigeria:
Ahmadu Bello University Press.
Van Leur, J. C. (1955). Indonesian trade and society. The Hague: W. van Hoeve.
Van Sertima, I. (1976). They came before Columbus. New York: Random House.
Van Young, E. (1983). Mexican rural history since Chevalier: The historiography of
the colonial hacienda. Latin American Research Review 28(3):5— 61.
Vavilov, N. (1951). The origin, variation, immunity, and breeding of cultivated plants.
New York: Ronald Press.
Venturi, F. (1963). The history of the concept of "oriental despotism" in Europe. The
Journal of the History of Ideas 24:133-143.
Vilar, P. (1976). A history of gold and money, 1450-1920. London: New Left Books.
Vishnu-Mittre. (1978). Origin and history of agriculture in the Indian subcontinent.
Journal of Human Evolution 7:31—36.
Vives, J. Vicens. (1969). An economic history of Spain. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Wachtel, N. (1984). The Indian and Spanish conquest. In Bethell, L., ed., The
Cambridge history of Latin America: Colonial Latin America, Vol. 1. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Wai Andah, B. (1981). West Africa before the seventh century. In G. Mokhtar, ed.,
UNESCO general history of Africa: Vol. 2. Ancient civilizations of Africa. Paris:
UNESCO.
Wallerstein, I. (1974-1988). The modem world system. 3 vols. New York: Academic
Press.
Warren, B. (1980). Imperialism: Pioneer of capitalism. London: New Left Books.
Watson, A. (1983). Agricultural innovation in the early Islamic world: The diffusion of
crops and farming techniques, 700-1100. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
Watts, S. J., Okello, R., and Watts, S. (1990). Medical geography and AIDS. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 80:301-304.
Webb, W. P. (1951). The great frontier. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Weber, G. (1853). Outlines of universal history. Rev. ed. Edited by F. Brown. Boston:
Brewer and Tileston.
Weber, M. (1951). The religion of China. New York: Free Press.
. (1958). The Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism. New York: Scribner's.
. (1967). The religion of India. New York: Free Press.
. (1968). Economy and society. 2 vols. New York: Bedminster Press.
. (1976). The agrarian sociology of ancient civilizations. London: New Left
Books.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
. (1981). General economic history. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books.
Wendorf, E, and Schild, R. (1980). Prehistory of the Eastern Sahara. New York:
Academic Press.
Werner, K. F. (1988). Political and social structures of the West, 300-1300. In J.
Baechler, J. A. Hall, and M. Mann, eds., Europe and the rise of capitalism.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Werner, H., and Kaplan, B. (1964). Symbol formation. New York: John Wiley.
Wheatley, P. (1961). The Golden Khersonese: Studies in the historical geography of the
Malay Peninsula before a.d. J 500. Kuala Lumpur: University of Malaya Press.
. (1971). The pivot of the four quarters: A preliminary inquiry into the origins and
character of the ancient Chinese city. Chicago: Aldine.
Whelpley, S. (1844). A compound of history, from the earliest times. 12th ed. New York:
Collins Brothers.
White, G., ed. (1974). Natural hazards: Local, national, global. New York: Oxford
University Press.
White, Lynn, Jr. (1962). Medieval technology and social change. London: Oxford
University Press.
. (1968). Machina ex deo: Essays in the dynamism of Western culture.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
. (1968) The historical roots of our ecological crisis. In his Machina ex deo:
Essays in the dynamism of Western culture, 75-94. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality. New York: Humanities Press.
. (1938). Modes of thought. New York: Macmillan.
: — . (1948). Science and philosophy. New York: Philosophical Library.
Whitman, J. ( 1984). Philology to anthropology in mid-nineteenth-century Germany.
In G. Stocking, ed., Functionalism historicized: Essays on British social
anthropology. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Whitmore, T. (1991). A simulation of sixteenth-century population collapse in the
Basin of Mexico. Annals of the Association of American Geographers
81:464-487.
Wiethoff, B. (1963). Die Chinesische Seeverbotspolitik und der Private Oberseehandel von
1368 bis 1567. Hamburg, Germany: Gesellschaft fiir Natur- und Volkerkunde
Ostasiens.
Wilken, G. (1987). Good farmers: Traditional resource management in Mexico and
Central America. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Willard, E. (1845). Universal history in perspective. 2d ed. New York: Barnes.
Williams, E. (1944). Capitalism and slavery. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina
Press.
. (1966). British historians and the West Indies. London: Andre Deutsch.
Williams, R. (1990). The American Indian in Western legal thought: The discourses of
conquest. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wisner, B. (1989). Power and need in Africa. Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press.
, and Mbithi, P. (1974). Drought in Eastern Kenya. In G. White, ed., Natural
hazards: Local, national, global. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wittfogel, K. (1957). Oriental despotism. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Wolf, E. (1982). Europe and the peoples without history. Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press.
Wrigley, E. (1969). Population and history. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Wunder, H. (1985). Peasant organization and class conflict in eastern and western
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Germany. In T. Aston and C. Philpin, eds., The Brenner debate: Agrarian class
structure and economic development in pre-industrial Europe. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Yadava, B. (1966). Secular land grants of the post-Gupta period and some aspects of
the growth of the feudal complex in northern India. In D. Sircar, ed., Land
system and feudalism in ancient India. Calcutta, India.
. (1974). Immobility and subjugation of Indian peasantry in early medieval
complex. Indian Historical Review 1:18—74.
Yang Lien-sheng (1970). Government control of urban merchants in traditional
China. Tsingh.ua Journal of Chinese Studies 8:186-206.
Yapa, L. ( 1980). Diffusion, development, and ecopolitical economy. In J. Agnew, ed.,
Innovation research and public policy. Syracuse, NY: Department of Geography,
Syracuse University.
Zwernemann, J. (1983). Culture history and African anthropology. Acta Universitatis
Upsaliensis, Uppsala Studies in Cultural Anthropology. Uppsala, Sweden:
Uppsala University.
Index
Abel, W., 209
Abu-Lughod, J., 51, 57, 172, 177, 178
Acapulco, 190
Accessibility. See Location
Accumulation, 129, 152, 187, 189, 192, 195,
199, 204-206, 212
primitive, 188, 189, 210
Adams, B., 212
Adulthood, 17, 95-98
Africa, Africans, 4, 15, 20-22, 45, 51, 57, 62, 64,
98-99, 103, 105-107, 109, 116, 119, 120,
123-124, 138, 140, 149, 153, 155-158, 160,
162, 166, 168-169, 171, 173-174, 180, 183,
187, 188, 189, 193, 195, 196, 197, 200, 201,
203, 206, 209
East, 167, 182-183, 191, 192, 207-209
South, 89, 141, 144, 152, 155-157, 166-167
apartheid in, 75, 141, 144
myth of emptiness in, 75
North, 3, 46, 82-90, 157, 209
tropical, 69-80, 140, 141
West, 79, 155, 181-183, 191, 204, 207-209
African-Americans, 98
Agriculture, 29, 44-45, 117, 154-165, 169
aridity and, 80-90, 143
drainage, 85-86, 143, 164, 174
and industrial revolution, 213
intensification and commercialization, 157—
158, 161, 163-164, 166
irrigated, 74-78, 80-90, 109-110, 143, 162,
164, 174
labor productivity in, 89, 91, 143, 157, 174
medieval, 110-115, 157-165, 168
origins. See Agricultural revolution
peasant. See Peasants
plantation. See Plantations
rain-fed (dry field), 74-76, 84, 86, 88-91
sedentary, 74-76
shifting, 72-76, 141-142, 174
tropical, 70-77, 140, 174
Agricultural revolution, 4, 7, 23, 44-45, 155—
157, 164, 172, 174, 185-186, 209
Ahn, P., 140
AIDS, 77, 215-216
and Africa, 142,215-216
Ajayi.J., 176
Akan, 157
Alavi, K, 212
Alchon, S., 209
Alliance for Progress, 49
Amazon river and basin, 71, 74, 207
America, 51, 103, 152, 162, 173, 180, 183-184,
187, 200, 204, 206, 208-209
Latin, 22, 76, 131
North, 180
South, 141
Americans, Native, 97, 138, 194, 195
Amin, S., 51, 56, 57, 47, 135, 136, 137, 154, 173,
177,205,211
Andean region, 20, 184, 194, 195
Anderson, J., 44
Anderson, P., 58, 108, 138, 142, 146, 176
Angola, 49
Anthrax, 78
Anthropology, 23-24, 30-33, 65, 97, 102
and primitive mind, 97, 102
Antilles. See West Indies, Antilles
Antwerp, 189-190, 192
Appadorai, A., 176
Arabia, 92, 167
Arabs, 98, 99, 181
Aristocracy, medieval, 123, 125-127
Armenia, 43
Aryan theory, 12, 84, 89
237
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Asad, X, 48
Asia, 21-22, 77, 80-90, 103-107, 123, 155-158,
160, 162, 165-166, 171, 173, 180, 183,
187-189, 193, 195, 196, 197, 200, 206
aridity in, 80-90
East, 30, 46, 152, 167
South, 46, 56, 76, 167
Southeast, 21, 56, 76, 117-120, 167, 171,
181
Asiatic mode of production, 81-83, 125, 157
Aston, X, 140, 149, 150
Athenian empire, 125
Atlantic Ocean, 181-182, 211
crossing, 14, 181, 207-209
Atwell, W., 210
Augsburg, 197
Australians, 45
Azores Islands, 182
Aztecs, 185
Baechler.J., 122-123, 125-127, 147, 149, 160,
176
Bailey, A., 142
Bailey, R., 205, 212, 213
Bakewell, P., 211
Bali, 120
Baltic Sea, 167, 171, 197, 200, 211
Bangladesh, 71
Barbados, 68, 71, 197
Barbarism, zone of, 14
Barnes, H. E, 44
Beckles, H., 205, 213
Belief-value matrix, 38
Beliefs, 30-43
compatibility of, 34-37
conformality and binding of, 35-41
ethnography of, 30-41
explicit and implicit, 36, 40-41, 65
truth and, 30-32
Bengal, 166
Berkner, L., 150
Bernal, M., 44, 55, 57, 137, 138, 144
Bernier, E, 142
Bible Lands, 3, 5, 7, 29, 43-45, 81
Big Bang Theory, 214-216
Birth
conception and, 67, 139
control, 66-67, 129, 139
rates, 128-130, 140
Bjtfrklund, O., 149
Black, C, 136
Black death, 46, 77
Black magic, 16
Blaut, ]., 48, 49, 136, 138, 140, 141, 142, 143,
145, 149, 173, 174, 175, 176, 177, 178, 209,
212, 215
Blockages, historical, 69, 80, 117, 137
Blow-gun, 11
Blum, J., 139
Boas, E, 97, 139, 144
Bogeyman, 16, 47
Bois G., 150
Bojador, Cape, 209
Borah, W., 209,211
Bourgeois revolutions, 165, 179-180, 187, 199,
200
Bourgeoisie, 179, 195
Bowler, P., 48, 138, 141, 144
Brading, D., 210
Brantlinger, P., 48
Braudel,E, 178,210
Bray, Francesca, 143, 146, 211
Brazil, 20, 182, 188, 191-192, 195, 197, 216
Brenner, R., 58, 108, 127-128, 138, 146, 149,
150, 151, 160, 176, 177, 205, 213
Britain, 108, 146-147, 150, 166, 179, 187-188,
191-192, 197, 203, 211,213
Brown, L., 145
Buck, J. L, 131
Buckle, H. X, 76, 77, 141, 142
Burghers. See Bourgeoisie
Burma, 147
Cabral, A., 54, 136
Cairo, 187
Calicut, 190, 196
Cambodia, 147
Cambridge University, 135
Canada, 43, 156
Canals, in China, 93, 113
Canary Islands, 182, 208, 209
Cape Bojador, 209
Cape of Good Hope, 181
Capes and bays theory, 92, 122
Capitalism, 8, 51, 102, 152, 161-163, 165, 167,
169-170, 179-180, 187-206, 210
centration of, 180, 191, 197, 201-206
in colonial America, 55
origins and rise, 55, 102, 127-128, 150
triumph of, 179
Caribbean. See under West Indies
Carter, G., 47
Carus-Wilson, E., 212
Cassava, 156
Caucasus, 11, 43
Center-periphery model, 14
Centration of capitalism. See Capitalism, centra-
tion of
Cespedes, G., 210
Ch'in empire, 125
Chad, Lake and region, 120, 157
Chambers, M., 46
Chan-Cheung,]., 177
Chandra, B., 48, 142
Chandra, S., 177,211
Chao Phraya Basin, 120
Chariots, 143
Chaudhuri, K. N., 177, 207, 211
Chaudhuri, S., 177
Chaunu, H. and P., 210
Cheng Ho, 181, 182, 207
Chicherov, A., 176
Childhood, 17, 95-98
INDEX
China, 15, 21, 29, 46-47, 56-57, 78, 82, 87, 94,
96, 110, 113, 115-120, 122-123, 125, 131,
158-159, 166-167, 169-170, 173, 181-182,
198, 216
Jones on, 67, 106-107
Weber on, 64, 103, 116
Chirimuuta, R. C. and R. J., 142, 216
Christendom, 18
Christianity, 123-124
and diffusionism, 18-19, 21, 60-61, 108
Western (L. White, Jr.), 114-115
Church, 119, 123-124, 147-149
Cipolla, C, 118-119, 147
Cities, 153, 161, 167, 196, 207
ancient, 84
European, 84, 128, 188, 193
medieval, 113, 167, 175, 177
mercantile-maritime, 167-173, 181, 196, 207
Weber on, 84, 103-104, 116
City-states, 104, 123, 167, 171
Civil Rights movement, 5, 137
Civilization, zone of, 14
Class, 33-34, 41, 57, 88, 119, 123-128, 154,
157-158, 170
Baechleron, 125-127
Brenner on, 127-128, 150
Godelier on, 127
in precolonial Africa, 124—125
Class struggle, 8, 53, 127, 149, 150
Classless society, 123-125
Climate and personality, 70—7 1
Climatic determinism or energy, 70-71, 140
Clocks, in China, 117
Cockburn, A., 140, 141
Cognition, 98
of environmental hazards, 93, 101
of space, 101
Cohen, I., 145
Collier, W, 43, 44
Collins, K., 140
Collyer, O., 140
Colonial Development and Welfare, 49
Colonial Office, British, 24
Colonialism, 2, 4, 10, 18-30, 41, 49, 51, 53-57,
62, 70-71, 75, 81, 96, 135, 140, 150,
152-153, 179, 187-206
and diffusionism, 16, 18-30, 53-58
classical, 21-25
modern, 26-30
and rise of Europe, 2, 17-29, 187-205
settler, 15, 21-22, 25, 183
Colonizer's model, 10, 17-30, 41-42
Columbus, C, 209
Congo, 157
Conklin, H., 49
Conquest of America, 179-186
disease and, 183-186
technology and, 182-184
Consciousness, 98, 100-101, 144
Contemporary ancestors, theory of, 16
Continence, European sexual, 66-68, 121, 133—
135
Hall on, 134
Jones on, 67, 121
Cook, S. E, 209,211
Cooper, J., 150
Cordell, D., 139
Core areas, ecological and political, 93-97, 120,
122
Coromandel, 166
Cortes, H. 185, 186
Cotton, cotton textile industry, 164, 166, 212
in Britain and India, 203
Counterdiffusion, 17, 77. See also Black magic;
Dracula; AIDS; Plagues
Coursey, D., 141
Cro-Magnon, 4
Crone, P., 131, 133, 144, 150, 151
Croot, P., 150, 151
Crosby, A, 209
Cross, H. C, 210
Crowder, M., 176
Cuba, 29, 53, 185
Culture, 11, 27, 32-33, 94, 123, 172, 183, 208,
212
Curtin, P., 76, 79, 140, 141, 211, 212
Cyprus, 191
Dalai, E, 144
Danube R., 93
Darby, H., 146
Darity.W, Jr., 205,212, 213
Darwin, C, 4, 23
Das Gupta, A., 175
Decolonization, 28-30, 49, 55, 137
Deerr.Noel, 210, 211, 212
Degeneration, 44-45
Demesnes, farming, 112, 159
Democracy, 8, 88, 107, 120-121, 126
Demography, and diffusionism, 42, 53, 66-68,
93, 119, 139
Denevan, W, 140, 143, 174, 209, 211
Dependency theory, 55, 137, 149, 177
Depopulation
of America, 141, 184-186, 194
of Mexico, 184, 194
of West Africa, 76, 78-79
Descarte, R., 214
Development, 27-30, 53-55, 100-101, 105, 129,
133, 136, 152-153, 214-215
even and uneven, 152-153, 162
DeVisseJ., 207, 209
Dew, T, 44
Dewey, J. 38, 49, 145
Di Meglio, R., 176, 177
Diffusion, 11, 47, 98, 100-101, 115, 136, 145,
155-157, 161-162, 171, 173-174, 215
criss-cross, 115, 156, 160-162, 167, 171, 173
Diffusionism, 11-30, 52-54, 70, 100, 104, 137,
142, 180, 183, 189, 203, 205, 208, 214-215
as a belief system, 41—43
classical, 21-26, 81, 95-98, 170
extreme, 11-12, 27,47,49
modern, 26-30
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Diffusionism {cant.)
origins of, 18-21
Dirks, R, 147
Disasters, natural, 93, 145
Disease, 60, 107, 142. See also Plagues
and conquest of America, 184-186
and Africa, 77-80, 142
and Europe, 77-78
and tropics, 77-80, 142
Dobb, M., 173, 176, 177
Doolittle, W., 143
Dracula, 16, 21, 47
Dualism, 95-97
Man and Nature, 112
mind-body, 101
philosophical, 101, 145, 214
Dualistic-developmental theory of
rationality, 95-98
DuBois, W. E. B., 55
Dunn, R. S., 211
Duruy, V, 44
Dutt, R. P., 55, 212
Duyvendak, J., 56, 137
East India companies, 24, 197
East Indies, Dutch, 49
Edel, M„ 211
Eden, Garden of, 3, 43-44
Edmonson, M., 47
Education, U. S., 101, 145
Egypt, 12, 47, 82-83, 87, 143, 191-192, 197, 208
El Salvador, 7 1
Eliot Smith, G., 47, 49
Elvin, M., 57, 117, 137, 175, 176, 177
Empires, 120, 147
Chinese, 123
Oriental. See Oriental despotism
Roman, 147 '
Emptiness, myth of, 15, 25, 75
Engels, E, 48, 82-84, 86, 127, 142
Engerman, S., 205
England. See Britain
Environment, 69-94, 119
arid, 80-90
European, 90-94
humid-tropical, 69-80, 141
Environmentalism, environmental
determinism, 69, 140, 141, 182, 183
Episteme, Western (Marglin), 101
Equilibrium theories, 27-28
Ethiopia, 157
Ethnogeography, 23, 32
Ethnography of beliefs. See Beliefs
Ethnohistory, 32
Ethnoscience, 2, 32-43, 49
Ethology, 105, 107, 151
Eurocentrism. 1-2, 7-11, 47. See also Diffusion-
ism
Europe, 43, 45, 51, 90-94, 152, 186-187
Greater, 3-8, 14, 46
European intellect, 1, 15-17, 20, 95-108, 121
mind, 58
miracle, myth of 2, 50-151, 214
personality, 132-135, 144
rationality. See Rationality, European
spirit, 1, 15-17, 20, 103-104, 121
Evolution, cultural, 11, 16-17, 22-26, 47, 57,
65, 85, 127, 152-153, 172, 174, 185, 209
Evolutionism, 12, 24, 47
Exploitation, internal and external, 161
Family, 58, 68, 119, 128-135
extended and nuclear, 128-134, 150
European, 90, 126, 128-135
Hajnal on, 129-130
Macfarlane on, 131-134
modern, 128
preindustrial, traditional, 68, 128
Stone on, 130-135
Fei Hsiao-tung, 175
Feminism, 139
Feudal mode of production, 154, 157-165, 171,
173
Feudal property and tenure, 83, 104, 158
Feudalism, 8, 46,51,95, 110, 112, 126-128, 146,
152-154, 158-165, 197, 210
in Africa, 157-158
in India, 55, 158, 160, 175
Fez, 209
Fiedel, S., 209
Fiefs, 158, 175
Figueroa, L., 215
Filesi, T. 209
Finley, M., 108, 146
Fisher, D., 211
Fisher, G., 44
Fisheries, Atlantic, 92, 182, 188, 192, 196-197,
207
Flanders, 166, 188, 197
Fleck, L., 49
Florescano, E., 211
Forests, 89, 106, 140, 143
and ancient Europeans, 84, 107
European, 89-90, 94, 108
tropical, 71-76
Foster, G., 145
Frake, C, 49
France, 147, 179, 203, 204
Frank, A. G., 51, 149, 205,211
Frankel, H., 216
Freedman, M., 150,
Freedom, love of, in Europe, 26, 107, 119,
120-121, 171
Freeman, E., 44
FRELIMO, 175
Freund, J., 145
FuChu-fu 175, 176
Fukien, 166
Functionalism, 27
Furtado, C. 211
Galloway, J. H., 210
Garraty, J., 141
Gay, P., 141
INDEX
Genesis, Book of, 23, 43-45
Genoa, 189
Gentry and nobility, 158
Geography, 1, 3-8, 17, 23-24, 31-32, 45, 47, 65,
96-97, 101, 125, 127, 136
in 19th-century education, 3—7, 96
Germanic culture, ancient, 25, 131—132
Germany, 147
Gernet.J., 176, 177
Giblin, J., 142
Gilfillan, S., 71, 140
Gill, D., 139
Gilman, A., 44
Glorious revolution (English), 165, 197
Godelier, M., 127, 149
Goitein, S., 178
Gold, 183, 188-191
American production, 188-191
and Asian trade, 118, 190
stock in E. Hemisphere, 189
Gold Coast, 166
Golson.J., 143, 174
Goodfield, J., 48
Gopal, L, 175
Gopal, S., 176
Gossett, T., 48, 138, 139
Gould, P., 145
Grand Banks, 182, 207
Greece, 4, 8, 50, 88, 107-108, 123, 147
Greenland, D., 140
Gregory, J., 139
Grosvenor, E., 44
Guilds, medieval, 166
Gunpowder, 115, 117
Guns, cannon, in China, 117-119, 173
Gupta, N. S., 177,210
Habib, 1., 55, 175, 176, 177
Hagen, E., 100-101, 144
Haitian revolution, 204
Hajnal.J., 129-130, 150
Hall, J. A., 59, 67, 77, 86-87, 91, 108, 122-124,
139, 141, 143, 144, 147, 151
Hallam, H., 124, 147
Haller, J., 139
Hallpike, C, 145
Ham, 44
Hamilton, E. J., 190-191,210
Handler, R., 150, 151
Hannemann, M., 211
Hanseatic League and cities, 197
Hardy, E, 140
Harewood, ]., 140
Harris, M., 44, 47, 49, 138
Harrison, P., 143, 176
Hasan, A, 175,210
Haskel, D., 48
Hassan, E, 139
Hawaii, 156
Hecht, S., 140, 141
Hegel, G. W. E, 53, 142
Hegelianism, 43, 48, 91, 120
Hilgemann, W., 149
Hilton, R, 140, 150
Historians, 52-59, 65, 136
absolutionist, 76, 79-80
Historical and ahistorical societies, 137
Historical atlases, 124
Historiography, modernization and, 53-59
History, 1, 3-8, 97, 127
in 19th-century education, 3-7, 43^46
march of (Mann), 91, 108
textbooks, 3-7, 43-46, 96, 124
Western, 46
world, 46
Hodgett, A. J., 210
Holism and reductionism, 22, 33, 41, 48, 119
Htflmhoe, H., 149
Hopkins, A., 174
Horse-collar, horse power, 111, 112—114
Household, extended-family and nuclear-
family, 128-129
Hoyle, R., 150
Huddleston, L., 48
Hudson, B., 45
Hulme, P., 48
Humboldt, W. von, 97
Huntington, E., 70
Hydraulic society. See Agriculture, irrigated;
Asiatic mode of production; Oriental despot-
ism
Iberia, 181-182, 183-184, 188, 197, 211
Ibn al-Faqih, 167
Ibn Khaldun, 183
Iceland, 93
India, 21, 47, 69, 82, 96, 98, 103, 106, 111, 116,
119-120, 122, 131
caste in, 122, 126, 161
classes, 126
de-industrialization of, 203
medieval polity, 122
personality (Weber), 64, 103, 138
Indian Ocean, 92, 117-118, 171, 182
Individual(ism), 25, 87, 90-91, 119, 132, 135,
144
English, 132
European, 87, 90-91, 107, 109, 132-133
Indo-European peoples, languages, 44, 50, 88,
97, 109, 131
Indo-European warrior aristocracy (Baechler),
123, 126
Indochina, French, 49
Indonesia, 92
Indus valley, 82
Industrial revolution, 8, 55, 107, 165, 179, 180,
201-206, 213, 215-216
and mechanization, 202
Industrial production, medieval, 110-115
Inflation, 16th-century,
in Asia, 210
in Europe, 187, 196
Inikori.J., 212,213
Inner Asia, 93
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Innovation, 15, 110-115, 116, 128, 149, 163
Insanity. See Sanity
Inside and Outside, 1, 5, 12-17, 30, 42, 138, 214
Interests and values, 30-31, 37-41
Invention, independent, 11-12, 47, 208
Inventiveness, 12-14, 17, 105, 108-109, 110-
115, 208
Iron, 88-89, 169
early use, 7,75,88-89, 109, 141
iron age, 7, 50, 88-89, 91, 107, 109, 131
Irrawaddy plain, 85
Irvine, E, 141
Irwin, G., 141
Isichei, E., 175
Islam, 119, 122, 123
Italy, 166, 171, 187, 192, 197, 211
Ivanov, V., 144
Jackson, P., 138, 139
Jagirdars, 158
James, C. L. R., 55, 137, 203-206, 212
Japan, 5, 30, 82, 149, 155, 167, 216
Japheth, 44
Java, 71, 120, 166
Jett, S. C, 47
Jews, 99
Jha, S. C, 176, 177
Joly, N., 45
Jones, E. L., 50, 58, 67, 70-71, 77, 86-87, 89, 91,
93, 104-108, 110, 120-121, 123-124, 131-
133, 135, 139, 140, 141, 142, 143, 144, 147,
150, 151
Judeo-Christian teleology, 114
Jung, C, 98, 144
Kabaker, A., 173
Kagan, D., 46
Kalah, 167, 172, 177,
Kant, I., 214
Kantianism, Neo-Kantianism, 48, 101, 214
Kaplan, B., 144
Kea, R., 174, 175, 176
Keightley T, 43, 44, 48
Kenya, 49
Kertzer, D., 150
Keynesianism, 27
Kilwa, 166, 208,
Kinder, H., 149
Kitching, G., 139
Koepping, K.-R, 47
Korea, 147
Kosambi, D. D., 146, 175
Kuhn, T., 37, 49
Labib, S., 207, 209
Labor,
counterdiffusion of, 16
colonial, 193-196
Labor force, colonial Americas and
Europe, 193, 195, 196
Laclau, E., 205, 213
Laibman, D., 142
Lambert, D., 71, 140
Landlords, 158-160, 162, 170
Landownership,
medieval European, 104, 159, 160
peasant, 127, 160
Lane, E, 178
Languages, primitive, 97, 145
Las Casas, B. 195
Lasktt, P., 131, 133-134, 150, 151
Le Roy Ladurie, E., 150
Lee, G., 150
Lee, R., 174
Lelekov, L., 144
Levant, 191
Levidow, L., 139
Levitzion, N., 176, 209
L6vy-Bruhl, L., 97, 101, 144
Lewis, A., 177
Lewis, W. A., 48
Li Ching-neng, 175, 176
Liceria, M. A. C, 175
Lie, B., 149
Lisbon, 190
Livingstone, D., 23
Llobera, J., 142
Lo Jung-pang, 177
Location, accessibility, 2, 157, 161-162, 169-
173, 181, 182, 197
Lombok, 120
Lopez, R., 147, 210
Love and marriage, in Europe, 132—133
Lovell, W.G., 209,211
Lowie, R., 49
Lowith, K., 145
Luzon, 85, 120
MaHuan, 177,209
Mahogunji, A., 175
Macauley, T., 48
Macfarlane, A, 131-133, 150, 151
Madeira, 182, 191
Madrid, 195
Magalhaes-Godinho, V, 21 1
Maghreb, 171, 181, 183
Magna Carta, 122
Magubane, B., 139
Mahalingam, X, 175, 176, 177
Maize, 107, 156
Malabar, 166
Malacca, 167, 172, 190
Malaria, 78
Malthus, T, 48, 66-68, 133
Malthusian theory, 66-68, 73, 87, 129, 133-134,
139-140, 162, 209
Mamdani, M., 139
Mandelbaum, M., 48
Manila Galleons, 190
Manila, 117
Mann, M., 59, 86-91, 93, 107-110, 122-124,
131-133, 139, 143, 144, 146, 147, 148, 150,
151, 176
Manorial system, 159-160
INDEX
Maquiladora plants, 215
Marglin, E, 145
Marglin, S., 101, 145
Mariana Islands, 49
Markets, 17th-century, 199-201
Markham, S., 70
Marriage pattern, European and non-European,
129-135, 139
Marx, K., 25, 39, 48, 76, 82-84, 86, 127, 141,
142, 158, 159, 175, 202, 205, 210, 212
Marxism, 46, 55-57, 77, 94-95, 137, 148, 168
177, 202, 210, 212
Marxists, Eurocentric, 46, 56, 58, 83, 108, 125,
137-138, 149, 157, 162, 205, 213
Maya civilization, 72—73
Mbithi, P., 141
McAlister, L, 210, 211
McClelland, D., 100, 144
McCurdy, D., 49,
McKay, D., 45
McNeill, W., 45, 46, 79, 140, 142, 143, 144, 146,
209
Mead, G. H., 48, 145
Mead, M., 97, 144
Mediterranean, 43-44, 92, 159, 167-168, 172,
181, 183, 200
Megaw, J., 173
Mekong valley, 120
Merchant capital, 179, 188, 192, 207-208, 212
Mesoamerica, 86, 195
Mesopotamia, 82, 85, 120, 143
Metals
age of, 7
precious. See Gold; Silver
Mexico, 20, 180, 182, 185-186, 188, 190,
194-195, 208
Middle East, 4, 7-8, 45^16, 63, 82-90, 109, 110,
116, 155, 156, 167, 170, 183
Migration, rural-urban, 161-162
Mill, J. S., 48
Miller, J., 76, 140, 141
Milne, G., 140
Minchinton, W., 211
Mind
criminal, 144
European. See European mind
female, 96
and matter. See Dualism
primitive, 17, 95-102, 144-145, 148, 151,
206
traditional, 15, 98-102, 145
Mintz, S. W., 205,212,213
Miskimin, H., 209, 210
Moctezuma 185
Modernization, 2, 27-30, 52-54, 59, 98-102,
206
as history, 53-54, 136
theory, 27-30, 98, 128-129, 131
Mohr, E., 140
Moluccas, 190, 192
Montesquieu, 140, 142
Morocco, 166, 191-192, 207, 209
Motivation, need-achievement (McClelland),
100, 125
Mozambique, 49
Mukherjee, Radhakamal, 176
Mukherjee, Ramkrishna, 176
MullerJ., 43
Myth, 59
Nag, M., 139, 140
Naqvi, H. K., 177
Nationalism, nation-state, 119-120, 172, 214
Nazism, 27, 63-64
Needham, J., 56, 115, 137, 143, 146, 147, 177,
178
Neocolonialism, 26—30
Neo-Kantianism. See Kantianism
Neolithic revolution. See Agricultural revolu-
tion
Neolocality, 131-133
Netherlands, Holland, 187-188, 194, 197
Neumann, E., 144
New Guinea, 155
New World (term), 207
Newfoundland, 192
Niane, D., 209, 211
Nicaragua, 195
Nicholas, D., 175, 176
Niger Valley, 86
Nile river and valley, 82, 86, 166, 183
Nisbet, R., 48
Noah, 43, 44, 48
Nurul Hasan, S., 176
Nye, P., 140
O'Keefe, P., 141
Oceania, 158
Okello, R., 142, 216
Olmec civilization, 208
Onimode, B., 174, 175
Operation Bootstrap, 49
Orient Express model, 4, 45, 91
Oriental despotism, 3, 4, 25, 80-92, 120, 142,
157, 171, 174
Hall on, 87, 147
Jones on, 86-87, 120
Mann on, 87-89, 109, 147
Marx and Engels on, 81-82
Weber on, 83-84, 86, 103-104
Wittfogel on, 84-88
Orwin, C. S., 146
Ottoman empire, region, 20, 45, 81, 96
Outside. See Inside
Overpopulation, 66-68, 121, 129, 133, 139. See
also Demography; Malthusianism
Pacey, A., 147
Padgug, R., 125,. 149
Padmore, G., 55
Paleolithic, 124
Palmer, R., 149
Panikkar, K. M., 55, 209
Paris Basin, 170, 195, 197
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Parker, D., 150, 151
Parsons, J. B., 176
Peace ^^oirjps 49
Peasants, 100-101, 107, 109, 112, 133-134, 154,
161-162, 214
Chinese, 166
European, 104
Indian, 127, 166, 175
Pendleton, R., 140
Pepper, 166, 169
Perry, W., 47, 49
Peru, 184-185, 188, 190
Philosophy, 26, 101, 106, 145, 214
Philpin, C, 140, 149, 150
Phoenicians, 47, 208
Piaget,J., 99, 101, 144
Piracy, 188, 196-197
Pires, X, 167, 170, 176, 177
Pizarro, F., 185
Plagues, 78, 142. See also AIDS; Disease, Black
death
counterdiffusion from non-Europe, 16, 77
Plantations, 166, 188, 191-193, 197-201, 204-
205, 212. See also Slave plantation
Brazil, 191-193
Caribbean, 198-201
Ploetz, C, 44
Plow, 88-89, 110-112, 174
Poland, 147
Polygenesis, theory of, 3, 23, 43—45, 61
Portugal, 181, 188, 192, 194, 197, 209
Potato, 156
in Europe, 92, 201
Potosi, 195
Powell, J., 23
Prakash, I., 177
Precious metals. See Gold; Silver
Prescott, J., 140
Printing, in China, Korea, 117
Production versus exchange, 168-170, 177, 205
Progress, 1, 14, 16, 19, 20, 22, 24, 48, 53-54, 60,
102, 114, 132, 136, 155, 180, 206
Progressiveness. See Progress
Property, private, 15, 25-26, 83-84, 88, 104,
116, 158
concept of, 15, 25—26
in medieval Europe, 83-84, 104, 127
in non-Europe, 25-26, 83-84, 116, 158, 175
Protocapitalism, 152, 165-173, 181
in Asia and Africa, 153, 165-173, 190, 195,
197
Protocapitalist system, network, 168-173, 177
Psychic Unity of Mankind, , 12, 47, 94-96, 184,
208
Psychology, 17, 94-100. See also Mind, Reason-
ing
cross-cultural, 98-100, 144
primitive. See Mind, primitive
Puerto Rico, 49
Putting-out system, 166, 215
Purcell, V, 116, 177
Pyle, G., 142, 216
Qaisar, A. J., 177
Quackenbos, J., 44
Racism, 27, 29, 43-44, 61-65, 138
cultural, 64
moderate, 64—65
and myth of European miracle, 1, 4, 29, 61-65,
186
Weber and, 64-65, 138
Radell, D. R., 211
Radin, P., 49, 97, 144
Rain forest, 72-76, 141
Rational Modern Adult European Man, 96-97
Rationality, 15, 17, 19, 21, 94-109, 145, 149,
186, 214
and diffusionism, 17, 60, 94-108, 214
European, 15, 17, 19, 27, 30, 47, 88, 94-108,
110, 114, 120, 129, 135, 139, 143, 149, 206
Hall on, 87
Indo-European, 107, 109
Jones on, 58, 104-107, 120
Jung on, 98
Levy-Bruhl on, 97
Mann on, 107-110
Piaget on, 99, 101
Weber on, 102-104, 145
Rawski, E., 175, 176
Raychaudhuri, T. 175, 176
Reasoning. See also Thought, abstract and
concrete
theoretical vs. empirical, 17, 96- 101, 105
Reclus, E., 45
Red R. (Vietnam), 120
Reductionism. See Holism
Reformation, Protestant, 103, 124, 197
Regionalism, 27
Relativism, cultural, 27
Religion and rise of Europe, 8, 18-19, 29, 60-61
Renaissance, 117, 187
Restlessness, of Europeans, 108
Rhine R.,93, 211
Rice
wet, agriculture, 85, 143, 166, 169, 174
Ritter, K. 82, 142
Robbins R., 43
Roberts, D., 140
Roberts, J., 45, 46, 140, 141, 147
Robinson, C, 205, 212, 213
Rodinson, M., 177
Rodney, W, 175, 205, 213
Rogers, E., 100, 144
R0hr, A., 149
Roman land law, 25
Rome, 4, 8, 25, 50, 107, 110, 125, 147, 195
Rorty, R., 145
Rostow, W, 53
Rotation, 74, 111, 113-114
fallowless, 114
shifting, 74
three-field, 111, 113-114
two-field, 113-114
INDEX
Roy, M. N., 55
Rules, cultural, and exploitation, 212
Russia, 147
Rwanda, 71
Sack, R., 102, 145
Sahara, 76, 183
Sahel, 76
Said, E., 48, 58, 144
Sanderson, E., 44
Sanity, insanity, 17, 96
Sao Tome, 191, 195-196
Sastri, K.N., 176
Savagery, zone of, 14, 44
Savages, 4, 60, 96
Schmidt, W., 49
Schweder, R., 145
Science, social, 31, 37, 38-41, 54, 97
Seccombe, W., 139
Semitic peoples, 44, 63
Semo, E., 211
Serfs, 127-128, 134, 154, 160, 175- 176
Service tenure, 158
Seville, 189, 195
Sexual frustration, and rise of Europe (Stone),
134-135
Shannon, G., 142, 216
Sharma, R. S., 55, 146, 175
Shem, 44
Sheridan, R., 205, 213
Sherif, A., 175, 176, 207
Shipping, 169-170, 181, 196
African and Asian, 117-118, 170, 181
medieval, 117-118, 169-170
Shoemaker, E, 144
Siberia, 199
Silver, 183, 188-191
American production, 188-191
and Asian trade, 118, 190
stock in E. Hemisphere, 189
Simkin C, 177
Simonsen, R., 211
Sinclair, P., 141
Slave plantation, 70, 125, 191-198, 204-205
Slave trade, 70, 79, 188, 192, 199, 203-205
Slavery, 62, 70, 79. 107, 125, 170, 192, 195, 197,
203-205, 208, 212
Smallpox, 78
Smith, Abdullahi, 175
Smith, Adam, 142
Smith, C.T., 146,210
Sofala, 166, 208
Soils. See also Agriculture
fertility, 72-77, 85, 89, 91
gley, in Europe, 92
podzolic, in Europe, 92
temperate, 90-92
tropical, 42, 71-76, 140
waterlogged, 92
Solow, B., 205, 213
South China Sea, 92
Sovereignty, concept of, 15, 25
Soviet Union, Russia, 29, 76, 81, 84
Spain, 181, 188, 192, 194, 197
Spatial revolution, medieval, 169-173, 181
Spatial transport of commodities. See Location;
Spatial revolution
Spencer, H., 22, 48
Spices, 168, 192
Spradley,J., 49
Stages, evolutionary, 125
Stagnation, cultural, 6, 17,84, 90., 116, 124-125
Stagnation of Chinese society, theory of, 1 15-
119, 142, 147
Stalinism, and theory of Oriental
despotism, 81
State, 8, 58, 81, 85, 87, 94, 119-123, 141, 147,
157, 161, 172
in Asia, 123, 126. See also Empire; Oriental
despotism
medieval European, 122
modern, 120-122
size of, 94, 119-122
Steele, E., 44
Steele, J., 44
Steward, ]., 47, 172, 178
Stirrup, iron, 111
Stocking, G., 47, 48, 138, 144
Stone, L, 130, 134-135, 150, 151
Sudan, 157, 183
Sudanic caravans, 93
Sugar, 166, 169, 191, 200
Sugar-cane. See Sugar
Sulawesi, 120
Sumatra, 120
Swai, B., 48
Sweden, 147
Sweet potato, 107, 156
Sweezy, P., 149, 177
Swindell K., 139
Swinton, W., 44
Taeuber.I., 131, 150
Takrur, 209
Talkington, L, 216
Tarzan, 97, 105
Tawney, R. H., 211
Taylor, G., 47, 49
Technological determinism, 108-109
Technology, 29, 57, 94, 108-119, 161, 184, 186,
202
ancient, 109-110
Chinese medieval, 116-119
European medieval, 110-115, 128, 160-161,
163
Temu, A., 48
Tenochtitlan, 185
Ternate, 196
Testing (ACT, SAT, 1Q), 101, 145
Textbooks, as cultural windows, 6, 43-46
Textiles, 169, 192, 203. See also Cotton
Thackeray, W., 48
Thailand, 147
Thalheimer, M., 44
THE COLONIZER'S MODEL OF THE WORLD
Thapar, R., 48
Theory, scientific, 17, 24, 31-32, 34
Third World, 54
Third Worldism, 79, 125, 149
Thorndyke, L, 147, 210
Thought, abstract and concrete, 17, 96—99, 103.
See also Reasoning
Thrupp, S., 176, 212
Tigris-Euphrates valley, 82, 86
Tillinghast, W, 44
Tobacco, 159, 192
Tolman, E., 38, 49
Torras.J., 150
Toulmin, S., 48
Toynbee, A., 71
Toyoda, T, 177
Trade winds, 182
Traditional society, 6, 68, 98, 128
Traditionalism, 15, 98-102, 145
Transoceanic diffusion, 11, 14, 207-209
Travel, radii, 181
Tributary mode of production, 154
Trigger, B., 138
Tropical soils. See Soils
Tropical-nastiness theory, 69—80
Tropics, humid (term), 71
Trypanosomiasis, 79-80
Tung, C, 176
Tunnel history, 3-8, 103, 109-110, 115, 150,
180, 187
Turkey, 45, 183
Turner, B. L, 143
Turshen, M., 142
Tytler, A., 43
Udovitch, A., 177
Underdevelopment, 153, 180
Underdevelopment theory, 55—56, 137, 149
Uniformitarianism, cultural, 42, 47, 122, 124,
184, 208
United Nations, 28
United States, 28, 43
Urbanization. See Cities
Usman, Y. B., 175
Validation of belief, 34
Values, 15, 30-31, 37^11, 103, 207
Vampires, 16, 21, 47
Van Baren, E, 140
VanLeur,J. C, 55,56, 137
Van Sertima, I., 208-209
Venice, 167
Venturi, E, 142
Verifiability, 34, 36, 40
Verification of belief. See Verifiability
Vijayanagar, 170
Vilar, P., 210
Village, 90
European, 159-160, 176
Indian, 127, 159-160, 175-176
Virgin Islands, US, 49
Vishnu-Mittre, 173
Vives, J. Vicens, 210
de Vries.J., 209, 210, 211
Wage labor, 167, 202-205
and slave labor, 203-206, 212
in post-conquest America, 189
Wai Andah, B., 141
Wallerstein, I., 51, 149, 205, 211, 213
Warren, B., 58, 138
Watson, A, 210
Watts, S., 142, 216
Watts, S.J., 216
Webb W. P., 210
Weber, G., 43
Weber, M., 15, 47, 59, 64-65, 83-84, 86-90,
102-104, 115-116, 124, 131, 138, 142, 143,
145, 158, 170
Weberianism, 54, 64-65, 87, 102- 104, 114, 117
Wei R., 86
Werner, H., 99, 144
Werner, K. E, 61, 124, 147-149
West, the, 1, 46, 94
West Indies, 20, 55, 180, 182, 203, 207. See also
under specific topics
and industrial revolution in Britain, 203-206
Whaling, 207, 192
Wheat, 169, 197
Wheatley, P., 57, 137, 177
Whelpley, S., 43
White, G., 145
White, Lynn, Jr., 61, 108, 110-115, 146, 147,
176
White man's grave, 78
Whitehead, A. N., 37, 49, 145
Whitman, J., 144
Whitmore.T, 209,211
Wiethoff, B., 177
Wilken, G., 140
Willard, E., 43
Williams, E., 48, 137, 203-206, 212, 213
Williams, R., 48
Williams thesis, 55, 205
Wisner, B., 141
Wittfogel, K., 83-88, 142
Wolf, E., 137
Women, and rationality, 96-97
Woolen trade, English, 191-192
World models, 30-31, 4M3, 214
World system, capitalist, 206
Wrigley.E., 151
Wunder, H., 150
Yadava, B., 175, 176
Yam, 74-75
Yang Lien-sheng, 177
Yellow R. 86
Zamindars, 24, 175
Zimbabwe, 157, 166, 197
Zwernemann, J., 47